Raymond Aron
Relations
With a new introduction by
Daniel J. Mahoney and Brian C. Anderson
PEACE
&WAR
Books by Raymond Aron Published by Transaction
• In Defense of Decadent Europe
• Main Currents in Sociological Thought
Volume 1: Montesquieu, Comte, Marx, Tocqueville,
and the Sociologists and the Revolution of 1848
. Main Currents in Sociological Thought
Volume 2: Durkheim, Pareto, Weber
« The Opium of the Intellectuals
• Peace & War: A Theory of International Relations
• Politics and History
. Thinking Politically: A Liberal in the Age of Ideology
PEACE
&WAR
A Theory of
International
Relations
Raymond Aron
With a new introduction by
Daniel J. Mahoney and Brian C. Anderson
Routledge
Taylor &. Francis Group
LONDON AND NEW YORK
Oiginallv published in 1966 by Doubleday & Company, Inc
Published 2003 by Transaction Publishers
Published 2017 by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park. Abingdon. Oxon 0X14 4RN
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017, USA
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an infonna business
New material this edition copyright © 2003 by Taylor & Francis.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or
utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now
known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in
any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing
from the publishers.
Notice:
Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks,
and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to
infringe.
Library of Congress Catalog Number: 2003048420
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Aron, Raymond. 1905-
[Paix et guerre entre les nations. English]
Peace and war: a theory of international relations / Raymond Aron; with
a new introduction by Daniel J. Mahoney & Brian C. Anderson,
p. cm.
Previously published as: Garden City, N.Y. : Doubleday, 1966. [1st ed.]
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-7658-0504-9 (pbk. : alk. paper)
1. International relations. I. Title.
JZ1305.A7613 2003
327’.1’01—dc21 2003048420
ISBN 13: 978-0-7658-0504-1 (pbk)
International law is based by nature upon this principle: that the various
nations ought to do, in peace, the most good to each other, and, in war, the
least harm possible, without detriment to their genuine interests.
—Montesquieu, L’Esprit des lots, I, 3
Taylor &. Francis
Taylor &. Francis Group
http://taylorandfrands.com
In 1954 , in a note on an article entitled “On the Analysis of Diplomatic
Constellations” published in the Revue frangaise da science -politique, I an¬
nounced a Sociology of International Relations. For several years I had been
contemplating the book that I now offer. During that time the theme broad¬
ened, and the distinctions of theory, sociology, and praxiology came to seem
to me fundamental in order to grasp, on the different levels of conceptual¬
ization, the intelligible texture of a social universe. Ultimately, although this
book deals chiefly with the world today, its deepest aim is not linked to the
present. My goal is to comprehend the implicit logic of relations among po¬
litically organized collectivities. This effort of comprehension culminates in
the question that will determine the future of the human race.
Will the nations henceforth capable of annihilating, without even disarm¬
ing, each other, discover the meaning of a truly peaceful coexistence? I do
not claim to give an answer which only history can afford. But perhaps this
hook will help readers to reflect on the problem in all its complexity . 1
Venanson, July 1959
Paris, October 1961
1 1 should like to take this occasion to thank those who have helped me to bring this
work to its conclusion; Harvard University, in appointing me Ford Research Professor
of Government for a semester of 1960-61, afforded me several months of the student’s
scholarly leisure; Suzanne Moussouris who indefatigably transcribed and retranscribed
manuscripts almost illegible to anyone but herself; Isabelle Nicol who edited the text;
Pierre Hassner who translated the English citations; and Stanley Hoffman and Pierre
Bourdieu who suggested important corrections.
Taylor &. Francis
Taylor &. Francis Group
http://taylorandfrands.com
CONTENTS
Introduction to the Transaction Edition
xi
Preface to the American Edition
xxi
Introduction The Conceptual Levels of Comprehension
i
PART ONE
THEORY
Concepts and Systems
Chapter 1
Strategy and Diplomacy, or On the Unity of Foreign
Policy
21
Chapter II
Power and Force, or On the Means of Foreign Policy
17
Chapter III
Power, Glory and Idea, or On the Goals of Foreign
^^o!ic^
7 1
Chapter IV
On International Systems
94
Chapter V
On Multipolar Systems and Bipolar Systems
125
Chapter VI
Dialectics of Peace and War
150
PART TWO
SOCIOLOGY
Determinants and Constants
Introduction
177
Chapter VII
On S£ac^
181
Chapter VIII
On Number
210
Chapter IX
On Resources
M3
Chapter X
Nations and Regimes
279
Chapter XI
In Search of a Pattern of Change
307
Chapter XII
The Roots of War as an Institution
339
PART THREE
HISTORY
The Global System in the Thermonuclear Age
Introduction
369
Chapter XIII
Le monde fini, or The Heterogeneity of the
Global System
373
Chapter XIV
On the Strategy of Deterrence
4°4
Chapter XV
Les grands Frires, or Diplomacy within the Blocs
44 1
Chapter XVI
Stalemate in Europe, or Diplomacy between the
Blocs
47 6
Chapter XVII
Persuasion and Subversion, or The Blocs and the
Non-Aligned Nations
506
Chapter XVIII
The Enemy Partners
536
PART FOUR
PRAXEOLOGY
The Antinomies of Diplomatic-Strategic Conduct
Introduction
575
Chapter XIX
In Search of a Morality:
I: Idealism and Realism
579
Chapter XX
In Search of a Morality:
II: Conviction and Responsibility
6u
Chapter XXI
In Search of a Strategy:
I: To Arm or Disarm?
6^6
Chapter XXII
In Search of a Strategy:
II: To Survive Is to Conquer^
665
Chapter XXIII
Beyond Power Politics:
I: Peace through Law
7°3
Chapter XXIV
Beyond Power Politics:
II: Peace through Empire
737
Final Note
Rational Strategy and Reasonable Policy
767
Index
789
INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSACTION EDITION
Not so long ago, liberal democracy and capitalism seemed on the ascen¬
dant. The Soviet Union and its satellite regimes in Eastern and Central
Europe had collapsed, the European Union was coming together, demo¬
cratic institutions were springing up across the globe, and the free market
was extending the circle of prosperity and growth ever wider. Political think¬
ers and pundits began to speak of an “end of history” in a triumphant
democratic capitalism, of the obsolescence of the nation-state, of a cosmo¬
politan “law of peoples.” At least for some, it was as if we were entering into
a new, post-political era, in which the traditional enmities, passions, and
conflicts of human history would give way to the management of success
and the stating off of boredomJD
The atrocities of September 11, the U.S. defeat of the Taliban in Af¬
ghanistan, imminent conflict in Iraq, internal national conflicts within
NATO, nuclear brinkmanship between India and Pakistan, the collapse of
the dot-com boom, and rising economic protectionism—how different the
world appears today. Politics has returned vengefully, making the liberal
optimism of the 1990s appear naively
The great French liberal Raymond Aron would not have been surprised
at the stubborn persistence of politics. In this impressive book, first pub¬
lished in French in 1962, Aron argues that international relations is, and
will likely always remain, the realm of independent sovereignties, jealous of
their interests and their prestige—their “Power, Glory, and Idea,” in Peace
and War’s formulation@These sovereignties refuse to surrender their right,
at least at the limit, to defend their interests and prestige through force of
arms. This partial state of nature between states (what Kant famously called
the “asocial sociality” of international life) is very different from the civil
relations within states. The possibility of war is thus always among the
statesman’s concerns and therefore should also be central to any attempt to
think about international relations.
The political thinker who ignores the problem of war fails two key inter¬
related duties of his calling: that of advising the statesman (and, in a demo¬
cratic context, educating the citizen); and that of mirroring as accurately, as
“scientifically,” as possible, the reality of the political world. Peace and War
is an ambitious attempt both to describe the permanent aspects of the life
of nations and to advise statesmen and democratic citizens. To guide the
reader in his reading of this big, complex book, we offer here a brief outline
of its principal themes.
Starting from the recognition of the partial state of nature among states,
Aron develops in Peace and War an array of analytical tools for thinking
Xll
INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSACTION EDITION
about international relations. These tools fall under four headings: theory,
sociology, history, and “praxeology” (that is, what is right and wrong among
states, as distinct from within them).
Under theory, Aron lays out a broad conceptual framework based on
power and system. Power concerns the means and ends of foreign policy. As
a means, power allows one political unit to impose its will on another, and in
Aron’s view it has three components—territory, resources, and the collec¬
tive capacity for action. To understand how territory influences power, sim¬
ply look at the United States, a vast country, bordered on its eastern and
western coasts by enormous oceans. These natural advantages have long
protected the United States from invasion, though the threats of intercon¬
tinental missiles and of terrorists wielding biological, chemical, and radio¬
logical weapons have of course diminished somewhat the importance of
territory as a means of power. As for resources, their contribution to a state’s
power is a function of economic development. America’s tremendous wealth,
generated from its vibrant open economy, has enabled it to exert its power
globally in ways no other nation can match.
It is at least possible to measure both territory and resources as means of
power. By contrast, Aron shows, the collective capacity for action of a state
depends on spiritual resources that resist all quantification. Who could
have anticipated England’s fierce resistance to National Socialist Germany
during the Second World War0A state can be far more powerful than its
territory or level of wealth would suggest.
And what do states use power for? Aron insists on the irreducible com¬
plexity of international relations —pace those like Kenneth Waltz, who boil
them down to the “structural” competition for power and influence, or to
neo-Marxists like Antonio Negri who see the machinations of capital be¬
hind every state actionH Nations pursue many ends, from the dream of
autarky to a sacred ideal to the quest for influence or even grandeur.
This irreducible complexity of ends means that we can at best discern
probabilities within international relations. No simply predictive theory of
state relations is possible. As Aron puts it at the end of Peace and War, it is
“incontestable” that “political science is not operational, in the sense in
which physics is, or even in the sense in which economics are.’0He shares
Aristotle’s belief that a discussion “will be adequate if its degree of clarity
fits the subject matter; for we should not seek the same degree of exactness
in all sorts of arguments alike, any more than in the products of different
crafts.’0 Conjecture is more art than science.
The notion of diplomatic system is the second part of Aron’s “theory”
framework. A diplomatic system consists of those political units that main¬
tain relations and that would find themselves inexorably drawn into a gen¬
eralized war. A system, Aron points out, can consist of “heterogeneous” or
INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSACTION EDITION
Xlll
“homogeneous” regimes—that is, regimes that pursue similar or dissimilar
goals or that have similar or dissimilar constituting principles; a mixed
system of heterogeneous and homogeneous regimes is also possible. To¬
day, the Western democracies and Iran or Iraq belong to a heterogeneous
system, the democracies themselves a homogenous one. During World War
II, the United States and the Soviet Union belonged to a mixed system,
dissimilar regimes fighting together against a common enemy. And so on.
Though Aron’s understanding of the political regime is narrower than
Aristotle’s, which encompassed an entire way of life, it shares with it a pow¬
erful sense of the importance of politics. Aron is a particularly incisive critic
of the “realist” delusion that great nations are guided by conceptions of
“the national interest” that are more or less immune to fundamental changes
of regime and ideology.
These kind of theoretical distinctions allow Aron to grasp international
relations from within, in accordance with their inner logic and historical
specificity, and the nature of the regimes involved. It is an approach that
avoids abstraction and conceptual hubris.
After laying out this broad theoretical framework, Aron next moves to
sociological analysis: the study of the myriad factors that influence foreign
policy. The sociologist must determine the degree to which such factors
influence the life of nations. The sociological causes, in Aron’s view, can
be material and physical on the one hand, and moral and social on the
other.
Physical causes fall under three headings in Peace and War. The first is
spatial. Like Montesquieu, Aron argues that environment may influence
international relations but not determine them. Spatial considerations are
also crucial in geopolitics—as the theater of battle and power. Space is also
a stake in international relations, though much less so than in the past,
given the general awareness that in the modern world wealth no longer
depends on land and natural resources but on intelligence and good eco¬
nomics, and that military technology has made distance a diminishing ob¬
stacle to lethal forceP^The second physical factor Aron considers is number.
In discerning how number influences peace and war, we can draw no solid
inferences, Aron believes. Economic ups and downs do not make war or
peace inevitable. As always with Aron, we are in the realm of better or worse
conjectures, not deterministic predictions.
Aron pays great attention to the moral and social causes of peace and war.
Knowing the nature of a particular political regime or political culture is
essential to making a good judgment about how it will act. The foreign
policy of the Soviet Union largely took its bearings from ideology, Aron
frequently argued. As long as the regime embraced Marxist-Leninist prin-
XIV
INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSACTION EDITION
ciples, it would seek only tactical peace with liberal democratic societies.
Post-communist Russia, for all its difficulties and seemingly endemic cor¬
ruption, has acted very differently on the world stage than would have a still-
communist state. Ignoring such regime differences obscured what political
judgment could achieve in international relations.
Nor was it the case that human nature required war. In a powerful pas¬
sage, Aron writes:
It is contrary to the nature of man that the danger of violence be definitively
dispelled: in every collectivity, misfits will violate the laws and attack persons. It
is contrary to the nature of individuals and groups that the conflicts between
individuals and groups disappear. But it is not proved that these conflicts must
be manifested in the phenomenon of war, as we have known it for thousands of
years, with organized combatants, utilizing increasingly destructive weapons!^
Different political regimes would allow different articulations of the hu¬
man propensity to violence, some much more sensible and less destructive
than others. Politics matters.
Aron devotes the third section of Peace and War to history—specifically,
the history of the twentieth century up until the early 1960s. Though its
examples might seem dated, in fact the argument is strikingly relevant. He
looks both at the technological revolution and the globalization of diplo¬
macy—phenomena Aron believed marked the beginning of “universal his-
tory.’^No one could deny that these two factors continue to play a prominent
role in international relations. But as important as technology and univer¬
sal diplomacy are, Aron rightly emphasized that they have not changed the
nature of man or his collective forms of organization. The dramatic features
of history—the conflict of men, nations, and regimes—was just as real in
1962—or 2002 for that matter—as it was when Thucydides wrote his great
historical narrative. Neither the nuclear bomb nor the global economy has
put an end to history. History may have slowed down, as Aron liked to put it,
but history would continue “to write its letters in blood’*-® as long as the
rivalry of men and regimes persisted.
Theory, sociology, history: a correct comprehension of these categories
will inform both a “science” of international relations and the decisions of
the prudent statesman. The fourth part of Peace and War —in many ways
the most profound of the book—concerns “praxeology,” Aron’s norma¬
tive theory of international relations. In it, Aron addresses two enduring
problems of statecraft.
The first Aron calls the “Machiavellian” problem. Is foreign policy essen¬
tially evil? What means may the statesman justifiably use? As the three ear-
INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSACTION EDITION
XV
lier sections of Peace and War have shown, the political leader confronts a
world of uncertainty; probabilities are the most he can rely on. He also
confronts a diplomatic universe in which states retain their sovereignty and
much of their freedom of action.
One possible practical option for the statesman is the idealist “morality
of law.” Idealist theories attempt to transcend international anarchy by pos¬
iting a categorical international morality. Aron rejects this approach as fool¬
hardy—and immoral. International “legality” and fairness often conflict.
“If, in 1933,” Aron writes, “France had heeded Marshal Pilsudski’s advice
and used force to overthrow Hitler, who had just come to power, she would
have violated the principle of non-interference in the internal affairs of
other states, she would have failed to recognize Germany’s right of free choice
with regard to regime and leader, she would have been denounced with indig¬
nation by American public opinion, by moralists and idealists hastening to
the rescue, not of National Socialism, but of the will of the people or the
rule of non-interference.’^But would France have been wrong?
This example, Aron maintains, illumines a fundamental truth of inter¬
national relations. Since states remain “sole judges of what their honor
requires,” the very existence of a political community can depend on the
statesman’s willingness to measure the relations of force and, if necessary, to
wield force in response to threats. To pretend that “international law” and
“collective security” will protect his community in the absence of military might
invites disaster. Indeed, such ingenuousness represents a moral failing. As
Aron avows, “it is the duty of statesmen to be concerned, first of all, with the
nation whose destiny is entrusted to them.The idealist promotes a vision
that reinforces injustice.
But if idealism fails as a morality of international relations, a “morality of
struggle’^ does no better. Its advocates argue that, given the existence of
independent sovereignties, the statesman may use all means at his dis¬
posal—from the simple ruse to assassination to lethal force—whenever he
deems it appropriate. Critics often describe Aron as a realist® But though
Aron, like the realists, appreciated the persistence of independent sover¬
eignties, he did not accept that state amorality was legitimate or even neces¬
sary. While the statesman owed his paramount moral duties to his own political
community, Aron argued, relations between communities were
“not...comparable to those of beasts in the jungle.”®
Aron held that certain soi-disant realists took the dark and violent side of
human nature—man as a beast of prey—as human nature tout court. This
was to encourage the very brutality the realist pretended only to explain.
“Even in relations between states, respect for ideas, aspirations to higher
values and concerns for obligations have been manifested,” Aron pointed
out. “Rarely have collectivities acted as if they would stop at nothing with
XVI
INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSACTION EDITION
regard to one another. ’^The realist might deny it, but morality remained
an integral feature of political history.
The realist would even place democratic regimes and totalitarian re¬
gimes on the same level—all states indistinguishably pursuing their na¬
tional interest. But for Aron this was a kind of historical nihilism, treating
“Christians” and “barbarians” as if there was no moral difference between
them. This was immoral—and unwise even from the standpoint of national
interest. For a democracy had more to fear from political marauders than
from other democracies, as the twentieth century has proved.
Superior to both the “morality of law” and the “morality of struggle,” in
Aron’s view, was what Aron called the “morality of prudence.” Attuned to
the rivalrous nature of international relations, yet aware also of a shared
human nature and certain moral universals, prudence offered a better sense
of reality and morality than its rival approaches. The prudent statesman
preferred “the limitation of violence...to so-called absolute justice,” and
strove to attain “concrete accessible objectives conforming to the secular
law of international relations and not to limitless and perhaps meaningless
objectives, such as ‘a world safe for democracy’ or ‘a world from which power
politics has disappeared.”^ It captured what was true in both idealist and
realist approaches while correcting their excesses.
The morality of prudence represented political wisdom in the partially
Hobbesian world of international relations, where states retained sover¬
eignty but still acknowledged some measure of human universality. Was a
different world possible if states surrendered their sovereignty? This, Aron
suggested, was the “Kantian” problem of universal peace, Peace and War s
second “praxeological” exploration.
There were signs of a world community, but they were for the most part
relatively superficial. A transnational society, for example, had emerged
from the technological marvels of the twentieth century. Planes and televi¬
sions (and today the Internet) brought far-flung corners of the world into
regular contact. Yet for every indication of a transnational society, Aron
suggested, one could come up with a counter-indication, showing growing
conflict between societies and cultures. There might be more talk of hu¬
man rights in our time, he added, but how could any observer of the age of
extremes—an age of mass atrocity and obliterating wars—say that a greater
awareness of the human community as a whole had gained much ground?
In many ways, humankind remained as divided as ever.
As Aron explained, only law or empire could overcome the “immemo¬
rial” order of collectivities. And neither approach was likely to succeed.
Even if some super-tribunal or compelling political will came into being,
would it not simply amplify the causes of conflict, Aron asked? The in-
INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSACTION EDITION
XVII
equalities and resentments that cause tension within political commu¬
nities—and that can even lead to revolution—would now be the respon¬
sibility of one universal sovereign. Why would such resentments
disappear within a universal state or world federation? This would mean
that man had solved the problem of politics itself.
And would a post-political world be desirable? It would mean the end of
a strong sense of nationhood. Aron saw a sense of political particularity as
something rooted in human nature—and therefore something to treasure.
“The diversity of cultures,” he wrote, “is not a curse to be exorcized but a
heritage to be safe guarded. ”0 To regret this, the way, say, John Rawls and
other cosmopolitan liberals have done, is to deny that which is common in
the quixotic quest for what is individual and absolutely universal. It would
represent an impoverishment of human existence.
One way to address both the need for a community of culture and to
move toward universal peace would be to pursue federation. But could the
world become a giant Switzerland? Turning to the German theorist Carl
Schmitt, Aron said such an outcome was utopian 10 In Schmitt’s view—and
Aron had some sympathy for it—the distinction between friend and enemy
is central to politics. The force that binds a community results in part from
opposition to the other. While Aron did not deduce the impossibility of
world federation from Schmitt’s friend-enemy distinction, he did believe
that hostility was natural to man and could only be moderated, not elimi¬
nated. And that moderation required a binding of community that in turn
required an outside—if not an enemy, then at least an other. There was a
big difference, Aron felt, between the feasible broadening of world commu¬
nity and the unification of the world, which was a dream at the limits of the
historically possible. At best, the notion of a unified humanity might func¬
tion as an “idea of reason” that could serve to moderate the bellicose pro¬
clivities of human beings and political communities. Here, too, sobriety
and a sense of historical realism are necessary to avoid the twin extremes of
false realism and false idealism.
Peace and War was perhaps Aron’s most ambitious book. Aron was justly
proud of this book but was never wholly satisfied with it. He had consider¬
able doubts about whether he had finally succeeded in integrating its theo¬
retical and historical dimensions and he feared that his work contained too
much analysis of the passing events of his day. In any case, Peace and War is
by no means Aron’s final word on the nature of international relations or
the politics of the twentieth century. It needs to be read in conjunction with
his magisterial book on Clausewitzp^the work that Aron considered to be
his great masterpiece, as well as with his writings on the history of the twen¬
tieth century, now collected in English as The Dawn of Universal History:
XV111
INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSACTION EDITION
Selected Essays from a Witness to the Twentieth Century (Basic Books, 2002).
Together, these writings convey the magnitude of Aron’s achievement as an
authoritative, humane, and trustworthy guide to politics and history in an
age unhinged by the ideological temptation. Despite Aron’s own lingering
doubts. Peace and War remains an indispensable book for those who wish to
comprehend the place of peace and war in the human order of things.
Written with the clear, classically restrained language Aron was noted for,
the book stands out as one of the twentieth century’s great works of political
thought. At a time when history is once again on the move, and the liberal
utopianism of recent years appears increasingly shallow. Peace and War
reminds us of the fallibility of human knowledge, and the limits, but also
the grandeur, of human morality in a dangerous and imperfect world.
Daniel J. Mahoney
Brian C. Anderson
Notes
E-kee Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press,
1993); Kenichi Ohmae, The Borderless World: Power and Strategy in the Interlinked Economy
(New York: HarperCollins, 1991) ; and John Rawls, “The Law of Peoples,” in Stephen
Shute and Susan Hurley, eds., On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures, 1993 (New
York: Basic Books, 1993), pp. 41-82.
0For Fukuyama’s updated, post-September 11 view on whether history has ended or not,
see “Has History Started Again?” Policy, Winter 2002, pp. 3-7. Flis answer: no.
0This introduction adapts and draws on longer treatments of Peace and War published
earlier in Brian C. Anderson, Raymond Aron: The Recovery of the Political (Lanham, MD:
Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 1997), pp. 121-165 and Daniel J. Mahoney, The Liberal
Political Science of Raymond Aron (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 1992),
pp. 91-110. See also Bryan-Paul Frost, “Raymond Aron’s Peace and War, Thirty Years
Later," InternationalJournal, Vol. 51, Spring 1996, pp. 339-361.
I^This collective capacity for action can increase or diminish as a consequence of politi¬
cal leadership—another variable of international relations that escapes measurement.
Aron underscored this point elsewhere: “Without Churchill, would England have stood
firm all alone against the Third Reich?... Traditional history is action, that is to say it is
made of decisions taken by men in a precise place and time. These decisions could have
been different with another man in the same situation, or with the same man with
another disposition. No one can fix, either beforehand or retrospectively, the limits of
the consequences that some of these localized and dated decisions generate.” Raymond
Aron, In Defense of Political Reason, edited by Daniel J. Mahoney (Lanham, MD: Rowman
& Littlefield Publishers, 1994), p. 138.
ElSee Kenneth Waltz, Theory of International Politics (Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley,
1979). For a neo-Marxist vision of the life of nations, see Michael Hardt and Antonio
Negri ,Empire (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001).
OOSee below, p. 768.
^Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics, trans. By T. Irwin (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishers,
1995), Bk. I, 1094b.
0On military technology, see Raymond Aron, The Century of Total War (Lanham, MD:
University Press of America, 1985). On knowledge as a source of wealth, see Michael
INTRODUCTION TO THE TRANSACTION EDITION
XIX
Novak, The Catholic Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (New York: Free Press, 1993), pp.
114-43.
0See below, p. 366.
®See Raymond Aron, Progress and Disillusion: The Dialectics of Modern Society (New York:
Praeger, 1968).
0See Raymond Aron, Clausewitz: Philosopher of War (Englewood Cliffs, N.T.: Prentice-
Hall, 1985), p. 412.
li^See below, p. 580.
EUlbid.
EUlbid., p. 608.
^See, for example, Charles R. Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), pp. 27-28.
E^See below, p. 581.
□ ibid., p. 609.
QUlbid., p. 585.
G3lbid„ p. 750.
EDSchmitt, writing during the collapse of Weimer Germany, believed liberalism irrepara¬
bly doomed by its refusal to recognize the violent core of politics—that politics invari¬
ably opposed friend and enemy. See The Concept of the Political , trans. By G. Schwab, with
comments by Leo Strauss (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996). Schmitt’s subse¬
quent involvement with the Nazis has rightly tarnished his reputation, but his work
raises pressing questions for liberal democracies, as Aron acknowledged. Philippe Raynaud
has sketched out what one could call the “hidden dialogue” between Aron and Schmitt.
See “Raymond Aron et le droit international,” Cahiers de philosophic etjuridique. No. 15,
1989, pp. 115-28.
[^Raymond Aron, Clausewitz: Philosopher of War (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall,
1985).
Taylor &. Francis
Taylor &. Francis Group
http://taylorandfrands.com
PREFACE TO THE AMERICAN EDITION
This book, begun several years ago, was completed during the 1960-61 aca¬
demic year, first at Cambridge, where the author was a Research Professor at
Harvard University, then in France during the following spring and summer.
It was published in 1962 in Paris, and therefore appears in the United States
almost five years after it was written, four years after its first French edition.
If the text, aside from several minor corrections already introduced, for
the most part, into the second French edition, has not been modified, the
chief reason for this is pre-eminently the character of the book, which is not,
in its author’s mind, concerned with the present in the sense in which this
term is utilized by the press. Of course Part III, entitled "History,” offers an
analysis of the diplomatic universe in which we live: coextensive with the
limits of the planet, dominated by thermonuclear weapons, mainly possessed
by two giant states. In a certain sense the first two parts, “Theory” and “Soci¬
ology,” are also oriented toward the present. But the effort of comprehension,
both theoretical and sociological, emphasizes primarily a conceptual apparatus,
indispensable to a grasp of relations between states, then the scope of the
determinants which affect these relations, and finally the possible constants
revealed by the study of the past. Even historical comprehension, beyond the
unforeseeable vicissitudes of the cold war or of peaceful coexistence, has for
its object the lasting and, so to speak, structural characteristics of the post-
1945 world.
Writing at the end of 1965 , I should probably be led to formulate or to
orient my views differently on one point or another, but the essential thing is
that the instruments of analysis remain effective and that the changes that
have occurred during these last four years have taken place within an es¬
tablished context. Now, without claiming to summarize the events of the
1961-65 period, I should like to indicate, in a few pages, why the more or
less spectacular transformations of the diplomatic scene proceed from ten¬
dencies long since visible, and in what direction they tend.
The governing idea by which I interpreted the diplomatic situation was
that of the solidarity of the two great powers—the warring brothers—against
a total war of which they would be the first victims. Inevitably enemies by
position and by the incompatibility of their ideologies, the United States and
the Soviet Union have a common interest not in ruling together over the
world (of which they would be quite incapable), but in not destroying each
other. This politico-strategic doctrine was openly professed in the universities
and institutes of the United States; it very nearly became the official doctrine
of the Kennedy administration. And the Soviet leaders acted as if they in
effect acknowledged this same doctrine. But they often spoke as if they were
ignorant of it or rejected it. That is why I wondered, before the autumn of
1962 , if the asymmetry of strategic conceptions (flexible response on the
American side, inevitable escalation on the Russian side), the rejection of
XXII
PREFACE TO THE AMERICAN EDITION
even limited agreements (such as relative agreement on the suspension of
nuclear tests), was not due to Mr. Khrushchev’s conviction or illusion that
he was gaining an advantage from the fear such a war inspired—a fear that
he felt quite as much as did his rival, but that he affected to ignore.
The Cuban crisis of October-November 1962 seems to have shaken this
conviction or dissipated this illusion. Mr. Khrushchev had several times,
though in a vague and reticent manner, threatened to utilize thermonuclear
rockets to protect Cuba. When he committed the imprudence of constructing
a Cuban base for medium-range missiles, an American quasi-ultimatum
forced him to choose between a reply in another zone of the planet—where
he could benefit from a superiority in conventional weapons comparable to
that of the United States off the coast of Florida—a recourse to the apocalyptic
weapons, or retreat. It appears that Mr. Khrushchev did not hesitate long:
he preferred retreat, at the risk of being accused of “capitulationism” by his
Chinese friends.
No shot had been fired, except by the Cubans who had downed an Ameri¬
can plane, and yet the American notes, supported by military preparations,
had transmitted to Moscow a message whose meaning was clear. For the first
time, two states equipped with thermonuclear weapons faced each other in a
direct confrontation. Deterrence ceased to be an abstract notion. Discovering,
perhaps with surprise, that the American weapons were at the disposal of a
man determined, in certain circumstances, to assume all risks, Mr. Khru¬
shchev provisionally drew a lesson from the crisis and from his defeat: hence¬
forth, on the subject of thermonuclear war, he was to use the same language
as the American President. Further, insofar as the Soviet leaders continue to
affect a certain skepticism toward the subtleties in which American analysts
indulge, asserting that local wars, when the nuclear powers are involved in
them, will escalate to a general and total war, they must adopt a still more
prudent attitude than their enemy. For this reason, the Soviet leaders have
officially accepted the American doctrine; they proclaim it on all occasions,
and have given two proofs of their adherence in actions: the signing of the
Moscow Treaty on the partial suspension of nuclear tests, and the establish¬
ment of a direct line between the Kremlin and the White House, a symbol
of the enemies’ alliance against war.
However incontestable it may be, this change chiefly affects climate and
language. The Moscow Treaty allows of no supervision and does not forbid
underground tests, lacking as it does an agreement concerning the number of
on-site inspections necessary to guarantee respect for the treaty. But it is true
that the acceleration phase of the 1961-62 arms race, which I noted at the
completion of this book, has been succeeded by a slowdown; both phases are
in accord with the logic of that singular hostility that limits the common de¬
sire not to perish together for the sole advantage of today’s or tomorrow’s
rivals.
The Russo-American raffrochement, though its essential cause and objec-
PREFACE TO THE AMERICAN EDITION
XX111
tive was to reduce the danger of nuclear war, is situated in a political context
which has, to a degree, provoked it, and which it influences in return. We
know better, in 1965 , the various episodes of the Sino-Soviet conflict than we
knew four years ago. The Chinese have taught us that in 1957 an agreement
had been concluded between the two great Communist powers providing for
Soviet aid to the Chinese atomic program, and that two years later, after the
military operations in the Strait of Formosa in 1958 , this agreement had been
denounced by Moscow. The desire of the Soviet Union to retain a monopoly
of nuclear weapons in the socialist camp has thus been one of the causes of
the—subsequently public—break between the Russians and the Chinese. The
Russian desire, like the Chinese refusal, was the expression of the normal
conflict between two sovereign states, one of which claims to retain the lead¬
ership of a common strategy, while the other aspires to independence on the
day it can make its own vital decisions.
Perhaps Mr. Khrushchev decided to sign the Moscow agreement, in 1963 ,
only after he had lost all hope of re-establishing the unity of the socialist
camp. For in signing with his enemy a treaty whose evident objective was to
make the acquisition of nuclear weapons more difficult for his ally, he was
consecrating in the eyes of the world a divorce that the publicity of interna¬
tional polemics no longer permitted him to conceal. Of course, the treaty seen
from Paris had the same meaning it had for Peking. The three members of
the atomic club were trying to keep the other states from doing what they
themselves had done, were condemning them in advance to the moral repro¬
bation of the world. Relations between Paris and Washington, as was fore¬
seeable, suffered from a treaty that the American leaders regarded as useful to
peace, hence to the protection of humanity, and that General de Gaulle re¬
garded as a manifestation of the age-old egoism, indeed cynicism of national
states, “those cold monsters.”
However bad relations between Washington and Paris today, however com¬
parable the French or Chinese refusals to subscribe to the Moscow Treaty or
to submit to the authority of the leader of their respective camps, the differ¬
ences are still more marked than the similarities, because the diplomacy of
the democratic states obeys different rules from that of the totalitarian states.
The split between Moscow and Peking reminds us that a common ideology
does not suffice to cement an alliance, but, assuming that conflicting national
interests of the Soviet Union and the People’s Republic of China were a
major cause of the split, the latter would not have had the same character if
each of the two rivals had not immediately translated into ideological terms its
conception of its own interests or of the opportune strategy, and had not at¬
tempted to win over to its cause the other socialist parties throughout the
world. In their alliances as in their disputes, the Communist states are neither
exclusively governed by their ideologies nor indifferent to the historical philos¬
ophy from which they derive. States of the liberal type, such as the United
States or France, remain more easily allied, even when they do not manage
XXIV
PREFACE TO THE AMERICAN EDITION
to agree, because divergence of opinions is a part of the natural process of
democracy, and because none of them claims to possess a final truth (nor
even imagines that in such matters there is a final truth).
The rapprochement of the United States and the Soviet Union in order to
prevent war, the Sino-Soviet conflict, the effort of Gaullist France to acquire
a purely national nuclear strategic force and even an independent diplomacy
—does all this mark the end of the bipolar system and the beginning of a new
phase of international relations? Let us remember first of all that bipolarity
has never been effective except in the military sphere, and in a limited region
of the world. Now, in military terms, bipolarity subsists in the sense that
weapons or means of destruction possessed by the Soviet Union and the
United States remain overwhelmingly superior to those of all other states,
even of Great Britain, which possesses a nuclear force, and of France and
China, which are on the way to acquiring one.
But the destructive capacity the giants possess does not correspond to a
proportional capacity to impose their wills upon the other states. Never have
weapons been so terrifying, never have they inspired so little terror in those
who are not equipped with them. Albania defies the Soviet Union, and Cuba
the United States. It is as if military strength can be translated into diplo¬
matic power only with great difficulty when the so-called supreme weapons
are so monstrously inhuman. Or again, to use another formula, it is as if the
Russian and American thermonuclear forces paralyzed each other, preventing
the amplification of local conflicts and functioning only in a subsidiary way
in relations between great and small powers, particularly in the Southern
Hemisphere. At most, the thermonuclear weapons impose on those who do
not possess them some moderation in the conduct of their undertakings. In
the Siberian north as in southeast Asia, China harasses the “revisionist” ally
or the “imperialist enemy.” She cannot, without incurring an extreme danger,
launch an open aggression.
Outside the two European blocs the so-called non-aligned states, with their
many and varying versions of neutrality and neutralism, become more numer¬
ous year by year. But in this regard, nothing has changed except at most an
accentuation of the tendency to form diplomatic sub-systems, each involving
a local balance of forces, national or traditional rivalries between non-aligned
states, sub-systems linked to the global system but not merely reflecting it.
Within the two European blocs the symptoms of dissolution have multi¬
plied in the course of recent years. As a result of the Sino-Soviet conflict
the states of Eastern Europe have asserted their national interests, some, like
Rumania, by opposing the COMECON plans, others, like Hungary or even
Czechoslovakia, by internal liberalization, and all, finally, by rejecting the
exclusive influence of Russian culture and by re-establishing links with the
West. Merchandise, men, and ideas cross what was once the Iron Curtain.
Bilateral agreements between the countries of Eastern and Western Europe
are increasing. Since the Cuban crisis, Soviet rulers have accommodated them-
PREFACE TO THE AMERICAN EDITION
XXV
selves to the existing status of Berlin and no longer brandish their weapons
to obtain, its modification. In this pacified atmosphere, in the absence of a
real fear of war, the members of the Atlantic Alliance feel less bound by
solidarity. France’s veto of Great Britain’s membership in the Common Mar¬
ket, Gaullist diplomacy’s effort to assure France the greatest possible auton¬
omy in relation to the United States, Bonn’s hesitation between the treaty
with France and the Atlantic Alliance—all these recent vicissitudes afford an
image of the Continent quite different from that available to the observer five
years ago. In the light of present events it is not impossible to imagine, on the
horizon of history, the reunification of Europe “from the Atlantic to the
Urals.”
But for the moment these are only eventualities possible at an indeter¬
minate date. In military terms the division of Europe exists, as does that of
Germany and of Berlin. So long as Germany remains divided, the funda¬
mental stake of the cold war in Europe will remain the same. Only the Soviet
Union’s abandonment of the so-called German Democratic Republic and her
consent to a united Germany would mark the liquidation of the consequences
of the Second World War. Now it is on the territory of the German Demo¬
cratic Republic that the twenty Soviet divisions are stationed threatening
Western Europe and effectively guaranteeing a minimum of discipline among
the satellite states. The day these divisions withdraw inside the boundaries of
the U.S.S.R., what will remain of the Soviet bloc? What will limit the re¬
visionism and nationalism of peoples who have been subjected against their
will to a Communist regime but who, after twenty years, have not been con¬
verted to the new faith? Communism’s historical failure in Eastern Europe
is a promise for the future, but at the same time it forbids the Kremlin leaders
to make concessions that might involve the complete dissolution of their bloc.
The easing of the political situation in Europe is accompanied by mount¬
ing tensions in the third world. Asia in particular is becoming the center of
the crisis. But this situation is no longer one of direct confrontation of the
two blocs, or the two super powers. The Soviet Union and the People’s Re¬
public of China are being drawn into a sort of cold war, the prize of which is
leadership in the international communist movement. At the same time, the
United States, directly engaged in Vietnam, is endeavoring, by the limited
use of military weapons, to contain China and to convert Mao Tse-tung and
his men to a policy of peaceful coexistence.
The interrelationship between these two conflicts on occasion results in the
convergence of the respective interests of the Soviet Union and of the United
States. For example, in September 1965, the two super powers both desired
the rapid halting of the Kashmir dispute between India and Pakistan. It is
possible that the Soviet Union would look favorably upon a solution reached
by negotiation, but she has lost the capability to impose her will upon the
Asian communist countries. She is avoiding open intervention, this being sus¬
ceptible to provoking the emergence of an American republic. Despite every-
XXVI
PREFACE TO THE AMERICAN EDITION
thing, she sent a few arms to North Vietnam (ground-to-air missiles) in order
not to appear indifferent to the lot of a socialist state; in order not to lose, in
the eyes of the third world, the prestige of the revolutionary idea. The Soviet
Union cannot ostensibly collaborate with the United States without furnish¬
ing some form of argument for her ideological rival.
More than ever before, the distinction between appearances and diplomatic
realities is becoming apparent. In the past, the Soviet Union has often con¬
cealed the action she has taken with regard to Western Europe. Today, we
have reached the stage where she conceals, under veil of invective, an im¬
plicit accord with the United States.
Whatever judgment we formulate on the present phase, whatever the
optimism with which we envisage the immediate prospects, the fundamental
problems of international relations in the thermonuclear age remain today
what they were four years ago. Perhaps a change of leaders in Moscow or in
Washington would revive the recently allayed anxieties. Certainly, if China
became the national enemy of the Soviet Union and no longer merely a rival
within the same camp, if the Soviet Union consented to a European settle¬
ment acceptable to the West, the situation would become essentially different.
Even in this hypothesis, the main uncertainty of our age would still remain.
China has already exploded a first atomic bomb. Like the Soviet Union, like
the United States, she must seek an answer to the question that dominates
the diplomacy of our epoch: how to use the thermonuclear weapons diplo¬
matically so that they will never have to be used militarily?
But how long can a threat be brandished without having to be carried
out? Can strategic interaction be indefinitely prolonged in the shadow of the
apocalypse? And if the answer is negative, how escape from that interaction?
It is reasonable for the great powers not to wage a war to the death, but if the
philosophers have often defined man as a reasonable being, they have rarely
asserted with the same assurance that human history deserved the same
epithet.
INTRODUCTION
The Conceptual Levels of Comprehension
Troubled times encourage meditation. The crisis of the Greek city-state has
bequeathed us Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Politics. The religious conflicts
that lacerated Europe in the seventeenth century produced, with Leviathan
and the Tractatus, the theory of the neutral state, necessarily absolute accord¬
ing to Hobbes, broadly interpreted, at least philosophically, according to
Spinoza. In the century of the English Revolution, Locke defended and
elucidated civil liberties. In the period when the French were unconsciously
generating their Revolution, Montesquieu and Rousseau defined the essence
of the two regimes that were to emerge from the sudden or gradual decom¬
position of the traditional monarchies: representative governments restrained
by the balance of power, and so-called democratic governments invoking the
will of the people but rejecting all limits to their authority.
After this century’s Second World War, the United States, which through¬
out its history had dreamed of standing aloof from the affairs of the Old
World, found itself responsible for the peace, the prosperity, and the very
existence of half the planet. GIs were garrisoned in Tokyo and Seoul in the
Orient, in Berlin in Europe. The West had known nothing like it since the
Roman Empire. The United States was the first truly world power, since
there was no precedent for the global unification of the diplomatic scene.
In relation to the Eurasian land mass, the American continent occupied a
position comparable to that of the British Isles in relation to Europe: the
United States was continuing the tradition of the insular state by attempting
to bar the dominant continental state’s expansion in central Germany and in
Korea.
No great work comparable to those we have mentioned has emerged from
the circumstance created by the joint victory of the United States and the
Soviet Union. International relations have become the object of an academic
discipline. Professorships, whose incumbents are dedicating themselves to the
new discipline, have multiplied. The number of books and manuals has
swollen proportionately. Have so many efforts come to anything? Before an-
2
INTRODUCTION
swering, we must specify what the American professors, following statesmen
and public opinion itself, propose to discover or elaborate.
Historians did not wait for the accession of the United States to world
primacy to study “international relations,” but they described or related more
than they analyzed or explained. No science, however, limits itself to describ¬
ing or relating. Further, what profit can statesmen or diplomats derive from
the historical knowledge of past centuries? The weapons of mass destruction,
the techniques of subversion, the ubiquity of military force because of avia¬
tion and electronics, introduce new human and material factors which render
the lessons of the past equivocal at best. Or, at least, such lessons cannot be
used unless they are assimilated into a theory that includes the like and the
unlike, and separates constants in order to elaborate, and not to eliminate, the
part played by the unknown.
This was the decisive question. Specialists in international relations were
unwilling merely to follow the historians; like all scholars, they wanted to
establish axioms, create a body of doctrine. Only geopolitics was concerned
with abstraction and explanation in international relations. But German geo¬
politics had left bad memories, apart from which the spatial framework was
insufficient for a theory whose function was to grasp the multiplicity of causes
affecting the course of relations among states.
It was easy to characterize the theory of international relations in general
terms. “First of all, it makes possible the ordering of data. It is a useful in¬
strument for understanding.’!!] Next, “the theory requires that the criteria for
selection of problems for intensive analysis be made explicit. It is not always
recognized that whenever a particular problem is selected for study and anal¬
ysis in some context or other, there is practically always a theory underlying
the choice.” Lastly, “Theory can be an instrument for the comprehension not
only of uniformities and regularities, but contingencies and irrationalities as
well.” Who could object to such formulations? Ordering of data, selection of
problems, determination of constants and variables— every theory, in the social
sciences, must in any case fulfill these three requirements. The problems arise
beyond these incontestable propositions.
The theoretician often tends to simplify reality, to interpret behavior by
uncovering the implicit logic of the actors. Hans J. Morgenthau writes: “A
theory of international relations is a rationally ordered summary of all the
rational elements which the observer has found in the subject matter. Such a
theory is a kind of rational outline of international relations, a map of the
international scene,® The difference between an empirical and a theoretical
0 Kcnneth W. Thompson, "Toward a Theory of International Politics,” American
Political Science Review, XLIX, 3, September 1955, pp. 735-36.
Ld These remarks are quoted from a report by Mr. Morgenthau entitled “The Theoretical
and Practical Importance of a Theory of International Relations” (p. ;) cited in
Thompson, p. 737.
INTRODUCTION
3
interpretation of international relations is comparable to the difference be¬
tween a photograph and a painted portrait. “The photograph shows every¬
thing that can be seen by the naked eye. The painted portrait does not show
everything that can be seen by the naked eye, but it shows something the
naked eye cannot see: the human essence of the person who is portrayed.”
To which another specialist replies by asking: what are the “rational ele¬
ments” of international politics? Is it enough to consider merely the rational
elements in order to produce a sketch or paint a portrait in accord with the
model’s essence? If the theoretician replies negatively to these two questions,
he must take another path, that of sociology. Granted the goal—to sketch the
map of the international scene—the theoretician will attempt to retain all the
elements instead of fixing his attention on the rational ones alone.
To this dialogue between the advocate of “rational schematics” and the
champion of "sociological analysis”—a dialogue whose nature and implications
the interlocutors have not always grasped—a traditionally American contro¬
versy is often added: the dialogue between idealism and realism. The realism,
today baptized Machiavellianism, of European diplomats seemed, from across
the Atlantic, typical of the Old World, the symptom of a corruption that men
had sought to escape by emigrating to the New World, the land of infinite
possibility. But having become the dominant power by the collapse of the
European order and the victory of its own weapons, the United States gradu¬
ally discovered, not without upheavals of conscience, that its diplomacy re¬
sembled less and less the old ideal and more and more the practice, once so
harshly judged, of its enemies and its allies. Was it moral to buy Soviet
intervention in the war against Japan with concessions at China’s expense?
It was revealed, after the fact, that the venture was not a profitable one; that
in rational terms Roosevelt should, in fact, have bought Soviet non-interven¬
tion. But would the calculation have been more moral if it had been rational?
Was it right or wrong of Roosevelt to abandon Eastern Europe to Soviet
domination? To plead the constraint of facts was to return to the argument
that Europeans had used and that Americans, mighty in their virtue and their
geographical situation, had long dismissed with scorn or indignation. The
military leader is accountable to his nation for his actions, his successes or his
defeats. What do good intentions and respect for private virtues matter? The
law of diplomacy or strategy is a different thing. But under these conditions,
what becomes of the dichotomy between realism and idealism, Machiavelli
and Kant, corrupt Europe and virtuous America?
This work seeks first to clarify, and subsequently to transcend, these de¬
bates. The two concepts of the theory are not contradictory, but comple¬
mentary: rational schematics and sociological propositions constitute succes¬
sive moments in the conceptual elaboration of a social universe.
Understanding a realm of action does not permit us to settle the antinomies
of action. Only history will perhaps some day curtail the eternal debate be¬
tween Machiavellianism and moralism. But by proceeding from formal theory
INTRODUCTION
4
to the determination of causes, and then to the analysis of a specific circum¬
stance, I hope to illustrate a method, applicable to other subjects, which
shows both the limits of our knowledge and the conditions of historical
choices.
In order to explain the structure of the book in this introduction, I must
first define international relations, then specify the characteristics of the four
levels of conceptualization which we call theory, sociology, history, praxiology.
[i]
Recently a Dutch historian® appointed to the first chair of international
relations created in his country, at Leyden, attempted in his inaugural lecture
to locate the discipline that it was his task to teach. He concluded with an
admission of failure: he had sought but not found the limits of the field he
proposed to explore.
His failure is instructive because it is definitive and, so to speak, obvious.
“International relations” have no frontiers traced out in reality, they are not
and cannot be materially separable from other social phenomena. But the
same proposition would be valid apropos of economics, or politics. If it is true
that “the proposal for developing the study of international relations as a
self-contained system has failed,” the real question lies beyond its failure and
concerns the meaning itself. After all, the attempt to make the study of eco¬
nomics a closed system has also failed; there nevertheless exists, and with
reason, a science of economics, whose own reality and the possibility of
whose isolation are not doubted by anyone. Does the study of international
relations involve a proper focus of interest? Does it aim at collective
phenomena, human behavior whose specificity is recognizable? And does this
specific meaning of international relations lend itself to a theoretical elabora¬
tion?
International relations are, by definition it would seem, relations among
nations. But in that case, the term nation is not to be taken in the historical
sense it has assumed since the French Revolution; it does not designate a par¬
ticular kind of political community, one in which large numbers of individ¬
uals have a consciousness of citizenship and in which the state seems to be
the expression of a pre-existent nationality. In the expression “international
relations,” the nation equals any political collectivity that is territorially or¬
ganized. Let us say, provisionally, that international relations are relations
among political units, the latter concept covering the Greek city-states, and
the Roman or Egyptian empires as well as the European monarchies, the
bourgeois republics or the people’s democracies. This definition involves a
double difficulty. Are we to include in the relations among political units the
i~3>j.
H. N. Vlekke, On the Study of International Political Science, the David Davies
Memorial Institute of International Studies, London (undated).
INTRODUCTION
5
relations among individuals belonging to those units? Where do political
units, that is, territorially organized political collectivities, begin or end?
When young Europeans want to spend their vacations beyond the borders
of their respective countries, is this a phenomenon that should interest the
specialist in international relations? When I buy German merchandise in a
French store, when a French importer deals with a manufacturer across the
Rhine, do these economic exchanges fall within the realm of “international
relations?”
It seems almost as difficult to answer affirmatively as negatively. Relations
among states, i.e., strictly inter-state relations, constitute international relations
par excellence: treaties are an indisputable example of such relations. Let us
suppose that the economic exchanges between one nation and another are
entirely regulated by an agreement between the two states: in this hypothesis,
such exchanges pertain without reservation to the study of international rela¬
tions. Let us suppose, on the other hand, that the economic exchanges are
withdrawn from strict regulation and that free exchange is the order of the
day: in consequence the purchase of German merchandise in France, the sale
of French merchandise in Germany will be individual acts not presenting the
characteristics of inter-state relations.
This difficulty is a real one, but it would be a mistake, it seems to me, to
exaggerate its importance. No scientific discipline possesses distinct bound¬
aries. It is of little importance, in the first instance, to know where interna¬
tional relations end, to specify at what moment inter-individual relations cease
to be international relations. We must determine the focus of interest, the
proper significance of the phenomenon or of the action that constitutes the
nucleus of this specific domain. Now the focus of international relations is on
the relations which we have called inter-state, those which bring these en¬
tities to grips with one another.
Inter-state relations are expressed in and by specific actions, those of indi¬
viduals whom I shall call symbolic, the diplomat and the soldier. Two men,
and only two, no longer function as individual members but as representatives
of the collectivities to which they belong: the ambassador, in the exercise of
his duties, is the political unit in whose name he speaks; the soldier on the
battlefield is the political unit in whose name he kills his opposite number.
It is because he struck an ambassador that the blow of the Dey of Algiers’ fan
assumed the status of a historical event. It is because he wears a uniform and
acts out of duty that in war the citizen of a civilized state kills with a clear
conscience. The ambassadoEland the soldier live and symbolize international
relations which, insofar as they are inter-state relations, concern diplomacy
and war. Inter-state relations present one original feature which distinguishes
Eht follows that, in this abstract sense, the statesmen, Ministers of Foreign Affairs,
Prime Ministers and heads of state are also, in certain of their actions, ambassadors.
They represent the political unit as such.
6
INTRODUCTION
them from all other social relations: they take place within the shadow of
war, or, to use a more rigorous expression, relations among states involve, in
essence, the alternatives of war and peace. Whereas each state tends to re¬
serve a monopoly on violence for itself, states throughout history, by recogniz¬
ing each other, have thereby recognized the legitimacy of the wars they
waged. In certain circumstances the reciprocal recognition of enemy states
has proceeded to its logical conclusion: each state used only its regular army
and refused to provoke, within the state it opposed, a rebellion which would
have weakened its enemy but would also have shaken the monopoly of
legitimate violence which it intended to preserve.
As a science of peace and war, the science of international relations can
serve as a basis for the arts of diplomacy and strategy, the complementary and
opposed methods by which dealings among states are conducted. “War be¬
longs not to the province of Arts and Sciences, but to the province of social
life. It is a conflict of great interests which is settled by bloodshed, and only
in that is it different from others. It would be better, instead of comparing it
with any Art, to liken it to business competition, which is also a conflict of
human interests and activities; and it is still more like State policy, which
again, on its part, may be looked upon as a kind of business competition on
a great scale. Besides, state policy is the womb in which War is developed,
in which its outlines lie hidden in a rudimentary state, like the qualities of
living creatures in their germs.’IH
Thus we can readily understand why international relations afford a focus
of interest to a particular discipline and why they escape any precise delimita¬
tion. Historians have never isolated the account of events which touch on
relations among states; such an isolation would have been impossible in prac¬
tice, so closely are the ups and downs of military campaigns and diplomatic
combinations related to the vicissitudes of national destinies, and to the rival¬
ries of royal families or social classes. Like diplomatic history, the science of
international relations has to recognize the multiple links between events on
the diplomatic and national scenes. Nor can it rigorously separate inter-state
relations from inter-individual relations involving several political units. But
so long as humanity has not achieved unification into a universal state, an
essential difference will exist between internal politics and foreign politics.
The former tends to reserve the monopoly on violence to those wielding legit¬
imate authority, the latter accepts the plurality of centers of armed force. Poli¬
tics, insofar as it concerns the internal organization of collectivities, has for
its immanent goal the subordination of men to the rule of law. Politics,
insofar as it concerns relations among states, seems to signify—in both ideal
and objective terms—simply the survival of states confronting the potential
threat created by the existence of other states. Hence the common opposition
HlKarl von Clausewitz, On War, Book II, Chap. 3, p. 121. All future references to
this work are taken from the translation by J. J. Graham, Barnes and Noble, 1956.
INTRODUCTION
7
in classical philosophy: the art of politics teaches men to live in peace within
collectivities, while it teaches collectivities to live in either peace or war. States
have not emerged, in their mutual relations, from the state of nature. There
would be no further theory of international relations if they had.
It will be objected that this opposition, distinct on the level of ideas, is no
longer distinct on the level of facts. It presupposes, indeed, that political
units are circumscribed, identifiable. This is the case when the units are repre¬
sented by diplomats and uniformed soldiers—in other words, when they
effectively exercise the monopoly on legitimate violence and recognize each
other’s existence. In the absence of nations conscious of themselves as such,
and of juridically organized states, internal and foreign politics tend to blend,
the former not being essentially pacific and the latter not being radically bel¬
licose.
Under what rubric ought one to classify relations between the sovereign
and his vassals in the Middle Ages, when the king or emperor scarcely pos¬
sessed armed forces which unconditionally obeyed him and when the barons
swore an oath of fealty but not of discipline? By definition, the phases of
diffused sovereignty, of dispersed armament, seem difficult to conceptualize,
whereas conceptualization is appropriate to political units limited in space
and separated from each other by the consciousness of men and the rigor of
ideas.
Occasionally the uncertainty of the distinction between conflicts among
political units and conflicts within a political unit appears even in periods of
concentrated and legally recognized sovereignty. If a province, an integrated
portion of the state’s territory or a fraction of the population, refuses to sub¬
mit to the centralized power and undertake an armed struggle, the conflict,
though civil war with regard to international law, will be considered a foreign
war by those who see the rebels as the expression of an existing or nascent
nation. Had the Confederacy won, the United States would have been di¬
vided into two states, and the War of Secession, having begun as a civil war,
would have ended as a foreign one.
Let us imagine a future universal state including all of humanity. In theory,
there would be no army (the soldier is neither a policeman nor an execu¬
tioner, since he risks his life against another soldier), only a police force. If a
province or a party took arms, the single global state would declare it a rebel
and treat it as such. But this civil war, an episode of internal politics, would
retrospectively seem a return to foreign politics should the rebel victory in¬
volve the dissolution of the universal state.
This ambiguity in “international relations” is not to be imputed to the
inadequacy of our concepts: it is an integral part of reality itself. It reminds
us once again, should we need reminding, that the course of relations among
political units is influenced in many ways by events within those units. It re¬
minds us, too, that the stakes of war are the existence, the creation or the
elimination of states. Their study of transactions between organized states
8
INTRODUCTION
often causes specialists to forget that extreme weakness is as dangerous to
peace as extreme strength. The zones in which armed conflicts break out are
often those in which the political units are decomposing. The states that know
or believe themselves condemned awaken rival greeds or, in a desperate at¬
tempt to save themselves, provoke the outbreak that will consume them.
Does the study of international relations, if extended to include the birth
and the death of states, lose all distinct limits, all originality? Those who be¬
gin by assuming that international relations are concretely separable will be
disappointed by this analysis. But tbeir disappointment is not justified. Having
for its central theme inter-state relations in their specific significance, that is,
their characteristic alternatives of peace and war, and the alternations between
these, the discipline devoted to the study of international relations cannot
ignore the various modalities of relations among nations and empires, nor the
many determinants operative within world diplomacy, nor the circumstances
in which states appear and disappear. A complete science or philosophy of
politics would include international relations as one of its chapters, but this
chapter would retain its originality since it would deal with the relations be¬
tween political units, each of which claims the right to take justice into its
own hands and to be the sole arbiter of the decision to fight or not to fight.
[2]
We shall attempt to consider international relations at three levels of con¬
ceptualization, and we shall then examine the ethical and pragmatic prob¬
lems confronting the man of action. But before characterizing the three levels,
we should like to show how two other realms of human action—sport and
economics—lend themselves to an analogous distinction with respect to the
modes of conceptualization.
Let us consider the game called soccer. For the average spectator, the theory
of the game consists of specifying the nature of the plays and the rules to
which the player is subject. How many players oppose each other on either
side of the central line? What means are the players entitled and not entitled
to use? (They have the right to touch the ball with their heads, not with
their hands.) How are the players distributed between the different lines (for¬
wards, center, wings)? How do they combine their efforts and thwart those
of their opponents? This abstract theory is known by both players and spec¬
tators. The coach has no need to remind his players of it. On the other hand,
in the framework of the rules, many situations can arise, either without de¬
liberate intention, or conceived in advance by the players. For each side, a
coach works out a strategy, specifies each player’s role (this wing will cover
the opponent’s forward), assigns each player responsibilities in certain typical
or predictable situations. At this second stage, theory decomposes into various
discourses addressed to the different players: there is a theory of effective be-
INTRODUCTION
9
havior for the wing, for the forward, for the center, simultaneous with an
effective behavior for all or part of the team in specific circumstances.
At the next stage the theoretician is no longer coach or teacher, but sociol¬
ogist. How do the games proceed, not on the blackboard but on the field?
What are the characteristics of the methods adopted by the players of this or
that country? Is there a Latin American soccer, an English soccer? What is
the share of technical virtuosity and moral virtue in the success of the various
teams? It is impossible to answer such questions without a historical study;
we must observe the succession of games, the development of methods, the
diversity of techniques and temperaments. The sociologist of sport might in¬
vestigate what causes determine national victories, either at a certain period
or continually (exceptional gifts, number of participants, state support, etc.).
The sociologist must combine the lessons of both theoretician and historian.
If he does not understand the logic of the game, he will follow the players’
movements uncomprehendingly. He will not discover the meaning of the
various tactics adopted, of zone play, of individual scoring. But general propo¬
sitions relating to factors of power or causes of victory are not enough to
explain the Hungarian defeat in the world championship finals, nor to satisfy
our curiosity completely. The outcome of a particular game is never deter¬
mined by the logic of the sport nor by the general causes of success: certain
games, like particular wars, remain worthy of the account that historians de¬
vote to the heroes’ ordeals.
Following the coach, the sociologist and the historian, a fourth person in¬
tervenes, inseparable from the actors: the referee. The rules are given in the
text, but how are they to be interpreted? Did the fact warranting sanctions
—the hand foul—actually occur in such and such circumstances? The referee’s
decision is without appeal, but players and spectators inevitably judge the
judge, either silently or noisily. Collective sport, or team competition, pro¬
vokes a series of judgments, laudatory or critical, on the part of players about
each other, of teammate about teammate, of one team about the opposing
team, of players about the referee, of spectators about the players and the
referee. All these judgments oscillate from the appreciation of effectiveness
(he has played well), to the appreciation of correctness (he has respected the
rules), and the appreciation of team spirit (this team has played according to
the spirit of the game). Even in sports, everything not strictly forbidden is
not thereby morally permitted. Lastly, the theory of soccer might envision
the sport itself in relation to the men who participate in it or to the entire
society. Is this sport favorable to the physical health or morality of the play¬
ers? Should the government support it?
Thus we find the four levels of conceptualization we have distinguished,
the schematic arrangement of concepts and systems, the general causes of
events, the development of the sport or of a particular game, and pragmatic
or ethical judgments, bearing on behavior within a particular domain or on
the domain itself considered as a whole.
IO
INTRODUCTION
Diplomatic or strategic behavior affords certain analogies with sport. It too
involves both cooperation and competition. Every collectivity finds itself
among enemies, friends, neutrals or the indifferent. No diplomatic playing
field is marked off with lines, but there is a diplomatic field on which all the
participants appear, capable of intervening in case of a generalized conflict.
The arrangement of the players is not fixed once and for all by rules or
customary tactics, but we do find certain characteristic groupings of partici¬
pants, which constitute so many schematically designed situations.
Cooperative and competitive, the practice of foreign politics also, by its
very nature, involves risk. The diplomat and the strategist act—in other words,
they make decisions before they have assembled all the knowledge desirable
and acquired certainty. Their action is based on probabilities. It would not
be reasonable if it rejected risk: it is reasonable insofar as it calculates risk.
But we can never eliminate the uncertainty inherent in the unpredictability
of human reactions (what will the other do, whether a general or a states¬
man, Hitler or Stalin?), in the secrecy with which states are surrounded, in
the impossibility of knowing everything before taking a decisive step. The
“glorious uncertainty of sport” has its equivalent in political action, whether
violent or non-violent. Let us not imitate the historians who believe that the
past has always been inevitable, and thus suppress the human dimension of
events.
The expressions we have used to characterize the sociology (causes of suc¬
cess, national characteristics of play) and the history of sport, or of a single
game, also apply to the sociology and history of international relations. It is
rational theory and praxiology which differ essentially from one realm to the
next. Compared to soccer, foreign policy seems strangely indeterminate. The
goal of the participants is not as simple as merely getting a ball across a white
line. The rules of diplomatic performance are imperfectly codified, and a
player may violate them when he finds it to his advantage to do so. There is
no referee, and even when all the participants claim the right to judge as a
body (the United Nations), the national actors may not submit to the de¬
cisions of this collective referee whose impartiality is not indisputable. If the
rivalry of nations suggests sport, it is all too often a free-for-all—a catch-as-
catch-can—that would be the appropriate image.
More generally, sports have three particular characteristics: the objective
and the rules of the game are clearly specified; the game is played within a
fixed space, the number of participants is fixed, and the system, delimited in
relation to the external world, is structured within itself; action is subject to
rules of effectiveness and to the decisions of the referee, so that there are
moral or quasi-moral judgments concerning the spirit in which the partici¬
pants play the game itself. Apropos of each of the social sciences, we might
question if or to what degree the goal and rules are defined, if and to what
degree the participants are organized into a system, if and to what degree
INTRODUCTION
II
individual action is subject to obligations, either of effectiveness or of moral¬
ity-
Let us turn from sports to economics: every society, consciously or not, has
an economic problem, and solves it in a particular way. Every society must
satisfy the needs of its members with limited resources. The disproportion be¬
tween desires and goods is not always felt as such. Once a way of life is
accepted as normal or traditional, a collectivity may aspire to nothing beyond
what it already possesses. Such a collectivity is poor in, not for, itself. One
may add a paradox only in appearance—that societies have never been so
aware of their poverty as in our own day, despite the prodigious increase of
their wealth. Desires have advanced even more rapidly than resources. The
limitation of resources seems scandalous once the capacity to produce is—
mistakenly—regarded as unlimited.
Economics is a fundamental category of thought, a dimension of collective
or individual existence. This category is not to be confused with that of
scarcity or poverty (disproportion between desires and resources). Economics
as -problem presupposes merely scarcity or poverty: economics as solution
presupposes that men can master their poverty in various ways, that they
have the possibility of choosing among different ways of utilizing their re¬
sources; in other words, it presupposes the multiplicity of choices which Rob¬
inson Crusoe himself was not unaware of on his island. Crusoe disposed of
his own labor time, he could choose a certain distribution of hours of the day
between labor and leisure, a certain distribution of labor among consumer
goods (food) and investments (house). What is true of the individual is
truer still of the collectivity. Labor force being the primary resource of human
societies, the multiplicity of possible uses of resources is given from the start.
As the economy grows more complex, the possibilities of choice multiply and
goods become increasingly interchangeable; the same object can serve several
ends and various objects can be used for the same ends.
Poverty and choice—poverty is the problem faced by collectivities, and a
particular choice is one solution effectively adopted. These define the eco¬
nomic dimension of human existence. Men who ignore poverty because they
ignore desire are unconscious of the economic dimension. They live as their
ancestors have lived, as they themselves have always lived. Custom is so strong
that it excludes dreams, dissatisfaction, desire for progress. There would be a
post-economic phase if, along with scarcity, the necessity of choice, of pain¬
ful labor, should disappear. Trotsky says somewhere that abundance is now
visible on the horizon of history and that only the petit bourgeois will refuse
to believe in his radiant future and regard the biblical curse as eternal. A
post-economic period is conceivable: capacity for production would become
such that each man could consume according to his will and, out of respect
for others,, would not take more than his fair share from the whole.
The soccer player attempts to send the ball into a space delimited by the
two vertical goal posts linked, two yards above the ground, by a horizontal
12,
INTRODUCTION
bar. Economic man wants to make the best use of insufficient resources, to
utilize them so that they supply the maximum of satisfactions. Economists
have constructed, elaborating various kinds of logic concerning these individ¬
ual choices, the marginal theory, which is, even today, the most common
version of this rational formulation of economic behavior, one that starts with
individuals and their ranges of preference.
Although the theory covers the route which proceeds from individual
choices to total equilibrium, it seems to me logically as well as philosophically
preferable to start from the collectivity. Indeed, the specific characteristics of
economic reality are not discernible except on the level of the collectivity.
Individual ranges of preference may not differ fundamentally within a given
society, since all the individuals more or less adhere to a common system of
values. Nonetheless, activities tending to the maximization of individual satis¬
factions would be ill-defined if money did not introduce the possibility of a
rigorous and universally recognizable measurement. African savages rationally
preferred glass beads to ivory as long as the objects exchanged did not appear
on the same market and did not each have its price in money.
Monetary quantification permits the recognition of accounting standards
for the total economy. Such standards, from the physiocratic table down to
modem studies of national accounting, do not afford an explanation of
changes, but constitute the evidence from which economics attempts to grasp
primary and secondary factors, or those which are determining and those
which are determined. At the same time, the reciprocity of variables, the in¬
terdependence of elements of the economy, becomes evident. To modify
one price is indirectly to modify all. To reduce or increase investments, to
reduce or increase rates of interest is, step by step, to act on the national prod¬
uct as well as on the distribution of this product among its categories.
All economic theories, whether micro- or macro-theory, whether liberal or
socialist in inspiration, emphasize the interdependence of economic variables.
The theory of equilibrium, as Walras or Pareto would call it, reconstructs
the whole by starting from individual choices, as it defines a point of equi¬
librium that would also be the point of maximization of production and in¬
dividual satisfactions (given a certain distribution of income at the start).
Keynesian theory or the macro-theories tackle the system directly as a unity,
and attempt to isolate the determining factors that must be brought into play
to avoid unemployment, raise the national product to its maximum potential,
etc.
Hence the purpose of economic activity, at first glance, appears to be de¬
fined: maximization of satisfactions for the individual making rational choices,
and maximization of monetary resources in the later phase, money being the
universal intermediary among goods. But this definition leaves room for un¬
certainties: at what point, for instance, does the individual prefer leisure
to the increase of his income? Further, the uncertainty—or, if one prefers, the
indeterminacy—becomes an essential aspect if we consider the collectivity.
INTRODUCTION
13
The collectivity faces an “economic problem”: by a certain organization of
production, of exchange and of distribution, the collectivity chooses a solu¬
tion. This solution involves a degree of cooperation among individuals and a
degree of competition. Neither the collectivity as a whole nor individuals as
economic subjects are in situations where one and only one decision is ra¬
tional.
Maximization of the national product as opposed to reduction of inequali¬
ties, maximization of growth as opposed to maintenance of a high level of
consumption, maximization of cooperation authoritatively imposed by the
government as opposed to a laissez-faire attitude toward the machinery of
competition—all societies have these three alternatives, but the choice is not
a logical consequence that can be deduced from the immanent goal of eco¬
nomic activity. Given the plurality of goals ascribed to societies, every eco¬
nomic solution, up till now, involves a debit account along with a credit one.
We need merely invoke duration (what sacrifices must the living accept for
the sake of posterity?) and the diversity of social groups (what distribution
results from a certain organization of production?) to prevent any solution of
an economic problem from being called rationally obligatory under particular
circumstances. The immanent goal of economic activity does not unequivo¬
cally determine either the choice of individuals or the choice of collectivities
as a whole.
According to this analysis, what are the modalities of the theory of the
rational economy? Since the economic problem is fundamental, between the
phase of unconsciousness and the possible phase of abundance, the theoreti¬
cian’s first obligation is to elaborate the major concepts of the economic order
as such (production, exchange, distribution, consumption, money).
The theoretician’s second and most important task is to analyze, elaborate
or construct economic systems. Marginal theorists, Keynesians, specialists in
econometrics or in game theory, and specialists in national income account¬
ing, whatever their differences, all attempt, with equal success, to isolate the
intelligible texture of the economic whole, the reciprocal relations of the
variables. Controversies have no bearing on this texture itself, as expressed in
uniform standards of measurement: no one doubts the accounting equivalents
for saving and investment, but this equivalence is an ex post facto statistical
result, and the mechanics by which it is obtained are complex, often obscure.
The point is whether and under what circumstances excess savings may be
the cause of unemployment, whether and under what circumstances savings
do not provoke reactions likely to end unemployment, whether and under
what circumstances a balance without full employment is possible.
In other terms, neither the Walrasian design of equilibrium nor the modern
designs of national accounting can be refuted as designs. On the other hand,
the models of unemployment or of crisis drawn from theories are contestable
insofar as they imply an explanation or an anticipation of events. The “models
of crisis”—relations determined among the diverse variables of the system—are
14
INTRODUCTION
comparable to the “patterns of situation” in a game, with this difference, that
individuals as economic subjects are in danger of not knowing the exact situ¬
ation created by the relations among variables, whereas the soccer players see
the exact position of their opponents and their teammates.
Economic theory, as we have just sketched it, attempts to isolate the
economic ensemble—the total behavior which actually solves, whether well
or badly, the problem of poverty—and to emphasize the rationality of this
behavior, that is, choices in the use of limited resources, each of which in¬
volves many practices. Every theory, whatever its inspiration, substitutes
economic subjects for concrete individuals, whose behavior is simplified and,
so to speak, rationalized. It reduces to a small number of determinants the
multiple circumstances that influence economic activity. It regards certain
causes as exogenous, without the distinction between endogenous and exog¬
enous factors being constant from one period to the next or from one author
to the next. Sociology is an indispensable intermediary between theory and
fact. The passage from theory toward sociology can be achieved in various
ways.
The behavior of economic subjects—managers, workers, consumers—is
never determined unequivocally by the notion of one maximum: the choice
of an increase in income or a diminution of effort depends on psychological
data that cannot be reduced to a general formula. More generally, the actual
behavior of managers or consumers is influenced by the ways of life, the
moral or metaphysical conceptions, and the ideologies or values of a collectiv¬
ity. Hence there exists a sociology or an economic psychosociology whose
goal is to comprehend the behavior of economic subjects by comparing it
with theoretical schemata or by specifying the choices actually made be¬
tween the various kinds of maximization elaborated by theory.
Sociology can also attempt to relate the economic system to the whole of
society, to follow the reciprocal action which the various realms of action
exercise upon each other.
Finally, sociology can take as its goal a historical typology of economies.
Theory determines the functions which must be fulfilled in any economy.
Measurement of values, conservation of values, distribution of collective re¬
sources among the different occupations, matching products with consumer
desires—all these functions are always fulfilled in fact, whether well or badly.
Each regime is characterized by the mode in which the indispensable func¬
tions are fulfilled. In particular, to confine ourselves to our own period, each
regime grants a greater or lesser share to central planning or to the mecha¬
nisms of the market: the former represents cooperative actions submitted to a
superior authority, the latter a form of competitive action (competition, con¬
forming to rules, assures the distribution of income among individuals, and
produces results which have not been conceived, determined, or desired by
anyone).
The economic historian is indebted to the theoretician who furnishes him
INTRODUCTION
*5
the instruments of understanding (concepts, functions, models), and to the
sociologist who suggests the framework within which events occur and who
helps him to grasp the different social types. As for the experts, the minister
of state or the philosopher—that is, those who advise, decide or act—they
need to know the rational models, the determinants of the system and the
recurrent circumstances. Further, in order to decide for or against a regime,
and not for or against a given measure within a regime, we must know
first the probable merits and defects of each regime, and next what is re¬
quired of the economy: what is the good society and what influence do
certain economic institutions exert upon life? Praxiology, which necessarily
follows theory, sociology and history, again brings into question the premises
of this cumulative comprehension: what is the human meaning of the eco¬
nomic dimension?
The goal of economic action is not so simple as the goal of a sport, but
although there are several notions of a maximum, the theories can reconstruct
the behavior of economic subjects by defining in a certain way the maximum
aimed at and, subsequently, the implications of rationality. The economic
system is less rigorously structured than the system constituted by a game
of soccer: neither the physical limits nor the participants in the economic
system are as precisely determined, but the reciprocal solidarity among the
variables of the economic system, the standards of measure, permit, once a
hypothesis of rationality is admitted, the comprehension of the total texture
starting from the elements. As for the precepts of action, they claim to be
rational on the level of theory, reasonable on the level of fact. They are
devoted to effectiveness when an unequivocal goal has been set, to morality
when it is a question of respecting the rules of competition, and to ultimate
values when we question ourselves about the economic dimension of life,
about work and leisure, abundance and power.
[ 3 ]
Let us turn back to foreign policy and inquire how the levels of con¬
ceptualization are characterized in this domain.
All human behavior, insofar as it is not a simple reflex or the act of a
madman, is comprehensible. But there are manifold modes of intelligibility.
The behavior of the student who has just attended a lecture because it is cold
outside or because he has nothing else to do between two classes is com¬
prehensible. It can be called either “logical” (Pareto’s expression) or “rational”
(Max Weber’s), if it is a means of avoiding the cold or of whiling away an
idle hour pleasantly enough. But it does not present the same characteristics
as the behavior of the student who attends a lecture because he thinks he
may be asked about the subject in an examination, or the behavior of the
manager who makes each of his decisions by referring to the balance-sheet
i6
INTRODUCTION
at the end of the year, or the behavior of the forward who keeps back in
order to disconcert the opposing center, who is guarding him.
What are the traits common to the behavior of these three actors—student,
manager, player? It is not the mode of psychological determination. The
manager may be personally greedy or, quite the contrary, indifferent to gain.
The student who establishes the courses he will take according to the time at
his disposal or the likelihood of the examination questions may like or detest
the subjects he is studying, may want a diploma as a matter of conceit, or
because he must earn his living. Similarly, the soccer player may be an
amateur or a professional, may dream of glory or of wealth, but he is bound
by the requirements of effectiveness which result from the game itself. In
other words, these actions involve, more or less consciously, a calculation, a
combination of means with a view to an end, the acceptance of a risk varying
with certain probabilities. This calculation itself is dictated by both a hierarchy
of preferences and by circumstances, the latter possessing, in both game and
economy, an intelligible texture.
The behavior of the diplomat or the strategist presents certain of these
characteristics, although according to the definition given above, this be¬
havior has neither a goal as determined as that of the soccer player’s or even
an objective, in certain conditions rationally definable by a maximum, like
those of economic subjects. The behavior of the diplomat-strategist, in effect,
is specifically dominated by the risk of war, confronting adversaries in an
incessant rivalry in which each side reserves the right to resort to the ultima
ratio, that is, to violence. The theory of a sport is worked out starting from
the goal (to send the ball across the line). The theory of economics, too,
refers to a goal through the intermediary of the notion of maximization
(although various modalities of this maximum are conceivable). The theory
of international relations starts from the ‘plurality of autonomous centers of
decision, hence from the risk of war, and from this risk it deduces the
necessity of the calculation of means.
Certain theoreticians have tried to find the equivalent of the rational goal
of sport or economics for international relations. A single goal, victory, ex¬
claims the na'ive general, forgetting that military victory always affords satis¬
faction for amour-propre, but not always political benefits. A single impera¬
tive, national interest, solemnly proclaims the theoretician, hardly less naive
than the general, as if adding the adjective national to the concept of interest
were enough to make it unequivocal. International politics is a struggle for
power and security, declares another theoretician, as if there were never any
contradiction between the two, as if collective persons, unlike individuals,
were rationally obliged to prefer life to the reasons for living.
We shall have occasion to discuss these theoretical endeavors during the
course of this work. At the outset, let us confine ourselves to stating that
diplomatic-strategic behavior does not have an obvious objective, but that the
risk of war obliges it to calculate forces or means. As we shall try to show
INTRODUCTION
*7
in the first part of this book, the alternatives of peace and war permit the
elaboration of the fundamental concepts of international relations.
The same alternatives permit us to express "the problem of foreign policy”
as we have expressed the problem of economics. For thousands of years, men
have lived in closed societies which were never entirely subject to a superior
authority. Each collectivity had to count chiefly on itself to survive, but
it also had—or should have had—to contribute to the task common even to
enemy cities, exposed to the risk of perishing together by dint of constantly
fighting each other.
The double problem of individual and collective survival has never been
lastingly solved by any civilization. It could only be definitively solved by a
universal state or by the rule of law. One might call pre-diplomatic the
age in which collectivities did not maintain regular relations with each other,
and post-diplomatic the age of a universal state which would allow only for
internecine combats. As long as each collectivity must think of its own safety
at the same time as of that of the diplomatic system or of the human race,
diplomatic-strategic behavior will never be rationally determined, even in
theory.
This relative indeterminacy does not keep us from elaborating a rational
type of theory in Part One, proceeding from fundamental concepts (strategy
and diplomacy, means and ends, power and force, power, glory and idea)
to systems and types of systems. Diplomatic systems are neither spread out
on the map like a playing field nor unified by standards of measure, and
by the interdependence of variables like economic systems, but each partici¬
pant knows roughly in relation to which adversaries and which partners he
must situate himself.
Such a theory, producing models of diplomatic systems, distinguishing
typical situations on a generalized level, imitates economic theory, which
elaborates models of crisis or unemployment. But, lacking a single goal of
diplomatic behavior, the rational analysis of international relations cannot
b e developed i nto an inclusive theory.
Chapter Vlj dedicated to a typology of peace and war, serves as a transi¬
tion between Part I and Part II, between the interpretation growing out of
the conduct of foreign policy and the sociological explanation of the course
of events, drawn from material or social causes. Sociology seeks the circum¬
stances which influence the stakes of the conflicts among states, the goals
which the participants choose, the fortunes of nations and empires. Theory
reveals the intelligible texture of a social ensemble; sociology shows how the
determinants (space, number, resources) and the subjects (nations, regimes,
civilizations), of international relations vary.
Part III of the book, concerned with present circumstances, aims first at
testing the method of analysis elaborated in the first two parts. But in certain
respects, because of the worldwide extension of the diplomatic field and the
invention of thermonuclear weapons, the present circumstances are unique
i8
INTRODUCTION
and unprecedented. They involve situations which lend themselves to
analysis by "model.” In this sense Part III, at a lower level of abstraction,
contains both a rationalizing theory and a sociological theory of diplomacy in
the global and thermonuclear age.
At the same time it constitutes a necessary introduction to the last part,
which is both normative and philosophical, and in which the initial hypoth¬
eses are re-examined.
Economics disappears with the disappearance of scarcity. Under conditions
of abundance, the problem becomes one of organization, not of economic
calculation. Similarly, war would cease being an instrument of politics the
day it involved the mutual suicide of the belligerents. The capacity for indus¬
trial production restores some relevance to the utopia of abundance, the de¬
structive capacity of weapons revives the dreams of eternal peace.
All societies have known the “problem of international relations”; and
many times cultures have been destroyed because they were unable to limit
wars. In our day not only one culture but all of humanity would be threat¬
ened by a hyperbolic war. The prevention of such a war becomes for all
participants in the diplomatic game a goal as evident as the defense of purely
national interests.
According to the profound and perhaps prophetic view of Immanuel Kant,
humanity must travel the bloody road of war to have access one day to peace.
It is through history that the repression of natural violence is achieved, the
education of man to reason.
PART ONE
THEORY
Concepts and Systems
Taylor &. Francis
Taylor &. Francis Group
http://taylorandfrands.com
chapter I
Strategy and Diplomacy
or
On the Unity of Foreign Policy
‘War ... is an act of violence intended to compel our opponent to
fulfill our will-SThis famous definition will serve as our point of departure:
it is no less valid today than at the moment is was written. War, insofar
as it is a social act, presupposes the conflicting wills of politically organized
collectivities. Each seeks to prevail over the other. “Physical force ... is
therefore the means; the compulsory submission of the enemy to our will is
the ultimate object.I
I. Absolute War and Real Wars
From this definition, Clausewitz deduces the tendency of war to escalate
or even to become total. The basic reason for this is what we might call the
dialectics of the contest.
“War is an act of violence pushed to its utmost bounds; as one side
dictates the law to the other, there arises a sort of reciprocal action, which
logically must lead to an extreme.tH Any belligerent that refuses to resort
to certain brutalities must fear that the adversary will gain the advantage by
abandoning all scruples. Wars among civilized nations are not necessarily
less cruel than wars among savage tribes. For the basic cause of war is the
hostile intent, not the sentiment of hostility. In general, given the hostile
intent on both sides, passion and hatred soon animate the combatants, but in
theory a major war without hatred is conceivable. The most one can say
apropos of civilized peoples is that “intelligence exercises greater influence
on their mode of carrying on War, and has taught them more effectual means
of applying force than these rude acts of mere instinct.’H The fact remains
that the desire to destroy the enemy, inherent in the concept of war, has not
been hindered or repressed by the progress of civilization.
Clausewitz,
Ibid.
j^lbid., p. 4.
Hi bid.
I, I, p.
22
THEORY
The goal of military operations, in the abstract, is to disarm the adversary.
Yet since “the enemy is to be reduced to submission by an act of War, he
must either be positively disarmed or placed in such a position that he is
threatened with it.” But the adversary is not an “inert mass.” War is the
impact of two living forces. “As long as the enemy is not defeated, he may
defeat me; ... he will dictate the law to me as I did to him.’fH
War is won only when the adversary submits to our will. If necessary, we
measure the means at his disposal and determine our own effort accordingly.
But the will to resist cannot be measured. The adversary proceeds in the
same fashion, and each side augments its preparations to allow for the hostile
intent, so that the competition once again leads to extremes.
This dialectic of the contest is purely abstract; it does not apply to real
wars as they unfold in history, but reveals what would happen in an instan¬
taneous duel between adversaries defined solely by reciprocal hostility and
by the will to conquer. At the same time, this abstract dialectic reminds us
what might actually occur each time passions or circumstances bring a histori¬
cal struggle close to the ideal model of combat and, thereby, of absolute war.
In the real world “war [does not become] a completely isolated act, which
arises suddenly, and is in no way connected with the previous history of the
combatant states.® The adversaries know each other in advance, they form
an approximate idea of their respective resources, even of their respective
intent. The forces of each of the adversaries are never entirely mustered. The
fate of nations is not staked on a single momentUlThe intentions of a vic¬
torious adversary do not always involve an irreparable disaster for the van¬
quished. As soon as these various considerations intervene—the substitution of
real adversaries for the abstract concept of the enemy, the duration of opera¬
tions, the apparent intentions of the belligerents, the accumulation and use
of every means in order to conquer and disarm the enemy—it becomes a
venturesome action, a calculation of probabilities varying with the informa¬
tion accessible to the partner-adversaries in the political game.
For war is a game. It requires both courage and calculation; calculation
never excludes risk, and at every level the acceptance of danger is alternately
manifested by prudence and audacity. “From the outset there is a play of
possibilities, probabilities, good and bad luck, which spreads about with all
the coarse and fine threads of its web, and makes War of all branches of
human activity the most like a gambling game.{l
Yet, “War is always a serious means for a serious object.” The initial ele¬
ment, animal as much as human, is animosity, which we must consider a
natural blind impulse. Belligerent action itself, the second element, involves
j’lbid., p. j.
® Ibid., p. 7.
ilPreparation for a single engagement that would decide everything leads to absolute
war, Clausewitz says. In the twentieth century, modem weapons risk creating precisely
this situation. This has never been the case until the present.
[Hlbid., p. 20.
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
2 3
an interaction of probabilities and risks which makes war a “work of a free
enthusiasm.” But a third element must be added to these, one which ulti¬
mately dominates them: war is a political action, it rises out of a political
situation and results from a political motive. It belongs by nature to pure
understanding because it is an instrument of policy. The emotional element
involves chiefly the people, the problematical element the commander and his
army, and the intellectual element the government; and it is this latter
element that is decisive and that must control the whole.
Thus Clausewitz’s famous formula—“War is not merely a political act, but
also a real political instrument, a continuation of political commerce, a carry¬
ing out of the same by other means’El-is not the expression of a bellicose
philosophy, but a simple observation of fact: war is not an end in itself,
military victory is not the goal in itself. Commerce between nations does not
cease the day guns begin to speak; the belligerent phase takes its place in a
continuity of relations always controlled by the collectivities’ intentions to¬
ward each other.
The subordination of war to policy as a means to an end, implicit in
Clausewitz’s formula, establishes and justifies the distinction of absolute war
and real wars..Escalation is the more to be feared, and real wars risk coming
closer to absolute war, the more violence escapes the control of the chief of
state. Policy seems to vanish when it takes the destruction of the enemy
army as its single goal. Even in this case, war assumes a form that results
from political intentions. Whether or not policy is visible in the belligerent
action, the latter remains dominated by policy if we define policy as “the
intelligence of the personified State.” It is still policy—i.e., the total considera¬
tion of all circumstances by statesmen—that rightly or wrongly decides to
assume as its sole objective the destruction of the enemy’s armed forces,
without regard for ulterior objectives, without reflection as to the probable
consequences of victory itself.
Clausewitz is a theoretician of absolute war, not a doctrinaire of total
war or militarism, just as Walras is a theoretician of equilibrium, not a
doctrinaire of liberalism. Conceptual analysis, concerned with isolating the
essence of the human act, has been mistakenly confused with the determina¬
tion of an objective. Clausewitz, it is true, sometimes seems to admire the
war that tends to realize its own nature completely, and to reserve his con¬
tempt for the imperfect wars of the eighteenth century in which maneuvers
and negotiations reduced the combatants’ engagements, their brutality and
fur)', to a minimum. But granted that these sentiments appear on occasion,
they express simple emotions. When confronted with war driven to its ex¬
treme, Clausewitz feels a kind of sacred horror, a fascination comparable to
that wakened by cosmic catastrophes. The war in which each adversary pro¬
ceeds to the absolute of violence in order to vanquish the enemy’s will,
0Z bid.., p. 23.
24
THEORY
which stubbornly resists, is in Clausewitz’s eyes both awe-inspiring and hor¬
rible. Whenever great interests are at stake, war will approach its absolute
form. As a philosopher, he is neither delighted nor indignant. As a theoreti¬
cian of rational action, he reminds leaders of war and peace of the principle
both must respect: the primacy of policy, war being merely an instrument in
the service of politically determined goals, a moment or an aspect of relations
among states, each of which is obliged to submit to the political realm, i.e.,
the perception of the collectivity’s lasting interests.
Let us agree to call strategy the conduct of military operations as a whole,
and diplomacy the conduct of relations with other political units. Strategy
and diplomacy will both be subordinate to politics, that is, to the conception
on the part of the collectivity or its leaders of the “national interest.” In
peacetime, politics makes use of diplomatic means, not excluding recourse to
arms, at least when threatened. In wartime, politics does not exclude diplo¬
macy, since the latter conducts relations with allies and neutrals, and con¬
tinues to deal tacitly with the enemy, threatening defeat, or offering a pos¬
sibility of peace.
Here we are considering the “political unit” as an actor, enlightened by
intelligence and prompted by will. Every state has relations with other states;
as long as the states remain in peace, they must somehow manage to live
together. Unless they resort to violence, they attempt to convince each other.
The day they fight, they attempt to constrain each other. In this sense,
diplomacy might be called the art of convincing without using force (con-
vainer e), and strategy the art of vanquishing at the least cost ( vainere).
But constraint, too, is a means of convincing. A demonstration of force
causes the adversary to yield, symbolizing rather than actually imposing con¬
straint. The side possessing a superiority of weapons in peacetime convinces
its ally, rival or adversary without having to make use of such weapons.
Conversely, the state which has acquired a reputation for equity or modera¬
tion has a better chance of achieving its goals without proceeding to the
extremity of military victory. Even in wartime it will convince more than it
will constrain.
The distinction between diplomacy and strategy is an entirely relative one.
These two terms are complementary aspects of the single art of politics—the
art of conducting relations with other states so as to further the “national
interest.” If, by definition, strategy, the conduct of miliary operations, does
not function when the operations do not take place, the military means are
an integral part of diplomatic method. Conversely, words, notes, promises,
guarantees and threats belong to the chief of state’s wartime panoply with
regard to allies, neutrals, and even today’s enemies, that is, to the allies of
yesterday or tomorrow.
The complementary duality of the art of convincing and the art of con¬
straining reflects a still more essential duality which Clausewitz’s initial
definition reveals: war is a test of will. Human insofar as it is a test of will,
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
25
war by its nature involves a psychological element best illustrated by the
celebrated formula: he is not conquered who dares not admit defeat. Na¬
poleon could only win, Clausewitz writes, if Tsar Alexander admitted he
was beaten after the taking of Moscow. If Alexander did not lose courage,
Napoleon, though apparently the victor at Moscow, was already virtually
defeated. Napoleon’s plan of war was the only one possible, but it was based
on a gamble which Alexander’s steadfastness caused the emperor of the
French to lose. The English are beaten, Hitler howled in July 1940, but
they’re too stupid to realize it. Not to admit they were defeated was indeed
the first condition of final success for the English. Whether it was courage
or lack of awareness is of little account: what mattered was that the English
wanted to resist.
In absolute war, in which extreme violence leads to the disarmament or
the destruction of one of the adversaries, the psychological element ulti¬
mately disappears. But this operates as a limiting case. All real wars bring
into conflict collectivities which are united in expressing one will. In this
regard, they are all psychological wars.
1. Strategy and the Goal of War
The relation of strategy and policy is expressed by a double formula: “War
is to harmonize entirely with the political views and policy, to accommodate
itself to the means available for War .’0 In a sense, the two parts of the
formula might seem contradictory, since the first subordinates the conduct
of war to political intentions and the second makes political intentions depend
on the available means. But Clausewitz’s thought and the logic of action
leave no room for doubt: policy cannot determine the goals apart from the
means at its disposal, and, further, “the political element does not sink deep
into the details of War. Vedettes are not planted, patrols do not make their
rounds from political considerations; but small as is its influence in this
respect, it is great in the formation of a plan for a whole War, or a campaign,
and often even for a battle.Examples will illustrate the scope of these
abstract propositions.
The conduct of war requires the determination of a strategic plan: "every
War should he viewed above all things according to the -probability of its
character, and its leading features, as they are to be deduced from the political
forces and proportions .’ Hi In 1914 all the belligerents were mistaken as to
the nature of the war they were about to wage. On neither side had the
general staffs or the ministries conceived or prepared mobilization of indus¬
tries or populations. Neither the Central Powers nor the Allies had counted
on a prolonged conflict whose result would be decided by the superior
Mlhicl., VIII, 6, p. 127.
OlbuZ., p. 123.
tllhii., p. 125.
2.6
THEORY
resources of one of the two camps. The generals had rushed into a “fresh and
joyous” war, convinced that the first engagements would be decisive as they
had been in 1870. The strategy of annihilation would produce victory, and
the statesmen of the winning side would dictate the terms of peace to the
vanquished enemy.
When the French victory on the Marne and the stability of the eastern
and western fronts had dissipated the illusion of a short war, policy should
have reasserted itself, since it is effaced only at that moment of belligerent
paroxysm when violence rages without restraint and each of the belligerents
is concerned only with being physically the stronger. Of course, policy did
not cease to function between 1914 and 1918, but, particularly on the Allied
side, it seems to have had no other goal than to sustain the war itself. The
victory that the Allies had first sought by a strategy of annihilation they later
attempted through a strategy of attrition. But at no time did they seriously
consider the goals they might have been able to attain without total victory;
disarming the enemy and a dictated rather than negotiated peace became
their supreme war goals. The war itself approached its absolute form insofar
as the statesmen abdicated in favor of the army chiefs and substituted for
political goals, which they were incapable of determining, a strictly military
goal, the destruction of the enemy armies.
Perhaps this collapse of policy was inevitable under the circumstances.
Would Germany ever have renounced Alsace-Lorraine unless it had been
obliged to by the defeat? Could French public opinion ever have been forced
to accept a compromise peace, with neither annexation nor indemnities,
after so many sacrifices had been imposed upon the people and so many
promises lavished by the government? The secret treaties concluded among
the Allies sanctioned so many revenges and recorded so many solemn promises
that any impulse toward negotiations without victory risked dissolving the
fragile coalition of the future victors. Finally, hostilities themselves created
a new, ineffaceable fact which upset previous conditions: the status of all
Europe seemed jeopardized, and statesmen did not believe that the return to
the status quo ante afforded a likelihood of stability.
Perhaps major wars are precisely those which, by reason of the passions
they release, ultimately escape the men who have the illusion of controlling
them. Retrospectively, the observer does not always perceive the conflict of
interests that would have justified the passions and excluded the compromise.
Perhaps, as I am tempted to believe, it is the very nature of industrialized
warfare which ends by communicating hatred and fury to the masses and
inspiring statesmen with the desire to disrupt the map of the old continent.
The fact is that the first war of the century illustrates the transition toward
the absolute form of a war whose political stake the belligerents are incapable
of specifying.
The substitution of the military objective—victor)'—for the objectives of
peace is still more strikingly evident in the Second World War. General
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
27
Giraud, a soldier who had not given much thought to Clausewitz, repeated
in 1942: a single goal, victory. But it was more serious that President Roose¬
velt, though he did not coin this phrase, acted as though he believed it. The
fastest possible destruction of the enemy’s armed forces became the supreme
imperative to which the conduct of operations was subordinated. By de¬
manding unconditional surrender, a civilian war leader naively bore witness
to his incomprehension of the relations between strategy and policy.
Unconditional surrender corresponded to the logic of the War of Secession.
What had become the stake of the war was the existence of the United States,
the prohibition of the states from leaving the Union. The Union victory
involved the annihilation of the Confederacy. The demand for unconditional
surrender had a rational meaning, whether it concerned the political leaders
of the Confederacy or General Lee, commander of the last Southern armies.
There was nothing similar in the case of Germany: neither the Soviets nor
the Americans intended to suppress the existence of Germany as a state. The
temporary suspension of this existence involved as many disadvantages as
advantages for the victors. In any case, by assuming the destruction of the
German armed forces and the unconditional surrender of the Reich as its
sole objective, strategy laid itself open to three criticisms.
It is admitted that it is better to win with as few losses as possible (the
formula, in strategy, has a significance analogous to that of the lowest price
in economics). The insistence on unconditional surrender incited the German
people to a desperate resistance. The American leaders declared they wanted
to avoid the repetition of what had occurred in 1918-19, the German pro¬
tests against the violation of promises contained in President Wilson’s “Four¬
teen Points.” As a matter of fact, these protests had counted for little or
nothing in the failure of the Versailles Treaty. The Allied victory of 1918 had
been sterile because the war itself had released revolutionary forces and
because the English and American governments did not want to defend the
status they had helped establish. By suggesting the fate that would have
been reserved for a conquered Germany, the Americans would not have lost
their freedom of maneuver and would have allowed themselves an additional
chance of conquering without proceeding to the last extremity of violence.
The manner of achieving military victory inevitably influences the course
of events. It was not a matter of indifference in 1944 whether Europe was
liberated from the east, the south, or the west. It is no use speculating on
what would have happened had the English and American armies landed in
the Balkans. Was such a plan even possible? What would have been Stalin’s
reaction? It remains a mistake, on the theoretical level, that the American
decision was dictated by the exclusive concern to destroy the major part of
the German army and that consideration of the political consequences of one
method or another was regarded by Roosevelt and his advisers as an un¬
warranted intrusion of politics into the realm of strategy.
Finally, any conduct of a war, within a coalition, must take into account
28
THEORY
potential rivalries among allies, simultaneous with actual hostilities against
the enemy. There is, I believe, a radical distinction between permanent
allies and occasional allies. We may consider as permanent allies those states
that, whatever the conflict of some of their interests, do not conceive, in the
foreseeable future, that they can be in opposite camps. Great Britain and
the United States are, in the twentieth century, permanent allies, the En¬
glish political leaders having wisely decided that once England lost the rule
of the sea, the pax Americana was the only acceptable substitute for the
pax Britannica. France and Great Britain, after 1914, should also have con¬
sidered each other as permanent allies. Great Britain should have regarded
a temporary and fragile excess of French power with irritation perhaps, but
without distress or resentment. The reinforcement of a permanent ally
should not arouse jealousy or alarm.
The reinforcement of an occasional ally, on the contrary, is, as such, a
long-term threat. Occasional allies, in fact, have no bond other than a com¬
mon hostility toward an enemy, a hostility capable of inspiring sufficient fear
to overcome the rivalries that yesterday opposed and tomorrow will oppose
again the temporarily allied states. Moreover, occasional allies, on a deeper
level, may be permanent enemies : by this we mean states that are committed
to conflict because of their ideology or their position on the diplomatic
chessboard. Roosevelt, refusing to conduct the war in relation to the postwar
period as well, dreaming of a tripartite (or bipartite) directorate of the
universe, denouncing the French and British empires rather than the Soviet
Empire, mistook an occasional ally for a permanent one and lost sight of the
essential hostility hidden beneath a temporary cooperation.
The disastrous consequences of hyperbolic war were, after the fact, at¬
tributed in part to the obsession with military victory at any cost and by any
means. Perhaps the West’s political defeats, twice following the triumph of
arms (a defeat caused the first time by the loser’s attempt to gain revenge, and
the second time by the excessive reinforcement of the occasional ally but
permanent enemy), helped make statesmen aware of the primacy of politics.
The war in Korea offers a contrary, almost pure, example of a war waged
always as a function of politics and never with a view to military victory
alone. When General MacArthur proclaimed: “There is no substitute for
victory,’® he seemed to be adopting the concept that had been Roosevelt’s,
assuming as his goal the destruction of the enemy’s armed forces and a peace
dictated after the latter’s disarmament.
President Truman and his advisers hesitated as to their political objective.
Was the goal to be only that of repulsing North Korean aggression and re¬
establishing the status quo ante, that is, the partition of Korea at the 38th
Parallel, or the unification of the two Korean states in conformity with a
iUlf victory does not mean military victory here, the phrase is no more than a sen¬
tentious truism.
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
2 9
United Nations decision? Naturally the American leaders would have pre¬
ferred the second objective to the first, but contrary to what had happened
during the two majors wars, they did not start with the imperative of military
victory, deducing the logical consequences (total mobilization, recruiting of
allies, pitiless combat, etc.); they started with a different imperative (not to
transform the local war into a general one), and they sought objectives
accessible within the framework of refusal to enlarge the conflict.
After the landing at Inchon and the destruction of the North Korean
armies, President Truman, following the advice of General MacArthur, who
did not believe the Chinese would intervene, took the risk of crossing the 38th
Parallel. The intervention of the Chinese “volunteers” involved the first ex¬
tension of the hostilities. China became a non-official belligerent, but the
American leaders once again took as their goal the limitation of the conflict,
with the limitation of the theater of operation being its spatial projection and
in a sense its symbol. Again, and finally, the question raised in the spring of
1951 was that of the objectives accessible without the war’s amplification.
Soon even this question was abandoned and the American leaders, renouncing
a local or partial victory, had no ambition beyond obtaining a peace which
was virtually equivalent to a return to the status quo ante.
Who would the winner be? The Americans, because they had repulsed
the North Korean aggression? The Chinese, because they had repulsed the
American attempt to liquidate the People’s Republic of North Korea? Not
having been beaten by the world’s first-ranking power, the Chinese had
gained in prestige. But the Americans had confirmed the value of the guaran¬
tees they had distributed all over the world, and given striking proof that they
would not tolerate open aggressions (crossing of frontiers by regular armies).
It is not established that the American desire for the conflict’s limitation
stood in the way of local military successes (with two or three extra divisions,
the Eighth Army might have been able, not to disarm Communist China, but
to defeat the Chinese “volunteers").
The contrast between the essentially political conduct of the Korean War
and the essentially military conduct of both world wars cannot he explained
by human fallibility alone. The conduct of the Second World War was es¬
sentially political—i.e., dictated by consideration of the consequences remote
from the scene of hostilities and of victory —on the Soviet side. It is on the
American side that no attempt was made to discover whether the world
resulting from a total military victory would correspond to the lasting interests
of the United States. It is obviously not proved that the adoption of such a
line of thought would have sufficed to avoid the deplorable effects of the
victory—that is, the excessive reinforcement of the occasional ally but perma¬
nent enemy, the excessive weakening of the present enemy but future ally
confronting the ally that had become too powerful. The nature of each war
depends on many circumstances which the strategist must understand but
which he is not always in a position to modify.
3°
THEORY
It is possible that after 1915 the First World War had to follow its own
course to the end, the chiefs of state on either side being unable to formulate
and make their peoples accept the terms of a compromise peace. It is possible
that with or without unconditional surrender Hitler would have succeeded
in sweeping the German people to the twilight of the gods of race and blood.
It is possible that with or without the Yalta agreement, the Soviet Union
would have intervened in the Far East and reaped the fruits of the victory won
by the American forces. The fact remains that neither in Europe nor in Asia
did American strategists subordinate the conduct of operations against the
enemy and of relations with the occasional ally to a consideration of the
objectives they wished to achieve by the war. The strategists did not know
which Europe, which Asia would correspond to American interests. They
did not know if Japan or Germany was the enemy, or only a certain Japan, a
certain German)'.
It is not enough to determine the objective, the ally, the enemy, in order
to profit by the victory. If the intelligence of the state has not clearly
determined its goals, and discerned the true nature of enemy and ally alike,
the triumph of weapons will only by accident be an authentic victory, that is,
a political one.
3. To Win or Not to Lose
The choice of a strategy depends on both the goals of war and the available
means. We have just analyzed extreme examples of wars waged with a view
to military success alone, or with a view to avoiding the extension of the
conflict. But it is within these extremes that we find most of the real wars in
which a strategy is chosen with regard to both military possibilities and
intentions.
Perhaps the supreme alternative, on the level of strategy, is “to win or not
to lose.” A strategy can aim at decisively conquering the enemy’s armed
forces in order to dictate the terms of a victorious peace to the disarmed
enemy. But when the relation of forces excludes such an eventuality, the
war leaders can still propose not to lose, by discouraging the superior coali¬
tion’s intention of conquering.
German authors like H. Delbriick have found the ideal example of such
a strategy in the Seven Years’ War. Frederick II nursed no illusions of con¬
quering the Austro-Russian army, but he counted on holding out long
enough for his adversaries’ morale to disintegrate, and for the Alliance to fall
apart. We know how the death of an emperor actually provoked a reversal
of Russian policy. The recollection of this piece of luck was so deeply en¬
graved in the German memory that Goebbels, learning of Roosevelt’s death,
believed that the miracle of Frederick II would be repeated: was not the
alliance between the United States and the Soviet Union still more contrary
to nature than that of St. Petersburg and Vienna?
Other, more immediate examples will illustrate the problem’s lasting na-
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
31
ture. Given the relation of forces, what must be the strategist’s goal? This
was the basic question, by 1915-16, that divided German generals and states¬
men. Were the Central Powers to choose as their goal a victory that would
permit them to dictate the clauses of the peace treaty? Or, given the superi¬
ority of forces that the Allies were acquiring, should the Central Powers
renounce victory and limit their ambitions to a compromise peace based on
the recognition by each side of its incapacity to prevail over the other deci¬
sively?
Contrary to what most Frenchmen believed, the Verdun offensive, in the
framework of General von Falkenhayn’s strategy, aimed at wearing down,
rather than defeating, the French army. The German command intended to
weaken the latter until, by the spring and summer of 1916, it would be
incapable of any major undertaking. Unconcerned about the west, the Ger¬
man army could take the offensive in the east and score successes there
which would convince the Allies to come to terms, even if they were not
obliged to.
The Successor group, Hindenburg-Ludendorff, chose, on the contrary,
the other alternative. Until the spring of 1918 the German armies tried to
force the decision. Russia had been put hors de combat in 1917; American
troops were flowing into Europe; the balance of forces, still favorable at the
beginning of 1918, was becoming increasingly unfavorable. The German
general staff tried to win before the intervention of a still intact American
army with inexhaustible forces. Flistorians and theoreticians (in particular
FI. Delbriick) have speculated whether such a strategy of destruction didn’t,
by 1917, constitute an error. Shouldn’t the generals have economized their
means, limited the German losses in order to hold out as long as possible in
the hope that the Allies would weary of the struggle and be content with a
negotiated peace? Renouncing the effort to force a decision, strategy would
have tried, by defensive successes, to convince the enemy as well to renounce
his ambition of victory.
Another more striking example of this dialectic of victory and non-defeat
is that of Japan in 1941. How could the Japanese Empire, engaged for years
in an endless war against China, launch itself into the assault of every
European position in southeast Asia, simultaneously challenging Great Brit¬
ain and the United States, when it produced scarcely seven million tons of
steel a year and the United States was producing over ten times as much?
What calculation of the war leaders was responsible for this extravagant
venture?
The calculation was as follows: by the surprise attack on Pearl Harbor, the
Japanese fleet would gain several months’ control of the seas, extending at
least as far as Australia. Infantry and air force could conquer the Philippines,
Malaya, Indonesia, and perhaps the American outposts of the Pacific, such
as Guam. Controlling an enormous area rich in stockpiles of raw materials,
Japan would be in a position to organize and prepare her defense. None of
3 2
THEORY
the highest-ranking generals or admirals conceived of Japanese troops entering
Washington and dictating an unconditional peace following a total victory
over the United States. The Japanese leaders who took the responsibility of
launching the war intended to resist the American counteroffensive long
enough to exhaust the enemy will to be victorious (which, they believed,
must be weak, since the United States was a democracy).
The calculation turned out to be doubly false: in four years American
submarines and planes destroyed virtually the entire Japanese commercial
fleet. The latter was already basically defeated even before American bombs
set fire to the Japanese cities and Roosevelt purchased Soviet participation
in the war (though he should have been ready to purchase Soviet abstention).
The calculation was no less false with regard to psychology. Democracies
often cultivate pacifist ideologies: they are not always pacifist. In any case,
once enraged, the Americans struck hard: the attack on Pearl Harbor gave
the Japanese fleet a temporary mastery of Asian waters, but it made United
States renunciation of victory very unlikely. The success of the military
calculation during the first phase excluded the success of the psychological
calculation regarding the final phase. Not that a better strategy^] was avail¬
able to the Japanese leaders: none could reasonably promise victory in a
showdown between adversaries so unequal.
The hope of winning by attrition assumes another meaning in the case
of revolution or subversive wars. Insurrections are launched by minorities or
by mobs without consideration of the “relation of forces.” Usually the rebels
have no chance on paper. Those in power command the army, the police:
how can men without organization and without arms prevail? For that matter,
if the government obtains the obedience of its servants, they do not prevail.
But the Parisian rioters in 1830 and 1848 won because neither the soldiers
of the regular army nor, in 1848, the garde nationale seemed determined to
fight and because, abandoned by part of the political elite, the sovereigns
themselves lost their courage, quickly abdicated, and went into exile.
The riots which the weak morale of armies transforms into revolutions
do not belong in a theory of international relations. We have referred to them
because the wars called subversive present certain characteristics of revolu¬
tions: above all, the decisive importance of psychological elements. In the
Russian civil war between the revolutionary party and the conservative party,
between the Bolsheviks, masters of the state, and the generals advocating a
restoration, the will of the leading minorities and the state of mind of the
masses influenced the outcome no less than the material resources accessible
to either camp. (However, in Spain it was Franco’s material superiority which
determined the outcome still more than the discord in the Republican camp.)
The Vendeans did not fight any the less fiercely against the revolutionary
[^Except perhaps Admiral Yamamoto's proposal to carry the initial venture to still
greater extremes and attempt the occupation of Pearl Harbor.
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
33
power than the Blues for the new world. Let us avoid mythologies. Bare¬
handed rebels are irresistible when those in power cannot or will not defend
themselves. The Russian armies of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries
effectively restored order in Warsaw and in Budapest.
The wars known today as “subversive,” for instance that of a population in
a colonial regime against the European power, are intermediary between civil
and foreign wars. If the territory has been juridically integrated with that of
the metropolitan nation—as is the case with Algeria—the war, in terms of
international law, is chiefly civil (the sovereignty of France over Algeria was
recognized by all states), although the rebels regard it as a foreign war inso¬
far as they wish to become an independent political unit. In Tonkin, in
Annam, in Tunisia, in Morocco, countries that were not colonies but over
which France had established a protectorate or suzerainty, the “international
conflict” aspect prevails, even in terms of international law, over the “civil
war” aspect.
We bring together the problem raised by these subversive wars with that
which confronts the strategist who must establish his plan of war because
the rebel and the traditional leader must both deal with the alternative: to
win or not to lose. Yet there is a difference: in 1916, in 1917, even in 1918
the supreme commanders on either side nursed hopes of destroying the
enemy’s power to resist. Nivelle in the spring of 1917 and Ludendorff in the
spring of 1918 counted on forcing the decision by a direct offensive. Both
dreamed of an annihilating victory in the Napoleonic style—a victory inacces¬
sible to the efforts of both camps until the end of the war, the attrition of
one side, and the reinforcement of the other by American forces deciding
the outcome. In the case of a subversive war in which one side controls
administration and police, assures order, and mobilizes regular armies, the
disproportion of forces is such that only one of the belligerents can dream
of a total military success. The conservative party has the desire to conquer,
the rebel party the desire not to let itself be eliminated or exterminated. Here
again we find the typical dissymmetry: one side wants to win, the other
not to lose.
But this dissymmetry, which formally resembles that of the Seven Years’
War (Frederick II against an overpowering coalition), has, fundamentally,
an entirely different meaning. Frederick hoped to obtain a compromise peace
on the day his adversaries recognized, if not the impossibility of beating him,
at least the cost and the time victory would have demanded. Not having been
defeated, the King of Prussia was in relative terms a victor: he would keep
his previous conquests, and his prestige would be increased in proportion
to his heroism. Not having been victorious, the coalition of the traditional
great powers admitted the newcomer on a basis of equality. But if the
rebellious side—the Neo-Destour, the Istiqlal—is not eliminated, but seizes
power and obtains independence, it has won a total victory in political terms,
since it has achieved its objective, the nation’s independence, and since the
34
THEORY
protecting or colonial power has ultimately abandoned the authority it had
arrogated to itself. In this case it would be enough for the rebel side not to
lose militarily in order to gain politically. But why does the conservative party
accept its defeat politically without having been defeated militarily? Why
must it win decisively by eliminating the rebellion if it wants not to lose?
To understand the political outcome of a straggle that is indecisive in
military terms, we must recall another dissymmetry of the parties in a colonial
conflict. The nationalists who demand the independence of their nation
(which has or has not existed in the past, which lives or does not live in the
hearts of the people) are more impassioned than the governing powers
of the colonial state. At least in our times they believe in the sanctity of their
cause more than their adversaries believe in the legitimacy of their domina¬
tion. Sixty years ago the Frenchman no more doubted France’s mission
civilisatrice than the Englishman questioned the “white man’s burden.” Today
the Frenchman doubts that he has the moral right to refuse the populations
of Africa and Asia a patrie (which cannot be France), even if this patrie is
only a dream, even if it should prove to be incapable of any authentic
independence.
This dissymmetry is confirmed by the change in the colonial balance-sheet.
To administer a territory today is to assume responsibility for its development.
Most often, this responsibility costs more than the enlarging of the market or
the exploitation of natural resources brings in. It is hardly surprising that the
conservative party eventually wearies of paying the price of pacification and of
investments for the benefit of the very populations that oppose it. A formally
total defeat (the rebel side has finally won the sovereignty it sought) is not
necessarily experienced as such by the ex-colonial power.
The apparent simplicity of the stake—independence or not—conceals the
complexity of the situation. If the independence of the protectorate or the
colony were considered by the imperial state as an absolute evil, an irremedi¬
able defeat, we should return to the elementary friend-enemy duality. The
nationalist—Tunisian, Moroccan, Algerian—would be the enemy, not occa¬
sional or even permanent, to use the terms defined above, but rather the
absolute enemy, the one with whom no reconciliation is possible, whose very
existence is an aggression, and who consequently must be exterminated.
Delenda est Carthago: the formula is that of absolute hostility, the hostility
of Rome and Carthage; one of the two cities is de trop. If Algeria were to
have remained definitively French, the nationalists seeking an independent
Algeria would have had to be pitilessly eliminated. If millions of Moslems
were to become French in the middle of the twentieth century, they
would have had to be prevented even from dreaming of an Algerian nation,
and made to forget the witnesses “w'ho got themselves murdered.”
Perhaps some Frenchmen would have preferred this to be the case: reality
is less logical, more human. The colonial power conceives of various ways to
retreat, whose consequences are not identical; some of these ways to retreat
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
35
are in the long run preferable to maintenance by force. The interests of the
metropolitan country will be more or less preserved depending on which
men wield power in the ex-colony, promoted to the rank of an independent
state. Henceforth the imperial power is not in conflict with a single, clearly
defined enemy, the nationalist; it must choose, delimit its enemy. In Indo-
China, Western strategy should and probably could have held the Communist
nationalist to be the enemy, hut not the nationalist who was hostile or simply
indifferent to communism. Such a decision would have implied that France
did not regard the independence of the Associated States as fundamentally
contrary to her interests. France would have had more opportunities of win¬
ning the war by separating Communists and nationalists, granting the latter’s
chief demands. But to the officers thinking in terms of empire, this so-called
rational strategy would have seemed sheer idiocy.
In “subversive” wars since 1945, the conservative power has consistently
been confronted by three kinds of adversaries: Communists, intransigent
nationalists, and moderate nationalists who would accept progressive steps and
sometimes be content with autonomy. Among the intransigents, some sought
and others rejected collaboration with the colonial state. Extremists in the
immediate present were sometimes moderates in the long run. Depending on
the circumstances and the final intentions of the conservative strategy, the
three groups constituted a common front, or drew apart. When the imperial
power renounced sovereignty, only the Communists and those nationalists
desiring a break with the West have remained enemies. King Mohammed V
and M. Bourguiba, the Istiqlal and the Neo-Destour, can be the sovereigns
or the parties of friendly states. Once again, yesterday’s enemy is today’s
friend. Politics cannot be reasonable without the capacity to forget.
The conviction has spread that the nationalist victory is written in advance
in the book of destiny, in accordance with historical determinism. For many
reasons the victory of Asian and African revolutionists over the European
empires has been assured. But on this level of formal analysis, one observation
appears necessary. The inequality of determination among the adversaries was
still more marked than the inequality of material forces. The dissymmetry of
will, of interest, of animosity in the belligerent dialogue of conservers and
rebels was the ultimate origin of what French authors call the defeats of the
West.
Is will alone enough to stop the nationalist movement? The circumstances
in Algeria were, in certain respects, comparable to those in Tunisia and
Morocco: here, too, French strategy hesitated over the definition of the
enemy, sometimes inclined to include all nationalists in it, sometimes, on the
contrary, to limit it to FLN militants, or even to FLN extremists. In Algeria,
too, French strategy has learned the difficulty of winning a military victory
that must be total to be uncontested, and is prohibited by the very nature of a
guerrilla army scattered in the djebels and supplied from abroad. But all
these classical arguments are opposed by another: the guerrilla forces have
THEORY
3 6
still less chance of defeating the regular army. If the men in power are willing
to spend hundreds of billions of francs a year as long as is necessary, if the
army finds the pursuit of partisans in accord with the normal exercise of the
military profession, if public opinion in the metropolitan nation abides by
this prolonged conflict and consents to the necessary sacrifices, the impossi¬
bility of winning appears—what it actually is—bilateral, as obvious for the
rebels as for the forces of order so much do the former’s losses exceed
the latter’s.
The French established in Algeria did not seem any less persistent than the
rebels, and they communicated their obstinacy to a portion of the French¬
men in metropolitan France. That this stubbornness could change the out¬
come was never likely. That it changed the aspect of events cannot be
doubted.
4. Conduct of Engagements and Strategy
Policy does not control merely the conception of the whole conflict. In
certain cases it also determines the conduct of a battle, the risks an army
leader must accept, the limits the strategists must establish for the tactician’s
initiatives.
Let us again consider examples to illustrate these formulas. The man who
commands an army or a fleet can no longer take “victory as the sole objective”
any more than the general in charge of a vast theater of operations. In the
famous battle of Jutland, the last in which whole squadrons confronted each
other without aircraft, Admiral Jellicoe never forgot for an instant that on
that day he could lose not just a battle but the war. On the other hand, there
was no need to destroy the German fleet in order to obtain the strategically
necessary result. He had to repulse the German fleet’s attempt to break the
blockade, and still preserve numerical superiority: simultaneously, the only
success necessary to final victory would be achieved. In short, to return to the
expressions employed above, the English fleet had won as soon as it had not
lost. The German fleet had lost by the very fact that it had not won. The
relation of forces was not modified: the Allies retained control of the seas.
In relation to the total strategic perspective, Admiral Jellicoe was right
not to pursue the German fleet to the point of exposing his own vessels to
submarine or torpedo attack. Of course, the destruction of the German fleet
would have added to the glory of the Royal Navy and scored a point against
German morale, reinforced the confidence of the Allies, and influenced public
opinion in the neutral states. But these advantages were marginal, secondary;
they were absurd in comparison with the jeopardy of the British fleet, which
was indispensable to control of the seas and therefore to the very existence
of the Western camp.
Further, this prudence was justified by subsequent events. The German
fleet exerted no further influence upon the course of hostilities. It had won
prestige because it had fought in an undecided battle, and achieved several
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
37
technical or tactical successes. But if the chief military leader sometimes takes
glory as his supreme objective, the subordinate military leader must not take
any objective other than one in accord with the plan of war.
In this case the subordination of local action to the strategic conception
is strictly military, without reference to politics. The same is not true of the
decision the German military leaders had to make apropos of unrestricted
submarine warfare. The memorandum written on this occasion by Max Weber
is an admirable illustration of the political-military calculation necessary un¬
der such circumstances.
The question was not so much one of knowing if unrestricted submarine
warfare—the destruction of merchant vessels without warning—was or was
not in accord with international law: as a matter of fact, it was contrary to
the rules admitted by the ranking powers before 1914, but Allied behavior
in the war at sea (long-distance blockade, camouflaged armament of cargo
ships) was not irreproachable either. On the level of strict rationality, the
first question was to discover whether the proclamation of unrestricted sub¬
marine warfare would provoke the United States to enter the war, or if Ameri¬
can intervention would at least be delayed in the absence of such a declara¬
tion.
Even supposing this declaration provoked American intervention, it might
still be rational if the submarines could insure an effective counterblockade,
preventing or delaying the transportation of a great American army to
Europe, and if the German army were in a position to win before the weight
of this still intact army made itself felt on the battlefields. None of these con¬
ditions was realized. The strategic decisions of the Hindenburg-Ludendorff
group—unrestricted submarine warfare, offensive on the western front, main¬
tenance of relatively important forces to hold eastern gains—were, if not
radically erroneous, at least exaggeratedly reckless. The leaders of the Central
Powers played their trump card, not hesitating to defy the United States
or to assume offensives which would precipitate irremediable defeat if they
did not produce total victory. Let us add, to keep the reader from losing his
sense of historical irony, that the American navy practiced what in 1917 was
called unrestricted submarine warfare from the first day of hostilities against
Japan.
The limitation of military operations as a function of political necessities,
objected to by American generals in Korea and French generals in Algeria,
is not in itself at all original. It is likely that the bombing of the Manchurian
airfields in 1951 or 1952 would not have provoked an extension of the
theater of operations or of the number of belligerents. But the bombing
would also not have modified the course of hostilities substantially, since the
Chinese Migs were not attacking the American positions and were not pre¬
venting the American bombers from completing their missions. Further, the
Chinese might have replied to the bombing of the Manchurian airfields
by bombing Korean ports, if not Japanese bases. The unwritten convention
THEORY
38
of this limited war involved reciprocal respect of "zones of refuge,” of
"sanctuaries” outside the theater in which the conflict of the two Koreas was
taking place, supported respectively by Chinese and American forces.
Somewhat different is the case of the French decision with regard to
Tunisia (between 1955 and 1962). Tunisia was theoretically neutral in a
conflict that, in terms of international law, was not a warJlSJ between the
FLN and French authorities in Algeria. As a matter of fact, Tunisia, on
whose territory the FLN stationed troops, did not behave as a neutral state:
it gave assistance to the rebels, an action contrary to the international custom
of the past hut in conformity with the practice of the present. Juridically and
morally France was entitled to reply at least by raids on the fellagha bases.
The point was to discover the consequences, costs and advantage of such raids.
Even a temporary invasion of Tunisia would probably have made the
departure of the "French colony” inevitable, and obliged M. Bourguiba’s
government to break off relations with France and seek support elsewhere. It
would have provoked the censure (whether justified or not is of little im¬
portance) of Afro-Asian public opinion and of an important share of Western
public opinion. These political disadvantages could have been justified only
by military advantages of incontestable scope. Yet in order to destroy the
FLN’s logistic bases in Tunisia effectively, it would have been necessary to
occupy the nation over an extended period (which the French general staff,
short of forces, was reluctant to do, aside from any political consideration). A
temporary occupation of Tunisia, with unforeseeable political countereffects,
would have had little effect on the fundamental circumstances of the Algerian
conflict.
This analysis aims less at proving a thesis than at recalling a general prop¬
osition. Rare in modern history are the circumstances in which the leaders
have been free to do everything they regarded as effective and useful on the
strictly military level. That generals must renounce certain actions out of
respect for international legality, for allies or neutrals, is the rule rather than
the exception.
Perhaps it would be helpful to consider a final example of a politico-
military decision condemned by the outcome, which ministers and generals
blame on each other: the decision to defend Laos, then to organize this
defense around the entrenched camp of Dien-Bien-Phu. The thesis of the
unfortunate general is that the decision to defend Laos against the Viet-minh
was taken by the "supreme commander,” in this case the government in
Paris. This decision, continues the defense, implied the establishment of an
entrenched camp at Dien-Bien-Phu, the only position from which Laos could
be defended. Once again, it is not our concern to analyze the case in detail,
i.e., to determine whether the camp at Dien-Bien-Phu constituted the only
possible application of the decision to defend Laos, whether this camp could
El Although a certain "belligerence” can be attributed to the FLN.
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
39
have been organized so that resistance had a chance of success, or whether
this camp, finally, despite appearances, fulfilled at least one of its functions,
to preserve the capital of Laos and to keep the strength of the Viet-minh
forces out of the Tonkin Delta.
Retrospectively, the polemic between government and military command
over Laos or Dien-Bien-Phu is of double interest because it touches on two
aspects of the relations between strategy and politics. It was, in fact, politically
important to protect Laos, the member of the Associated States whose leaders
and population were least hostile to France. The loss of Laos, secondary in
military terms, would have dealt a blow to French prestige throughout Indo-
China, publicly symbolizing the weakness of French arms. But it would be
wrong to conclude as a result that on this occasion political considerations
and military considerations were opposed. Anxiety over prestige and the sig¬
nificance of a territory in terms of morale are part of the political order but
do not constitute its entirety. In any circumstance, partial political arguments
can be opposed by partial military arguments. But the point here is not a
conflict between strategy and diplomacy, since arguments for and against a
certain decision occur just as often in the military as in the political order.
The mistake would be to confuse partial motives of a political order with
the political order itself, which is essentially defined by the total situation, by
the unifying overview of the intellect. “That policy unites in itself, and
reconciles all the interests of internal administrations, even those of humanity,
and whatever else are rational subjects of consideration is presupposed, for it
is nothing in itself, except a mere representative and exponent of all these in¬
terests towards other states.’^ What the commanders in Paris who were in
charge of waging this Far Eastern war lacked was a total view of the war
itself, of the interests they wished to safeguard, of the goals they thereby
proposed. After the Communist victory in continental China, could they still
hope to defeat the Viet-minh? In this hypothesis they entirely misjudged the
relation of forces. Did they want to maintain a French demi-authority in the
Associated States or else keep the latter outside the Viet-minh zone? If the
first alternative was correct, they were subordinating the essential goal-
limiting Communist expansion—to a secondary objective, the mode of rela¬
tions between France and the Associated States. Did they envisage direct
negotiation with the Viet-minh or a broadened negotiation with China, the
Soviet Union, and the Western powers? In such a strategic perspective, it
would have been possible to specify the necessary means and the pledges
to be kept at any price. Lacking this total perspective and defined objectives,
policy' falls into the error indicated by Clausewitz: “That policy makes de¬
mands on the War which it cannot respond to, would be contrary to the
supposition that it knows the instrument which it is going to use, therefore,
contrary to a natural and indispensable supposition.’lllJln Indo-China, to use
GUClausewitz, op. cif., VIII, 6, p. 124.
UMlbid., p. 125.
40
THEORY
Clausewitz’s terms again, it is not “the prejudicial influence of policy on the
conduct of a War” that was at fault, but policy itself. "It is only when policy
promises itself a wrong effect from certain military means and measures” that
it exerts a pernicious influence on war by insisting that it follow a certain
course. “Just as a person in a language with which he is not conversant some¬
times says what he does not intend, so policy, when intending right, may
often order things which do not tally with its own views.’ED
It is worse still when politics gives no orders or when a political leader and
a military command are each unaware of the other. In Indo-China the military
command determined the establishment of the entrenched camp at Dien-
Bien-Phu before the Geneva Conference, of whose outcome it was unaware.
The International Conference upset the basic conditions of the problem, in¬
cluding the military ones. It incited the Viet-minh to achieve at any price a
spectacular success on the eve of negotiations. It should have suggested ex¬
treme caution to the French general staff. The Viet-minh had to seek a
spectacular success, just as the French expeditionary force had to refuse it the
occasion for such a success at any cost.
5. Diplomacy and Military Means
Let us turn back to one of the Clausewitz formulas we have quoted:
policy must know the instrument it is to employ. This formula is no less
true in peacetime than in war. Until the Korean War, U.S. foreign policy
oscillated from one extreme to the other, obsessed by military victory ex¬
clusively in wartime, indifferent to military considerations in peacetime. Alexis
de Tocqueville had already noted this inclination to a double extremism
—few soldiers in peacetime, little diplomatic subtlety once the guns speak—
and had considered it the expression of the democratic spirit.
Rationality, in fact, dictates reflection on peace despite the uproar of the
melee, and on war when weapons are silent. The commerce of nations is
continuous; diplomacy and war are only complementary modalities, one or the
other dominating in turn, without one ever entirely giving way to the other
except in the extreme case either of absolute hostility, or of absolute friend¬
ship or total federation.
Military indifference, in peacetime, can take two forms: one is characteris¬
tic, in our times, of the United States, the other of France. The first consists
of taking armament potential for actual power, imagining that diplomatic
notes have the same force of conviction whether they are supported by
statistics of steel production or by fleets of battleships, aircraft carriers and
planes. From 1931 till the summer of 1940 the United States refused to
recognize the Japanese conquests and to oppose such ventures by force.
The second modality of diplomacy not in accord with strategy, the French
modality, is characterized by the contradiction between the war a nation has
H Ibid., pp. 126-27.
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
41
the military means to wage and the war diplomatic agreements eventually
oblige it to wage. Between 1919 and 1936 the occupation or disarmament
of the left bank of the Rhine permitted France to impose her will upon
Germany, provided she had the determination and the courage to use force.
As long as the French army held the Rhine bridgeheads, it had an almost
decisive advantage in case of conflict, being in a position from the first days
of hostility to strike at the heart of the Reich’s industrial arsenal. In this
military instance the alliances on the other side of Germany, with the new
nations created out of the decomposition of the Austro-Hungarian Empire,
supported not French security but French hegemony over Europe. With
Germany open to the west, girdled by hostile states to the east and the south,
France extended her power to the frontiers of the Soviet Union. But in
order to maintain this pre-eminence, she required an army capable of profiting
offensively from the demilitarization of the left bank of the Rhine and of
forbidding the Reichswehr to reoccupy this zone so vital in military terms.
At the crucial moment, in March 1936, the French Minister of War, like the
general staff, insisted on complete mobilization before agreeing to a military
response. France had no army of intervention and, by digging the Maginot
Line, had given evidence of a defensive military attitude which corresponded
to the spirit but not to the necessities of a conservative diplomacy: to main¬
tain the Versailles Treaty and the system of alliances in the Balkans and
Eastern Europe, France would have had to be capable of military initiatives
in order to prevent Germany’s violation of the treaty’s essential clauses.
Once the Rhineland was reoccupied by the Reichswehr and the latter
transformed into a mass army, French pledges to Czechoslovakia, Poland and
Rumania changed their meaning. France promised to oppose German aggres¬
sion by a war which could only be a long one, on the model of that of 1914-
18. In such a war the eastern allies represented additional forces, but even
this contribution was precarious since these nations, being vulnerable, risked
being submerged by the German tide more rapidly than Serbia and Rumania
had been swallowed up during the course of the preceding conflict. Further,
it was easy to point to the French pledges as involving the risk of a not in¬
evitable war. After all, wouldn’t Hitler be satisfied once he had reunited all
the Germans into a single Reich, in accordance with his ideology (ein Volk,
ein Reich, ein Fiikrer)?
A diplomacy which claims to act without an army in condition to fight, a
diplomacy which possesses an army incapable of the missions required by its
objectives, these two lapses of rationality are as attributable to the psychology
of the leaders and peoples as to intellectual error. Before the age of strategic
bombers and ballistic missiles, the United States had never had to fear any
neighbor state. It had to win space from the Indians (militias sufficed) and
from nature (what was the use of soldiers?). Power politics was an invention
of despotisms, one of the aspects of European corruption which had been left
behind. The refusal to recognize territorial changes made by force expressed
42,
THEORY
simultaneously a confused legal ideology, the desire not to wage war, and an
obscure confidence in the final triumph of morality over force.
The American disarmament of 1945 (“bring the boys bach”) was the last
episode of this traditional policy (or non-policy), the last symbol of the radi¬
cal break between war and peace. The war had to be won: all other business
was broken off, the job had been done, and done well. The moment had come
to return to civilian life, to industry, to commerce, to sport, to what concerns
the citizens of a free democracy once the wicked or the mad, the fascists or
the imperialists, have been rendered harmless.
The French rupture of politico-military unity also had a psychological
cause. The status created by the Versailles Treaty was artificial insofar as it
did not express the true relation of forces once Great Britain and the United
States declared their hostility to it or showed their indifference to it. If the
Soviet Union and a rearmed Germany united to destroy it, France, with only
her Continental allies, did not have the force to save it. Logically, this pre¬
cariousness of the European order after 1918 should have incited France to
exploit fully, and to conserve as long as possible, the advantages she owed to
the victor)' (Germany disarmed, the Rhineland defenseless). Rationality dic¬
tated an active defense supported by the threat of military actions (barring a
frank attempt to appease Weimar Germany^ by offering it satisfaction). But
the feeling of potential inferiority prevailed even though there still existed a
hegemony in fact. The military organization reflected the desire for security
and withdrawal, whereas diplomacy still accorded with hegemony.
The coordination of diplomacy and strategy assumes a new character after
1945 because of the multiplicity of combat techniques. Before the Atomic
Age, no one imagined using different weapons according to different cir¬
cumstances. Today, one does not conceive of using a thermonuclear bomb or
even a tactical atomic weapon without regard to the kind of war involved.
The nature of the conflict formerly determined the volume of the forces en¬
gaged and the degree of mobilization of forces, whether actual or potential.
Today it determines the type of weapons used.
From every evidence, the conduct of wars will be still more political than
in the past. It is no longer a question of granting the military leaders com¬
plete freedom to win the war, no matter how and at no matter what price.
The very notion of winning is probably no longer the same and, in any case,
the question of the cost, though it has always been asked, now becomes de¬
cisive: what good is it to destroy the enemy if the latter simultaneously de¬
stroys you?
Let us say, generalizing, that all of yesterday’s questions are still asked:
What share of the potential forces should be permanently mobilized? What
are the strategic eventualities in relation to which military preparation must
be organized? What are the missions policy is liable to assign the army in
IUfTh is theoretical possibility no longer existed after Hider’s accession to power.
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
43
various circumstances? But to these classical questions we must henceforth
add new questions: How many types of war, distinct according to the weap¬
ons used, must be conceived? For how many of these wars can a state prepare?
To what degree can the military systems that would see action under various
circumstances be administratively separate? Will the same troops intervene in
case of total war, of limited war with atomic weapons, of limited war with
conventional weapons? A national defense organization has always been the
expression of strategic doctrine, but the instruments of combat could be more
or less numerous, manipulated according to various methods: the military
leaders did not have to choose among panoplies. Henceforth the diversity of
panoplies is plainly evident.
At the same time, there reappears in another form a danger present a half-
century ago: diplomacy risks becoming a prisoner, at the crucial moment, of
military mechanisms which must be prepared in advance, which the govern¬
ment remains free to set off or not, but which it can no longer modify. Dur¬
ing the fatal week in July 1914 which preceded the outburst, on two occa¬
sions the general staffs—in Russia and Germany—explained to the sovereigns
and their advisers that a certain measure was technically impossible. The Tsar
desired partial mobilization against Austria, but such a mobilization had not
been foreseen; it would have upset all plans and precipitated chaos. Similarly,
the only strategy envisaged by the German general staff was that of a war on
two fronts with an initial offensive in the west. The Reich, too, could not
mobilize against Russia alone nor, after mobilization, remain with guns at
the ready: France would have to be attacked and beaten as quicldy as possi¬
ble, before Russia could engage the majority of her forces. At a moment when
destiny was still hesitating, the automatic military machinery geared to the
war plans was set in motion and men were swept on almost in spite of them¬
selves.
At present the strategy of deterrence requires that the machinery of retali¬
ation be established in advance. Is there a risk that this machinery might be
set off by mistake or that it might be set off according to plans established in
advance, whereas, for various reasons, the military leaders might hope to
modify these plans (partial retaliation and not massive retaliation)? Before
1914 the automatism was that of “administrative machinery,” of military
bureaucracies in charge of mobilization. In i960 the automatism to be feared
is as much that of electronic devices as of strategic plans. In 1914 statesmen
had several days in which to make a decision. In the 1960s they have only
several minutes.
It is too simple, actually, to allow for only two actors, oneself and the
enemy. Particularly in our times, medium-size states must orient themselves
not only in relation to an adverse coalition but also in relation to allies who
may desire the enemy’s defeat, but who may be hostile or indifferent to the
particular objectives of their comrades in arms. The United States or Great
Britain, between 1939 and 1945, were not under the obligation to save the
THEORY
44
French Empire. Even in the West, the states, united in the effort to defeat
the Third Reich, did not otherwise necessarily aim at the same goals.
Curiously, the most serious dissensions among the Americans and the
British were not provoked by real contradictions of interest. The United
States had as much to gain as Great Britain by limiting Soviet expansion,
preventing the Sovietization of Eastern Europe. The strategy of the Western
invasion, of attack against the enemy’s “fortress,” was dictated by strictly
military arguments. It is true that at the time Roosevelt and his advisers were
not so aware as American leaders today of the Western community and of
the irreducible hostility of the Soviet Union.
A different conception of the best way of winning is enough to make the
conduct of war by a coalition difficult. But the various ways of winning
rarely lead to the same results for all the partners. Logically, each state
desires to contribute to the victory, but without weakening itself in relation
to its allies. These rivalries fatally diminish the effectiveness of the coalition.
The duality of considerations—defense of one’s own interests and con¬
tribution to the common cause—combines with the polymorphism of wars to
create the present circumstances of the Atlantic Alliance. The generally
valid rule for conduct to follow in a coalition is to concentrate forces in the
terrain where the nation’s particular interests are most important. In this
regard, the Indo-Chinese war, even interpreted as one of the fronts of resis¬
tance to communism, was an error on France’s part which involved a con¬
siderable portion of her total resources in a theater secondary for herself
as well as for the West.
More justifiable, in this regard, was the transfer to Algeria of the major
part of the French army. Of course, the coalition was weakened by this, and
the NATO shield became too thin. Insofar as they did not regard Algerian
nationalism as a threat, the other Western powers were inclined to criticize
France both because she did not furnish the contribution she had promised
to the Atlantic forces, and because she compromised relations between the
West and the Islamic world. Even if these reproaches were well-founded
from the point of view of the Alliance, the French decision was not neces¬
sarily erroneous. The weakening of the Atlantic forces did not noticeably
increase the danger of war in Europe; the transfer of the French divisions
afforded an opportunity of preserving sovereignty south of the Mediterra¬
nean. If this sovereignty had a vital importance, it would have justified the
engagement of the majority of French forces in Algeria, even if this action
displeased other members of the Alliance.
The danger is that all the allies, repeating the same rationale—I am doing
little disservice to the common interest but I am doing great service to my
own—might end by aiding the enemy’s victory. The neutral state, desiring
the victory of one camp but judging that the sacrifices required by its inter¬
vention would be considerable without adding substantially to the likeli¬
hood of victory, is correct—provided it does not set an example. Ultimately
STRATEGY AND DIPLOMACY
45
there would remain only a single state to assume the burden of indispensable
action. Furthermore, the leader of the coalition is the only one inclined to
identify the coalition’s interests with his own.
The choice, by each ally, of his contribution to the Alliance has been
rendered still more difficult in recent years by the alternative of conventional
weapons and atomic weapons. Yesterday Great Britain, today France wish to
enter the atomic club: what role will be left for conventional weapons if
atomic arms and delivery systems obtain their due? The very meaning of the
choice remains equivocal: will atomic weapons protect France from possible
aggression or possible Soviet blackmail, or will they reinforce France’s posi¬
tion within the Alliance?
The unity of policy, including both war and peace, diplomacy and strategy,
bars the total solidarity of allies. Only a miracle would insure the coinci¬
dence of all the interests of all the states within the coalition. The force of a
coalition is always less than the sum of the forces it possesses on paper.
The primacy of policy is a theoretical proposition, not a plan of action.
But this theoretical proposition is of a nature to do more good than harm, if
the reduction of violence is regarded as desirable.
The primacy of policy, in fact, permits the control of escalation, the
avoidance of an explosion of animosity into passionate and unrestricted bru¬
tality. The more the leaders calculate in terms of cost and profit and the
less they are inclined to relinquish the pen for the sword, the more they will
hesitate to abandon themselves to the risk of arms, the more they will be
content to limit their successes and renounce the intoxication of dazzling vic¬
tories. The reasonable conduct of politics is the only rational one if the goal
of the intercourse among states is the survival of all, common prosperity, and
the sparing of the peoples’ blood.
Of course, the subordination of war to policy has not meant, in fact, the
pacification of this intercourse. The nature of war depends on the total his¬
torical circumstances. “If policy is grand and powerful, so also will be the
War, and this may be carried to the point at which War attains to its
absolute formS^k But if war is in the image of policy, if it varies as a
function of the stake the latter determines, pacification ceases to be incon¬
ceivable. Calculation can make evident to princes that the cost of the war
will in any case be superior to the profits of victory.
Yet this calculation must convince all the participants. Otherwise it would
serve no purpose and by provoking inequality of determination would even
risk precipitating the very thing it was attempting to avoid. At this level
the principle of polarity reappears: a limited war does not depend upon only
one of the belligerents. “If . . . one of two belligerents is determined to
seek the great decision by arms, then he has a high probability of success, as
soon as he is certain his opponent will not take that way, but follows a dif-
[l^Clausewitz, op. cit., VIII, 6, p. 123.
THEORY
46
ferent object.® The theory of war, in the Atomic Age, would be easier but
for the fact that the conduct of one actor is at every moment subject to the
other’s reaction. No dialogue, peaceful or warlike, can remain reasonable if
all participants do not consent to it.
[13 Ibid., I, 2, p. 42.
chapter 11
Power and Force
or
On the Means of Foreign Policy
Few concepts are as frequently used and as equivocal as those of power
( puissance, Macht). In English the phrase power politics, in German the
expression Macht Poiitik, is spoken with an accent of criticism or resignation,
of horror or admiration. In French the expression politique de puissance
sounds as if it were translated from a foreign language. Few French authors
have glorified the politique de puissance as the German doctrinaires have
extolled Macht Poiitik, and few French authors have condemned the politique
de puissance in the way American moralists have condemned power politics.
In a general sense, power is the capacity to do, make or destroy. An ex¬
plosive has a measurable power, as does the tide, the wind or an earthquake.
The power of a person or of a collectivity is not strictly measurable, because
of the diversity of the goals chosen and the means employed. The fact that
fundamentally men apply their power to their fellow creatures gives the
concept its true political significance. An individual’s power is his capacity to
act, but above all to influence the actions or feelings of other individuals.
On the international scene I should define power as the capacity of a political
unit to impose its will upon other units. In short, political power is not an
absolute; it is a human relationship.
This definition suggests several distinctions: between defensive power (or
the capacity of a political unit to keep the will of others from being im¬
posed upon it) and offensive power (or the capacity of a political unit to
impose its will upon others); between the resources or military force of a
collectivity, which can be evaluated objectively, and its power, which, being
a human relationship, does not depend on material or instruments alone;
between the politics of force and the politics of power. All international
politics involves a constant collision of wills, since it consists of relations
among sovereign states which claim to rule themselves independently. So
long as these units are not subject to external law or to an arbiter, they are,
THEORY
48
as such, rivals, for each is affected by the actions of the others and inevitably
suspects their intentions. But these interacting wills do not necessarily set
up a potential or real military rivalry. Relations among political units are
not always bellicose, and peaceful relations are influenced, but not deter¬
mined, by past or future military accomplishments.
1. Force and the Tivo Kinds of Power
French, English and German all distinguish between two notions, power
and force (strength), puissance et force, Macht und Kraft. It does not seem
to me contrary to the spirit of these languages to reserve the first term for
the human relationship, the action itself, and the second for the means, the
individual’s muscles or the state’s weapons.
In the physical sense a man is strong if his weight or muscles afford
him the means of resisting or mastering other men. But such strength is
nothing without ingenuity, resolution, nerve. Similarly we propose, apropos
of collectivities, to distinguish between military, economic and even moral
forces, and power, which is the functioning of these forces in given circum¬
stances and with a view to particular goals. The forces being susceptible to
an approximate evaluation, power can be estimated, with an extended mar¬
gin for error, by reference to the forces available. But there is such a broad
distinction possible between defensive and offensive power, between war¬
time and peacetime power, between power within a certain geographical zone
and power beyond this zone, that the measurement of a power taken as
absolute and intrinsic seems to me to do more harm than good. It does harm
to the statesman who supposes himself in possession of specific information,
whereas he possesses merely a deceptively rigorous measurement of a re¬
sultant, of equivocal meaning. It does harm to the political scientist who
substitutes for the relation of states—i.e., for human collectivities—the con¬
frontation of masses, thereby depriving the object of study of its true mean¬
ing.
The notion of force, in its turn, requires distinctions. At least until the
advent of the Atomic Age the end and essence of war was combat. The en¬
gagement of soldiers, whatever the distance between the lines imposed by
the evolution of weapons, remained the supreme test, comparable to the
cash payment in which any credit operations ultimately conclude. On the
day of the denouement, that is, of the engagement, only the forces actually
mobilized influenced the outcome—the raw materials transformed into can¬
nons and shells, the citizens trained for combat. "The conduct of War is
not making powder and cannon out of a given quantity of charcoal, sulphur,
and saltpetre, of copper and tin: the given quantities for the conduct of War
are arms in a finished state and their effects.’H
Let us call potential force the total human, material and moral resources
Hciausewitz, op. cit., II, 2, p. 113.
POWER AND FORCE
49
which each unit possesses on paper, and let us call actual force those of its
resources that are mobilized for the conduct of international relations in war¬
time or peacetime. In wartime, actual force is close to military force (with¬
out entirely coinciding with it, since the course of operations is, in part,
determined by non-military forms of conflict). In peacetime, actual force is
not to be confused with military force since the divisions, fleets and air¬
planes in being but not utilized are only one of the instruments in the
service of foreign policy.
Between potential force and actual force the factor of mobilization inter¬
venes. The force available to each political unit in its rivalry with others is
proportional not to its potential but to its potential of mobilization. The lat¬
ter, in its turn, depends on many factors which can be reduced to two ab¬
stract terms: capacity and will. The conditions of economic or administrative
capacity, and of collective will as affirmed by the leaders and supported by
the masses, are not constant throughout history; they vary from period to
period.
Is the power of the leaders (the men in power ) of the same nature as
the power of political units?
The link between the two notionJl— power within the political unit
(pouvoir ) and the power of the political unit itself (puissance)— is easily
perceived. The political unit defines itself through opposition: it becomes
itself by becoming capable of external action. Yet it can act as a political
unit only by the intermediary of one or of several men. Those who come to
power (to translate literally the German expression an die Macht koinmen)
are the guides, the representatives of the political unit in relation to the out¬
side world. But they are thereby responsible for mobilizing the unit’s forces
in order to permit its survival in the jungle where “cold monsters” disport
themselves. In other words, when international relations have not emerged
from the state of nature, the men in power, that is, those responsible for
the nation in relation to the outside world, are at the same time men of
power, possessors of an extended capacity to influence the conduct of their
fellow men and the very existence of the collectivity.
This analysis does not lead us to confuse the two kinds of power, pouvoir
and puissance. The statesman’s action does not have the same meaning, is
not situated within the same universe, but differs according to whether the
action is internally or externally oriented. Whether the sovereign is a heredi¬
tary monarch or the head of a party, whether he relies upon birth or elec¬
tion, he wishes to be legitimate; the readiness with which he is obeyed de¬
pends on how widely his legitimacy is recognized. The conditions under
which any man becomes a sovereign tend to be codified, like the methods
according to which the sovereign must command. The choice of the chief
of state and the means by which his command is exercised are increasingly
HlDesignated by the same word in English (power) and in German (Macht).
5 °
THEORY
institutionalized. In modem societies, this institutionalization assumes a legal
character, expressed in abstract formulas. But in every period, the distinc¬
tion is at least implicit between the orders of a conqueror and those of a
legitimate sovereign. Initially, at least, the conqueror employs or invokes
pure force, while the sovereign desires to be the interpreter of the collectivity
itself and conform to the tradition or the law that has fixed the rules of
succession for the leaders, according to the decree of fortune or popular
sentiment.
Yet the confusion of the two kinds of power cannot be explained only by
the role played by the possessors of power on the international scene. These
latter are often, originally, men of •power who have succeeded. Political units,
constitutional regimes all owe their origin to violence. French school children
are taught that in a thousand years the kings made France. The authors of
our textbooks have never appeared to be embarrassed by the evocation of
the wars against barons or foreign states by which the kings achieved na¬
tional unification, or by the recollection of the violence with which the revo¬
lutionaries overthrew the monarchs in 1789, in 1830 and in 1848. Even in
1958 the vote of the National Assembly camouflaged the new regime’s il¬
legality more than it set the seal of legality on its accession. The threat of
violence—the landing of parachutists—was also a form of violence.
It is only a step from these incontestable facts to the so-called realist in¬
terpretation, of which Pareto’s sociology is the expression. In this view, the
struggle for power within the collectivity Qpouvoir) is equivalent to the
rivalry of powers Qpuissemce'), the active minorities being in each instance
the actors in this rivalry. The legalization of power does not change the
significance of the phenomenon: the ruling classes oppose each other as the
political units do, and the victorious class exercises its power in the same
manner in which the conqueror rules.
Such an interpretation, to my way of thinking, falsifies the meaning of
politics^ which is a search for an equitable order, and at the same time a
conflict among individuals or groups over positions of command and the
sharing of scarce goods. But it remains true that the struggle for power
and its exercise within collectivities preserves certain features common to
the rivalry for power among autonomous units.
He who commands by virtue of law actually possesses more or less power—
that is, capacity to impose his will—according to the ascendancy he assumes
over his comrades, his partners, his rivals or his subordinates, according to
the prestige he enjoys among the minority and the majority. Yet this power,
whether in relation to the government or pressure groups, is never precisely
defined by the legal distribution of privileges or prerogatives. The degree of
influence which individuals or groups actually possess, the share each has
in the state decisions which concern either relations with foreign states or
GDConsidered as a particular system within the social totality.
POWER AND FORCE
5 *
relations among the parts of the collectivity, depend on the means of action
at the disposal of each, and at the same time on the talent each manifests
in the use of these means. A constitution excludes open violence; it sketches
a framework within which it specifies the rules by which the struggle for
power must abide. It does not suppress the element of “rivalry for power.”
The actors in the internal political drama, too, are animated by a desire
for power and at the same time by ideological convictions. Those in power
satisfy their ambitions, rarely free of all personal concern, even when con¬
vinced that they are serving the collectivity. The terms of a constitution,
the official practices of parliaments, of administrations, of governments, still
do not afford us exact knowledge of the real distribution of power within a
country. What is the capacity of men of wealth, men of party, men of ideas
or men of intrigue to convince or constrain the governors, to purchase the
cooperation of the press or the administration, to provoke disinterested
loyalty, to transform the opinions of the elite or of the crowd? There is no
general answer to such a question. What is true is that it would be naive to
be influenced by the letter of a constitution or legal proceedings alone. But
it would be cynical, without being true, to regard a constitution as a mere
fiction and the legal wielders of authority as mere figureheads or mouth¬
pieces. There is no example to warrant the assumption that the rules of the
game do not influence the opportunities of the players, or that the legal
incumbents consent to do the will of others (even of those to whom they
owe their accession to office).
Thereby both the similarity and difference between the conduct of "in¬
ternal politics” and the conduct of “foreign affairs” are apparent, as well as
the reasons for which the theory of the one diverges from that of the other,
at least on first analysis. The theory of international relations is entitled to
take for granted the participants—the political units—as well as the absence
of an arbitrator or laws, and the reference to war as a possibility (hence
the calculation of forces, without which the conduct of a participant threat¬
ened with aggression would not be rational). On the other hand, political
theory is ambivalent, in that the fundamental concepts are not beyond the
reach of controversy. To reduce the uncertainty to its basic components, we
may perhaps think of politics in terms of permanent competition (who gets
what? how? when?); in terms of the need for a peaceful order at any price
(civil war is the supreme evil, any kind of order is preferable to it); in
terms of a search for the best order; finally, in terms of the reconciliation of
complementary and divergent aspirations (equality and hierarchy, authority
and reciprocal recognition, etc.).
States recognizing each other’s sovereignty and equality have, by definition,
no authority over each other. Statesmen controlling administration, army
and police are at the apex of a legal hierarchy. The distinction between the
two kinds of behavior, diplomatic-strategic and political, seems to me essen-
THEORY
5 ^
rial, even if the similarities are many. Power on the international scene
differs from power on the national scene because it does not use the same
means, nor function over the same terrain.
2. The Elements of Power
Many authors have enumerated the elements of either power or force with¬
out specifying whether they were discussing military strength or total capac¬
ity for action—whether they were referring to peacetime or to wartime.
Lacking these distinctions, the enumerations seem arbitrary, heterogeneous,
none complete or incontestable.
For instance, the American geographer N. J. Spykmar 0 enumerates the
following ten factors: r. surface of the territory; 2. nature of the frontiers;
3. size of the population; 4. absence or presence of raw materials; 5. eco¬
nomic and technological developments; 6. financial power; 7. the ethnic
homogeneity; 8. degree of social integration; 9. political stability; 10. na¬
tional morale.
Professor H. J. Morgenthai® lists eight: 1. geography; 2. natural re¬
sources; 3. industrial capacity; 4. state of military preparedness; 5. population;
6. national character; 7. national morale; 8. quality of diplomacy.
Rudolph Steinmet® also lists eight: 1. population; 2. dimensions of the
territory; 3. wealth; 4. political institutions; 5. quality of the command; 6.
national unity and cohesion; 7. respect accorded to and friendship with
foreign powers; 8. moral qualities.
Lastly, Guido Fischer, a German au thorP on the eve of the second major
war of the twentieth century, classified the elements of power in three cate¬
gories:
r. Political factors: geographical position, dimensions of the state, size
and density of the population, skill of organization and cultural level, types
of frontiers and attitudes of neighboring countries.
2. Psychological factors: economic flexibility and skill in invention, per¬
severance, and capacity for adaptation.
3. Economic factors: fertility of the soil and mineral wealth, industrial
organization and technological level, development of trade and commerce,
financial resources.
All these attempts at classification resemble each other, save for the last.
All include geographical data (territory) and material data (raw materials),
economic data and technological data, and lastly human data such as po-
B America’s Strategy in World Politics, Yale University of International Studies, 1942,
ri * 9 .\
UuPolitics among Nations, New York, 1949, p. 80.
GDSozioIogie des Krieges (2nd ed.), Berlin, 1929, pp. 227-60.
0 Der wekrurirtschaftliche Bedarf, Zeitschrift fur die gesamte Staatswissenschaft, Vol.
IC ( 1939 ), P- 519 -
POWER AND FORCE
53
litical organization, the moral unity of the people, and the quality of lead¬
ership. Doubtless all these elements influence in one way or another the
potential or actual strength of political units. But none of these lists seems
to me to meet the requirements that theory is entitled to prescribe.
The elements listed must be homogeneous— in other words, they must be
situated on the same level of generality in relation to history: the number
of men, the characteristics of the territory, the quality of arms or organization
influence the force of nations in all periods; financial resources signified
nothing for the Mongol conquerors and very little for Alexander.
The list must be complete, which implies that the elements must be ex¬
pressed by concepts which cover the concrete diversity of phenomena, vari¬
able from period to period. Even the military implications of a geographical
situation can be modified by the techniques of transportation and combat,
but the influence of the geographical situation upon the possibilities of ac¬
tion of the political units is a constant factor.
Lastly, the classification should he such as to permit us to comprehend why
the factors of power are not the smne from century to century and why the
measure of power is, in essence, approximate. This last remark is both ob¬
vious and, in relation to an abundant literature, paradoxical. Reading the
theoreticians one would often suppose they have an infallible scale for
measuring the power of political units with great precision. If such measure¬
ment were possible, wars would not occur, since the results would be
known in advance. Or, at least, wars could be accounted for only by human
folly. There is no war at sea, Anatole France writes in Penguin Island, since
the hierarchy of fleets is never subject to doubt. All armies being the Greatest
in the World, only trial by combat establishes the true hierarchy.
Let us turn once again to Clausewitz. No one has emphasized more than
this rationalist theoretician the part chance plays in war. “War is the prov¬
ince of chance. In no sphere of human activity is such a margin to be left
for this intruder, because none is so much in constant contact with him on
all sides. He increases the uncertainty of every circumstance, and deranges
the course of events.® “The diversity, and undefined limits, of all the cir¬
cumstances bring a great number of factors into consideration in War, [and]
most of these factors can only be estimated according to probability. ... In
this sense, Bonaparte was right when he said that many of the questions
which come before a General for decision would make problems for a
mathematical calculation not unworthy of the powers of Newton or Euler.®
And lastly: “The great uncertainty of all data in War is a peculiar difficulty,
because all action must, to a certain extent, be planned in a mere twilight,
which in addition not unfrequently—like the effect of a fog or moonshine-
gives to things exaggerated dimensions and an unnatural appearance. What
this feeble light leaves indistinct to the sight talent must discover, or must
Sdausewitz op. ext., I, 3, p. 49.
\y\lbid., p. 69.
THEORY
54
be left to chance.^i^By resorting to war, policy surrenders to a high degree
of uncertainty, “it troubles itself little about final possibilities, confining its
attention to immediate probabilities.” Of course, “each Cabinet places its
confidence in the belief that in this game it will surpass its neighbor in
skill and sharpsightedness.’d But its confidence is not always confirmed by
the event.
Can we imagine that a theoretician of power could eliminate war’s un¬
certainty by adding up the weight of various elements, and announce in
advance the result of the combat? Now the power or capacity of a collec¬
tivity to impose its will upon another should not be confused with its military
capacity. But if the outcome of battle is uncertain, it is because military
force cannot be measured exactly, and total power still less than military
force.
I propose to distinguish three fundamental elements: first of all the space
occupied by the political units; second the available materials and the tech¬
niques by which they can be transformed into weapons, the number of men
and the art of transforming them into soldiers (or, again, the quantity and
quality of implements and combatants ); and last the collective capacity for
action, which includes the organization of the army, the discipline of the
combatants, the quality of the civil and military command, in w'ar and in
peace, and the solidarity of the citizens during the conflict in the face of
good or bad luck. These three terms, in their abstract expression, account
for the total situation, since they are equivalent to the proposition: the
power of a collectivity depends on the theater of its action and on its
capacity to use available material and human resources. Milieu, resources,
collective action, such are, from every evidence, whatever the century and
whatever the forms of competition among political units, the determinants
of power.
These three terms are equally valid for the analysis of power on all
levels, from the tactical level of small units to the strategic level on which
armies of millions of men confront each other, and to the diplomatic level
on which states continuously compete. The power of a French army com¬
pany confronting an FLN company depends on the terrain, the troops, the
weapons, and lastly on the discipline and command of the two companies.
On the superior level of strategy or politics, the capacity to organize the
army, to mobilize civilians, to train soldiers is, so to speak, integral with the
military strength and seems to appertain to the second term, while the
conduct of the military leaders, their strategic and diplomatic talent, and
the resolve of the people alone seem to represent the third.
This enumeration suggests not so much universally valid propositions as
the means of accounting for historical changes. Only the first term partially
escapes the vicissitudes of the techniques of production and destruction.
53 Ibid., II, 2, p. 105.
nn ibid., vm, 6 , p. 122.
POWER AND FORCE
55
Certain situations favor defensive powerful in other words, put obstacles
in the conqueror’s way: mountains, rivers, deserts and distances. Most often,
the same terrain that offers relative protection to a collectivity thereby reduces
its possibilities of external intervention. “Small states’® regard as heaven¬
sent the barriers created by nature, since they do not claim starring roles
and are uninterested in offensive power. Yet the defensiv^^l power of a
collectivity is a function of the characteristics of the space it occupies.
Mountains account for Switzerland’s exceptional capacity for wartime
defense, while distance has kept Russia from being entirely occupied ever
since the dukes of Moscow first shook off the Mongol yoke. Napoleon could
not overcome the resistance of the Tsar and the muzhiks, nor could Hitler,
despite more brilliant successes, the Communist state and its people. The
capture of Moscow did not weaken Tsar Alexander’s resolve; Hitler did not
take Moscow. Even in 1941-42 Russia owed her salvation to geography and to
the inadequacies of modernization (the mediocre road system), as well as to
the factories that were built before the conflict or transferred to the Urals.
The state with great ambitions must be assured of its own territorial bar¬
riers while retaining possibilities of intervention outside itself. Until re¬
cently, distance deprived Tsarist and Soviet Russia of a large part of her
offensive capacity, while it added to her defensive capacity. For centuries
England’s territory, though far enough from the Continent to make in¬
vasion difficult, constituted an ideal base for distant expeditions or even for
sending expeditionary forces to the Continent. Neither Venice nor Hol¬
land possessed a territorial base enjoying such security. France was obliged
to distribute her resources between army and navy and suffered a particular
vulnerability because of the relative proximity of her capital to the open
northern frontier.
None of these three terms, not even the first, space, is exempt from history.
It still remains true that a terrain difficult of access increases the political
unit’s defensive capacity and diminishes its offensive capacity. Because of the
mountains, the populations living in Algeria could resist modem French pac¬
ification as well as they resisted Roman pacification seventeen centuries ago.
But depending on the techniques of war, England is vulnerable or invulner¬
able, the Dover Straits are a knot of strategic routes or an insignificant nar¬
rowing between two seas equally closed, land and air offering other practicable
means of communication.
HHThere are two aspects of defensive power: in wartime it is the capacity to stop the
invader; in peacetime it depends on this capacity and also on the cohesion of the unit,
lid We avoid here the common ejrpression “small powers,” so as not to introduce a
confusion in vocabulary. The use of the word power to designate the actors and not
merely the capacity of the actors is self-explanatory. The rivalry of power being part
and parcel of international life, we identify the actors and their capacity for action,
and establish a hierarchy of actors as a function of their capacity,
ill Military.
THEORY
56
Applied to the other two terms, most general propositions would be of
little or no interest. It might be said that all other things being equal, number
triumphs on the diplomatic field as on the battlefield. But all other things
never being equal, this proposition teaches us nothing. We might regard as
significant the order of the three elements, the effectiveness of weapons, col¬
lective action, number of soldiers: extreme inequality in weapons cannot be
offset by either discipline or number of soldiers. Extreme inequality in or¬
ganization and discipline cannot be offset by number (the principle of the
Romans’ superiority over the barbarians, of regular armies over militias and
mass risings). But it would be desirable—and it is impossible—to specify the
degree of inequality which cannot be compensated. Unindustrialized peoples
have found, in the twentieth century, a means of combat, guerrilla warfare,
which permits them to protect themselves against peoples equipped with
every modern weapon. Even in the conflict between political units, if one
possesses an overwhelming technical superiority, ingenuity and resolution can
inspire the weaker unit with the secret of a lasting if not victorious resistance.
The historical or sociological analysis of the elements of the total force of
the units involved has two principal stages: first, to establish what the ele¬
ments of military strength are. In each period a system of combat proves
effective through a combination of certain weapons, a certain organization,
and an adequate quantity of weapons and combatants.
The second stage of the analysis concerns the relations between military
strength and the collectivity itself. To what degree is superiority in arms and
organization the expression of a technical and social superiority (supposing
that the latter two kinds of superiority can be determined objectively)? An
army is always a social organization, the expression of the entire collectivity.
The degree of mobilization—that is, the proportion of fighting men actually
mobilized—depends on the structure of the society, the number of citizens in
relation to non-citizens (if only citizens are accorded the honor of bearing
arms), the number of nobles if the society in question is one in which par¬
ticipation in combat is forbidden to commoners.
In all societies and at all periods there has been a limit to mobilization:
enough men must be left at work in order to produce the resources indis¬
pensable to the life of the collectivity (the theoretical degree of mobilization
rises if there is a peasant overpopulation, if the same harvest can be obtained
with a reduced number of workers). But the actual degree has rarely reached
or even approached the theoretical degree, the extent of mobilization being
determined by social circumstances, the traditional means of combat, or the
fear of giving weapons to a portion of the population regarded as inferior or
potentially hostile.
Insofar as the organization of the army and the means of combat resulted
from custom, it is understandable that the superiority of an army or of a
weapon could be extended for decades, even for centuries. The minority that
held a monopoly of weapons within the collectivity was in a position to main-
POWER AND FORCE
57
tain its rule almost indefinitely—unless it grew corrupt, that is, lost its co¬
hesion and its determination. The political unit that perfected an effective
combination of various weapons (light and heavy cavalry, light and heavy
infantry, impact weapons and projectiles, lance and armor, etc.), had a chance
of maintaining its superiority for a long time. It was tempting to attribute to
virtue the greatness of the imperial peoples and to regard their superiority of
weapons as proof of a total superiority of customs and culture.
Without proceeding to a detailed study, it is clear that the ratio between
the collectivity’s resources and military strength becomes stricter as war itself
becomes more rationalized, and the mobilization of civilians and the means of
production are considered normal and are put into practice. It is in the twenti¬
eth century that we have had the misleading illusion that by measuring re¬
sources we are measuring military strength and power itself. It is true that
in the age of total mobilization the military system is inevitably related to the
mass of the collectivity. But the virtue of the minority can still incline the
balance to one side or the other, and in many ways quality limits the domi¬
nation of quantity. The conquest of vast empires by a leader and his comrades
belongs to the past, EE or at least the small troop must begin by conquering
its own country, which will serve as a base. But one must have a weakness
for historical analogies to identify the adventures of Genghis Khan with those
of Lenin and the Bolshevik party. Genghis Khan was chiefly a military
genius, Lenin primarily a political genius. One mustered his armies by im¬
posing himself as their leader and eliminating his rivals, the other was origi¬
nally a prophet without arms; he avoided forceful means by using the tech¬
niques of persuasion.
3. Power in Peacetime and in Wartime
The power of a political unit in peacetime can be analyzed by using the
same categories—geographical milieu, resources, capacity for action—but
whereas power in wartime depends primarily on military strength and the use
made of it, power in peacetime—that is, the ability to keep others from im¬
posing their will on the unit in question or to impose that unit’s will upon
others—also depends on the various means whose use is admitted as legitimate
by international custom in each period. Instead of considering the military
system, we must consider the non-violent means (or the violent means toler¬
ated in peacetime). As for the capacity for collective action, it is expressed
aggressively by the art of convincing or constraining without recourse to
force, and defensively by the art of not letting oneself be deceived, terrified,
upset or divided.
Between "power in peacetime” and “power in wartime,” Europe’s tradi¬
tional diplomacy assumed a vague relationship. The political units considered
El Even in die twentieth century Ibn Saud relied on swordsmanship in his struggle to
unify the Arab tribes.
THEORY
5 8
to be the great powers were defined, above all, by the volume of their re¬
sources (territories and populations) and their military strength. Prussia in
the eighteenth century, Japan at the beginning of the twentieth, were re¬
ceived on a basis of equality by the club of the great powers because they had
proved themselves on the battlefield.
The status of great nation confers certain rights: no matter of importance
can be treated in a system without all the great nations being consulted.
When one great nation had obtained or extorted an advantage somewhere, the
others, whether partners or rivals, insisted on their right to he compensated.
The status of great power was advantageous insofar as peaceful exchanges
and negotiated agreements tended to reflect the relation of forces (supposed
rather than real). A small nation was inclined to yield to a great one because
the latter was stronger. The great nation, when isolated in a conference,
yielded to the will of a coalition whose combined potential was greater than
its own. Nations referred to force in order to conclude a suit peacefully, be¬
cause this reference seemed to offer a relatively objective criterion and was
a substitute for the test of weapons, whose issue was imagined to be deter¬
mined in advance by the relation of forces. Gradually, and especially since
the Second World War, this policed intercourse, this wise Machiavellianism,
has vanished.
Between the two wars, diplomats committed such errors—overestimating
Italy’s strength to the point of absurdity, underestimating the power of Soviet
Russia—that the very notion of a "great power” has now become suspect. The
great powers of yesterday’s Europe, Great Britain and France, seek to remain
the great powers of global diplomacy, and their claims appear to be ratified by
a permanent seat on the Security Council of the United Nations. But the
real status of these great powers is in reality so uncertain that such official
status scarcely affords them any prestige or advantage. Atomic weapons dis¬
credit the traditional concepts: weapons become less usable as they become
more monstrous. The politeness and cynicism of good society have vanished
from the chancelleries. Diplomacy, in the traditional sense of the term, func¬
tions up to a certain point among allies, but hardly any longer among enemies,
or even between the blocs and the neutral nations. Lastly and above all, no
nation, small or great, considers itself obliged to yield to a nation stronger
than itself once the stronger nation is not in a position to use its strength
effectively. The tactic of the “challenge” ("you won’t dare to force me”) ap¬
pears in the ordinary process of international relations® As a matter of fact,
states permanently practice a kind of total diplomacy which involves the use
of economic, political and psychological procedures, of violent and semi-
violent means.
To constrain a state or convince it to yield, another state or coalition of
unit also includes “misfires.” Used by M. Bourguiba in July 1961, this tactic pro¬
voked a violent reply on the part of the French troops.
POWER AND FORCB
59
states may resort to economic pressure. By the decision of the League of Na¬
tions, sanctions were decreed against Italy: a prohibition against buying and
selling certain merchandise. This pseudo-blockade was ineffectual because it
was not general. Italy found enough customers to carry out her vital minimum
of foreign trade. The prohibition against selling to her was not extended to
materials whose scarcity might have dealt her a mortal blow. The blockade by
which the Soviet bloc attempted to liquidate the Yugoslav dissidence was not
any more effective, the West having come to the support of the state whose
very existence bore witness to the possible separation between the Marxist
regime and the adherents to the Soviet camp. The United States, in its turn,
vainly attempted to destroy Fidel Castro by blockade.
Yet economic means are not always ineffective. The examples just given
have a particular character: they all involve, in effect, an attempt at eco¬
nomic constraint or even the utilization of economic means as substitutes for
military means. The failure is significant, but it has as its cause the impossi¬
bility of a universal coalition against a state. The weapon of the blockade
could be, in our age, irresistible; however, it would require that the “criminal”
state find no external allies. Up to now, such a hypothetical situation has
never been realized.
On the other hand, in bilateral relations, economic means are useful, even
indispensable, to reaffirm a friendship or cement a coalition. The Marshall
Plan led to the Atlantic Alliance. The state that buys a great deal from others
is in a position to influence the states of which it is the chief customer (the
collapse of the market for raw materials is a catastrophe for the state which
derives the greatest share of its trade resources from exporting this product).
A state is also capable of influencing those states that expect financial aid
from it or that feel dependent on its economic system. Today, particularly,
the consent of the so-called underdeveloped nations to remain within a
political circuit is a function of the assistance that they find there for their
industrialization. Henceforth a state has few chances to maintain its sover¬
eignty over numerous peoples if it is incapable of assuming responsibility for
raising their standard of living.
On the economic level as well, the distinction appears between defensive
capacity and offensive capacity. An underdeveloped nation often has a great
capacity to resist eventual sanctions: only a small fraction of the population
would be affected by the interruption of foreign trade. On the other hand, a
great state that wants to create and lead a coalition with a minimum reliance
on force requires economic resources (technicians, available capital for invest¬
ment abroad, etc.).
The political means that states have used throughout history in their peace¬
time intercourse consist of actions affecting either the elite or the masses of
the political units. In every century the great states have infiltrated the small
states, through agents and money, corrupting consciences or recruiting loyal¬
ties. For a long time the presence of “foreign parties” was considered the
6o
THEORY
effect and the symbol of weakness. Those states were “Balkanized” whose
foreign policy was the object of dispute among various parties, each of which,
reserving its preferences for a great state, could be accused of serving a foreign
master.
A new factor, in our century—one implied by our democratic customs—is
that the masses are courted just as much as the leading minorities by the
words and the spokesmen of the aggressive states. Each of the blocs, each of
the giants, attempts to convince the governed, on the other side of the line of
demarcation, that they are exploited, oppressed, abused. The war of propa¬
ganda, the war of radio, marks the permanence of the conflict among states
and the ceaseless recourse to means of pressure. In this interplay, power is not
a function of military strength or economic resources. One regime is better
suited for export through advertising, another state is better able to recruit
disinterested representatives or more willing to supply money for the rape of
conscience.
Here, too, the factors of defensive capacity are quite different from those
of offensive capacity. The supreme, almost unique condition of defensive
power is the cohesion of the collectivity, the adherence of the people to the
regime, the agreement among members of the elite concerning the national
interest. Switzerland or Sweden, which have virtually no desire or possibility
of influencing the thought or action of other nations, are less vulnerable to
foreign pressures.
Beyond economic and psycho-political means—and increasingly in our pe¬
riod-states use violence in peacetime. I shall distinguish symbolic violence
and clandestine or sporadic violence. Symbolic violence is the kind expressed
by what is called gunboat diplomacy. The sending of a warship to the harbor
of a nation not paying its debts, attempting to deny its commitments or to
nationalize a concession granted to a foreign company, symbolized the ca¬
pacity and the resolution to constrain, if necessary by armed force. The sym¬
bol was enough. The transition to the act was never actually necessary. Re¬
called to order, the “weak nation” had no recourse but to yield. The day the
transition to the act of violence risks becoming normally necessary, symbolic
violence falls into desuetude. The Franco-British expedition to Suez in 1956
might perhaps have been rational if an internal opposition had been ready to
overthrow Nasser, if the latter, in the hour of danger, had found himself
alone or had suddenly lost his courage. The simulacrum of violence would
have been convincing enough.
If symbolic violence appertains to the nineteenth century, sporadic or clan¬
destine violence belongs to the twentieth. Clandestine violence—attacks in the
shadows—is always sporadic; the sporadic violence of partisans is often com¬
mitted out in the open. Terrorist networks in cities are clandestine, partisan
forces are scattered, but they eventually wear uniforms and live openly in
the djebels or maquis (underbrush). Some states not at war with each other
POWER AND FORCE
6l
fight, in peacetime, by means of terrorists and partisans. Egypt trained ter¬
rorist teams and sent them into Israeli territory. Algerian partisans were
trained in Egypt or Morocco, "the army of liberation” was supplied from
Tunisia and Morocco. It is now assumed that the peacetime use of speech
and small arms to overthrow a state regime is not contradictory to interna¬
tional law. Here, too, defensive power depends on national unity: revolu¬
tionaries do not succeed if they do not find some voluntary complicity among
the people. The capacity to use violence for repression is also a determinant
of defensive power against subversive efforts. In Hungary the Soviet Union
lost on the level of “prestige of morality,” but won on the level of “prestige of
cruelty.” As Machiavelli said, it is sometimes preferable for the sovereign to
be feared than to he loved.
The capacity for collective action in peacetime is manifested either by the
use of these various means or by the resistance to these same means shown
by the rival states. The diplomatic capacity, strictly speaking, has a double
aspect: it is either, in the largest sense, the use of all these means and the
choice of appropriate ones among them, or, in the more limited sense, it is the
quality of action as a result of which a state makes friends and disarms pos¬
sible adversaries, and the meeting of negotiators ends favorably.
Diplomacy without means of economic or political pressure, without sym¬
bolic or clandestine violence, would be pure persuasion. Perhaps it does not
exist. Perhaps “pure” diplomacy still suggests, however implicitly, that it
would be in a position to intimidate if it resolved to do so. At least pure di¬
plomacy makes every effort to convince both adversary and onlookers that it
desires to persuade or convince, not to constrain. The adversary must have
the illusion of freedom, even when he is in fact yielding to force.
Diplomacy approaches pure diplomacy when it acts upon neutrals and
independents, when its goal is to win sympathy or disarm prejudice. In dip¬
lomatic meetings, above all when the negotiators are in each other’s presence
and exchange arguments, words are paramount, since the interlocutors speak
and listen. Thus negotiation is for diplomacy the equivalent of engagement
for strategy: it is the cash with which credit operations are made good.
Yet a fundamental difference persists. Diplomatic preparation leads to the
conference table as military preparation to a trial by arms. But the negotia¬
tors’ margin of maneuver is limited by the potential forces of coalitions (when
there have been no hostilities), by the faits acconrplis of battle (when the
war has taken place): by manipulating disagreements among the adversaries,
a negotiator can occasionally repair the damages wrought by arms. But in this
case, it is less the tete-a-tete of negotiation than the adulterated diplomatic
interplay—the regrouping of forces—which has transformed the situation. On
the other hand, once military action begins, the essentials are in the balance,
that is, victory or defeat Pure diplomatic dialogue confirms the sanction of
events, the event judges among rival claims.
62
THEORY
4. The Uncertainties of the Measurement of Power
It may be useful to consider a particular case in order to specify the less
abstract terms in which the three fundamental categories, milieu, means, and
capacity for collective action, are projected in a given historical period—say
the 1919-39 period.
Combat technique and army organization, between the two world wars,
were such that total mobilization was both legitimate and possible. All the
citizens in condition to fight could be uniformed as soldiers, providing in¬
dustry was able to equip them. Total mobilization being the rule, the poten¬
tial of military strength seemed to vary directly with economic potential. Yet
this relationship was actually subject to many reservations, both quantitative
and qualitative.
It was difficult to determine the economic quantity by which military po¬
tential could be measured. Whether one selected the gross national product,
total industrial production or certain industrial statistics, any index chosen in¬
volved an error. The index of the gross national product was an inexact
measurement because agricultural production or services cannot be mobilized
for the war effort like the metallurgic or mechanical industries. The same
was true for the index of industrial production, for workers and machines
cannot be transferred from biscuit factory to aeronautics plant as easily as
automobile manufacture can be converted to tanks. Lastly, if only the figures
of heavy industry or factory production were used, there was a risk of error in
the contrary direction. With sufficient time, transfers of workers and machines
can proceed to great lengths. France’s industrial war effort between 1914 and
1918, despite the occupation of part of her territory, was remarkable: by the
end of hostilities the American army also was utilizing cannons and shells of
French manufacture. It is true that at the time, weapons and even planes were
relatively simple so far as scientific knowledge and technological potential
were concerned.
The transition from economic potential to military strength also depends,
in modem times, on the “capacity for collective action” in the form of tech¬
nical-administrative capacity. A German professor whose name has today
fallen into oblivion, J. Plenge, published, in 1916, an interesting worklll
whose central theme is the antithesis between the ideas of 1789 and those
of 1914. Ultimately the ideas of 1914 recall one key word: organization. For
the whole nation to work in terms of the war—some men in uniform, others
in factories or offices, others in the fields, all producing what is necessary to
nourish population and battle alike—the administration must be capable of
redistributing the population among the necessary jobs, reducing to a mini¬
mum the number of workers who produce those goods that are not indispens¬
able, and assigning to each man the task to which he is best suited. During
0 1789 nnd 1914. Die symbolischen Jahre in der Geschichte des ■politischen Geistes,
Berlin, 1916.
POWER AND FORCE
63
the last war it was Great Britain, among the Western powers, which achieved
the highest percentage of mobilization. Hitler’s Germany started the conflict
without having mobilized either all its industry or all its manpower, it had not
resolved upon total mobilization after the Polish campaign nor after the
French campaign, nor even after the Wehrmacht’s invasion of Russia. It was
not until Stalingrad that the total mobilization of German resources was un¬
dertaken, although millions of workers had been recruited from occupied
territories.
In wartime the degree of mobilization is chiefly a function of administrative
capacity, but also, in part, of the people’s acceptance of sacrifice. Beyond a
certain point the war effort cannot be increased except by reducing the level
of the standard of living of the civilian population. How far can this re¬
duction go without affecting the level of morale? This question cannot be an¬
swered in any general way. It would seem, however, that peoples accustomed
to a low standard of living accept privations more easily than those accustomed
to a higher standard of living, which tends to reverse the purely theoretical
proposition: the margin of mobilization is directly proportional to the standard
of living. In the abstract, the gap between the actual condition of the people
and the incompressible minimum is greater in rich countries than in poor
countries, but the former cannot always do without what the latter classify as
superfluous.
Lastly, belligerents wage war with actually mobilized, not potential forces.
Now the former depend on space and time, on the map and on the course of
hostilities. The total potential may be paralyzed or amputated by the lack of
certain raw materials (what would be the use of millions of tanks if they had
no gas?). Conversely, master}' of the seas combined with financial reserves or
foreign loans can add to the actual potential that of the legally neutral nations
(as from the United States, from 1914 to 1917, to the Allies’ benefit). But
the experience of the First World War had given the Franco-British powers,
in 1939, an ill-founded assurance. They assumed in advance the benefit of
duration. In the long run the mobilization of the Western world’s resources
guaranteed them superiority and a victory by attrition. Still, it was essential
that defeat in the first phases of the hostilities did not put the industrial po¬
tential of a fragment of the coalition into the enemy’s hands. Without the
victory of the Marne in 1914, there would not have been a total mobilization
of the French potential. Without the Battle of Britain, there would not have
been, starting in 1940, a total mobilization of the British and later the Amer¬
ican potential. In 1939 the Franco-British potential represented only figures
on paper if the two democracies did not have available time and freedom of
the seas. France had no time, Great Britain, in spite of everything, retained
freedom of the seas.
Once military forces are recognized as a function of the human and in¬
dustrial potential, with the reservations we have just indicated, the question
becomes one of quality. In each phase, what would be the relative value of
THEORY
64
a German, French, English, Italian or American division? The only true
measurement is combat itself. Therefore, in peacetime, the evaluation, a
problematical one, is made according to the experience of preceding battles.
Until the battle of Jena the Prussian army maintained the prestige of the
victories of Frederick the Great. Until 1940 the French army still appeared
to be that of Verdun (1916) or of Champagne (1918).
Whether it was a question of cannon or army, the same question was
raised: to what degree was the quality of weapons the reflection of indus¬
trial production? To what degree was the effectiveness of the troops the
expression of the martial vigor of the people? In other words, could military
force be estimated according to the state of the nation? Or did military
force depend primarily on factors peculiar to the military system itself?
Hitler did not believe that the United States could acquire, in the very
course of hostilities, an army of the first rank, for by reason of the funda¬
mentally pacificist, commercial attitude of the American people, there was
no military tradition or class comparable to the German officers corps. The
Fiihrer, to his misfortune and our salvation, was mistaken. A double dem¬
onstration has been convincingly presented: providing officers for the troops
is no less important in the twentieth than in the nineteenth century, but
this no longer requires a social class dedicated to the profession of arms.
Many military problems—organization, logistics—resemble the problems of
industry or transportation. Technicians rapidly learn the tasks that they must
fulfill within the military system, and that resemble those of their civilian
profession. But further, the citizens of a prosperous nation furnish soldiers,
officers and non-commissioned officers capable of sustaining the rigors and
dangers of modem battle.
In other words, the miracle of a leader of men giving his nation, by
genius or good luck, an honorable place on the world’s stage, the adventure
of a Mehemet Ali, though still possible in the last century, is no longer so
today. When regular armies are involved, the human and industrial potential
assigns narrow limits to the action of the leader. There is no great modem
army without a great industry behind it. Any nation provided with a great
industry is capable of establishing a great army.
The two propositions, relative to what is and is not possible, being es¬
tablished on the theoretical level, the error would have been to attribute to
an incontestable relation a rigor it did not have. Equipped in the same way,
two divisions were not equivalent. The role of a dozen German armored
divisions, which took a decisive part in the Polish and French campaigns,
then in the first victories on the Russian front, would remind us, if necessary,
that battle elites exist in the century of quantity. In the last case it seems
that training and technical perfection went hand in hand with the passion
of the officers and the soldiers to create an instrument which irremediably
exhausted itself before Moscow in November-December 1941. The Wehr-
macht still won its victories, it had other shock troops, but it never again
POWER AND FORCE 63
found the equivalent of that armored force which had been its spearhead
in the east, the west, and then again in the east.
That the quality of the military order and the effectiveness of the army
are influenced by the political regime and the national psychology cannot
be doubted. Depending on the prestige of the profession of arms, depending
on the material and moral position of the officers within the nation, the
recruiting of military cadres will be more or less good, better minds will be
attracted to the study of national defense or will turn from it. It is doubtful
that the circumstances to which the German army had owed the quality of
its command will be reproduced in the Federal Republic. Neither the
aristocracy of public service, nor faith in the country’s greatness, nor the
prestige of the uniform exist in a Federal Republic without colonized
lands to the east, without Junkers, without imperial prospects.
Of these complex and subtle relations, popular phrases, current in certain
periods, give us a caricature notion: “There is no discipline in the army
when there is no discipline in the nation.” The formula is quoted by Renan
with praise: as a matter of fact the apparent anarchy within the democracies
does not exclude discipline in factories or barracks. From 1945 to 1958 the
Fourth Republic sought a stable government: all the officers bore witness to
the discipline of the men in their contingents. On the other hand, propa¬
gandists of the Fascist Right were finally caught in their own fictions and
imagined that the Duce had transformed the Italians into a nation of lions
and had given Italy (with neither coal nor steel), a first-rank military force.
Spengler had already attributed to Mussolini the empire of North Africa,
fallen from the decadent hands of French democracy.
Similarly, an industry on a high technical level will normally furnish
effective arms, but Western peacetime industry aims at raising the labor out¬
put, hence at producing as cheaply as possible. Cost is not a decisive factor
when it is weapons that are being manufactured. A nation which invests a
great deal of money and uses its best minds in industries directly oriented
toward war production will eventually possess arms as good or better than
those of a rival whose industry has nonetheless a superior average pro¬
ductivity (such is the case in the United States and the Soviet Union).
Let us not forget, finally, that with regard to the quality of weapons in
our age, nothing is ever established once and for all. The race toward im¬
provement continues during the hostilities themselves. The time necessary
for the development of certain weapons was such that the First World War
was ended with models used since the beginning of hostilities (long-range
naval cannon). But artillery was a traditional weapon which, until the
advent of electronics and automatic adjustment, showed only slow improve¬
ments during the First World War and the period between the wars. On
the other hand, aviation progressed rapidly from 1914 to 1918, then from
1919 to 1939 (especially during the last years before the war), and
finally during the course of the Second World War. The side that at
66
THEORY
the end of the war had machines available or models perfected at the be¬
ginning of hostilities would have been immediately outclassed. In 1941 the
Japanese possessed the Zero, the best fighter plane in action in the Far
East. But they could not stay in the race: in 1945 they were forced to use
suicide planes while their fleet was being destroyed. The scientific-tech¬
nological competition which the rivalry of military forces has henceforth in¬
volved can never be won. Qualitatively and quantitatively, the advantage
shifts from one camp to the other. French aviation in the last war would
have been quite different if it had had another six months—in other words,
if industrial mobilization had been undertaken six months earlier, or if the
battle had broken out six months later. On the whole, a state with a tech¬
nologically superior industry has better chances of winning: still, we must
not forget that by a greater concentration in one sector, a country’s industry
can make up for its backwardness as a whole, and that, in peacetime
manufactures as well, the palm of victory is not always awarded to the same
country.
Beyond these calculations of force, we must take into account the in¬
telligence of the high command and the conduct of the war by the statesmen
on either side, and lastly the adherence of the peoples to the regime, their
resolution when put to the test. Would the Soviet people be loyal to the
state and the party in charge of agrarian collectivization and the great
purges? Would the German and Italian people enthusiastically follow their
Fiihrer and their Duce? Were the people in the democracies capable of
facing the horrors of battle? Whether military leaders or peoples were in¬
volved, the answers, formulated in advance, could not be proved, the knowl¬
edge on which they were based was not transferable.
The answer given by events themselves was above all a refutation of the
relations supposed to exist between the behavior of peoples and the nature
of the regime. The Italians were never convinced that the war fought at
the side of the Third Reich was really their own and justified supreme
sacrifices: the partisans who fought the German troops in northern Italy
after the fall of Fascism bore witness to a morale quite different from that
of the soldiers (ill-equipped, moreover) in Libya. The German people did
not desert their Fiihrer but, in the ruling circles, the conspiracy of July 20
had wide ramifications: the National Socialist regime was basically much
less united than the British or American democracy. In the Soviet Union
there was no conspiracy in leading circles, but during the first phase of
the hostilities, a fraction of the people, particularly the non-Russian groups,
received the invaders without hostility, and certain troops showed little ar¬
dor. In short, the two nations of Europe in which regime and people stood
together, in 1939, were Hitler’s Germany and democratic England, with
this reservation, that national unity was more capable of resisting defeat in
England than in Germany.
In terms of these calculations, what observations are suggested by the
POWER AMD FORCE
67
post eventum analysis of the events of the thirties? The totalitarian nations
were in peacetime, with equal forces, more powerful than the democratic
nations. They presented a fagade of unity, whereas the latter paraded their
disputes. France and Great Britain were saturated, conservative nations,
whereas Italy and Germany were assertive nations. Regimes in which one
man commands, in which the deliberations occur in secret, are more capable
of suggesting irresistible force and flawless resolution than those regimes
whose press is free and whose parliament debates. In the diplomatic poker
game the totalitarian state often bluffs and almost always wins—until the
day when another nation calls the bluff.
Italian politics, from 1935 to 1941, consisted of a series of “bluffs” and
“bets.” When Mussolini proclaimed that he was ready to declare war on
Great Britain and France rather than give up the conquest of Ethiopia,
according to all probabilities he was bragging of what he would have been
incapable of doing. What occurred in 1943 would have probably happened
in 1936 had Mussolini been mad enough to involve Italy in a conflict,
lost in advance, against the Franco-British alliance. He prevailed because
the partisans of sanctions did not want to run the risk of war, and because
the ruling circles of France and Great Britain were not unanimous as to the
advantage and the consequences of an eventual overthrow of Fascism. In
1940 there was no longer question of a bluff but of a bet—a bet that the
war was virtually over and that by intervening, Italy would receive a larger
share of the spoils.
The German venture had an entirely different style. It was subdivided
into two phases. Between January 1933 and March 1936 Germany would
not have had the strength to resist a military response from France. Hitler
assumed what at least looked like risks by successively violating all the
principal clauses of the Versailles Treaty. His diplomatic technique was
that of challenge: he defied France to use force in forbidding Germany
decisions which tended simply to suppress the inequalities resulting from
the Versailles Treaty. Challenged, France relied on protests—the worst of
solutions between the two extremes (equally unacceptable to French pub¬
lic opinion) of frank acceptance and military action.
From 1936 on, the technique of challenge continued, but in another form.
Hitler defied France and England to use military means because such means
henceforth signified a general war which Germany still had every chance of
losing but that constituted, in any case, a catastrophe for the saturated and
conservative states. After 1938 Hitler’s Germany had a superiority of
actual forces, not so great as it tended to claim, as we have since learned,
but sufficient to conquer Czechoslovakia in 1938 and Poland in 1939. In
case of a general war the Western powers could not win except in the
long run, by the mobilization of their superior potential. Hitler had only
one last stage to cover in order to acquire an apparently serious possibility
of victory, even in case of a general war: to neutralize the principal enemy
68
THEORY
to the east (the Soviet Union) while he first liquidated the secondary
enemy to the east (Poland) and then the Continental enemy to the west.
From this moment on, the calculation of potentials no longer signified
anything, since every enterprise was based on the succession of campaigns
and bets: to conquer Poland before France intervened, France before Great
Britain was mobilized and the Soviet Union belligerent, the Soviet Union
before Great Britain was in a position to land on the Continent. All these
bets were won, save the last. Protected by the guarantee the Western
powers had given Poland, Stalin decided to reserve his forces by signing
the pact with Hitler. Poland was eliminated without the French army’s
moving; France was eliminated from the conflict when Great Britain had
only a dozen divisions. But Great Britain was neither invaded in 1940 nor
paralyzed by bombings. The Soviet army, despite the disasters suffered in
1941, made a recovery before Moscow. This final lost bet determined all
the consequences. In December 1941 the United States was swept into the
war by the Japanese aggression. The war on two fronts, a war Germany
had already waged and lost, a war the German general staff had not ceased
to fear and considered as lost in advance, announced the pitiless ruin of the
Fiihrer’s hopes. The Germans in opposition, who had foreseen the East-
West coalition in case of general war and therefore the defeat of the Third
Reich, saw their anticipations confirmed. The bets and successes had merely
retarded the fatal outcome.
The Japanese bet, in 1941, was senseless, since on paper the Empire of
the Rising Sun had no chance of winning and could avoid losing only if
the Americans were too lazy or cowardly to conquer. Hitler’s bet was
risky and a legitimate leader would not have made it, since Germany could
have obtained more, without fighting, by the mere threat of war, and since
the dangers of defeat were so extreme. But the bet was not lost in advance.
Hitler won on all points until the armistice of June 1940. This, to use
Clausewitz’s terms, was the culminating 'point of victory. From this moment
on, he multiplied his mistakes. He could not determine whether to treat
France as an irreducible enemy or a recoverable ally; he hesitated to invade
England and finally decided to use the unemployed Wehrmacht in a Rus¬
sian campaign. Directing diplomacy, he himself forged the great alliance
which he had so labored to prevent. Directing strategy, he did not have the
courage to proceed to that ultimate concentration of forces that might have
given him decisive successes. Directing the conduct of the armies them¬
selves, he made on-the-spot resistance into a categorical imperative. As a
military leader, he hoped until the end for a disintegration of the enemy
coalition and finally died in a Wagnerian catastrophe, having long since
lost contact with reality.
Hitler had no monopoly on mistakes. If, in the last analysis, Stalin out¬
witted him, one dares not attribute the sole merit for this to his genius.
POWER AND FORCE
69
Once Germany was eliminated, there was no obstacle to Russian penetration
of Europe. Had the Americans been aware, in 1942, of the contradiction
between Soviet and American interests, the master of the Kremlin would
have had a difficult role to play. This was not the case. Invited to intervene
in order to deliver the coup de grace to Japan and authorized to occupy
Eastern Europe as far as central Germany, Stalin accepted, without having
to be asked twice, what was so graciously offered.
What is the role of power or of force in international relations? The
question is now classical in military schools in the United States. The
answer is not unambiguous because the same concept of power designates,
as we have seen, resources, military forces and power.
The status of a political unit within an international system is fixed by
the size of material or human resources that it can devote to diplomatic-
strategic action. The great powers, in each period, are reputed capable of
devoting considerable resources to external action and, in particular, of
mobilizing numerous cohorts. International society involves a hierarchy of
prestige which approximately reflects the hierarchy established by preceding
combats.
Relations of forces also establish, to a large extent, the hierarchy within
alliances: but this hierarchy does not necessarily express the relation of
power, the highest-ranking state imposing its will on those beneath it.
Once the superior state cannot employ military force, it must use means of
pressure, indirect and often ineffective, or else methods of persuasion. Al¬
liances are always directed by the great powers, but the small power some¬
times takes the great where the latter would not have chosen to go. The
small power has the last word in a discussion that concerns its own interests
because it forces the great power to choose between concession or the use of
force. The tactic of refusal or obstruction, as General de Gaulle practiced
it between 1940 and 1944 with regard to Great Britain and the United
States, often permitted the weaker entity to impose its will. Once the Free
French were established in St. Pierre and Miquelon, the United States could
not drive them out except by force and, in the middle of the war, Roosevelt
could not give orders to fight Frenchmen who symbolized their country
then occupied by the common enemy.
Even relations among rival states are not, in normal times, the pure and
simple expression of relations of force. The negotiators make mistakes as to
each other’s forces and, further, do not consider themselves obliged to con¬
clude the land of agreement that would emerge from the test of war. So
long as men “talk” instead of “fight,” reasons of fact and of law are not
without influence on the interlocutor. Diplomacy, a substitute for war, is not
limited to putting on record, at every moment, the latter’s supposed con¬
clusion. “That each receives according to the achievements of his weapons,”
THEORY
70
as General de Gaulle has said^is true only in its vague sense and in the
long run. Valid as a counsel of wisdom—states must not assume objectives
disproportionate to their resources—this formula implies, if taken literally,
an underestimation of the subtlety of relations between independent col¬
lectivities.
The disproportion between the potential of nations and the accomplish¬
ments of their diplomacy is often caused by the regrouping of units against
that power among them that seems about to assume the role of "trouble¬
maker.” By definition, sovereign states regard as an enemy any claiming
hegemony, that is, any that could deprive them of their own autonomy or
their capacity to make their own decisions freely. Therefore, a diplomat of
the classical school, like Bismarck, feared an excessive growth of the Reich’s
powers. He believed that the Reich should limit its ambitions and thereby
excuse its ascendency by wisdom and proportion. That his country’s power
was in the service of justice and European order was, in the eyes of the
Iron Chancellor, the necessary condition for German security, the means of
avoiding the coalition of rivals whom the Prussian victories must neither
humiliate nor disturb. During the first phase after 1870 it was vanquished
France, not victorious Germany, that made territorial acquisitions. Rarely,
between 1870 and 1914, did the representative of the Reich manifest a
capacity to convince commensurate with the armed forces his nation could
mobilize for war, either from a lack of diplomatic talent, or as a result of
the spontaneous opposition which any virtually hegemonic state faces.
“A universal monarchy,” as the eighteenth-century authors called it, or
else limited enterprises: the alternative was the unwritten law of the Euro¬
pean system, as it is of virtually any system of states. Either the great power
will not tolerate equals, and then must proceed to the last degree of empire,
or else it consents to stand first among sovereign units, and must win
acceptance for such pre-eminence. Whatever the choice, it will live in dan¬
ger, never having won all the victories necessary, always suspected of as¬
piring to domination.
If states sought to be great in order to enjoy security, they would be
victims of a strange illusion, but, through history, collective greatness has
been its own reward.
EUrhe formula occurs at the end of the report sent by him in January 1940 to the
French High Command.
chapter III
Power, Glory and Idea
or
On the Goals of Foreign Policy
Political units seek to impose their wills upon each other: such is the
hypothesis on which Clausewitz’s definition of war is based and also the
conceptual framework of international relations. At this point, one question
arises: why do political units want to impose their wills upon each other! 1
What goals does each of them desire and why are these goals incompatible,
or seem to be so?
If we focus on the moment at which a generalized war breaks out, it is
easy to indicate, with more or less precision, the goals chosen by each of the
states in conflict with the others. In 1914 Austria-Hungary sought to elimi¬
nate the threat that the southern Slav claims posed to the dualist monarchy.
France, which had consented to the annexation of Alsace-Lorraine without
acknowledging the fact morally, discovered intact and ardent, on the day
the first cannon thundered, the will to restore her lost provinces to the
mother country. The Italians claimed lands that once belonged to the Habs-
burg empire. The Allies were virtually no less divided than their adversaries.
Tsarist Russia wanted possession of Constantinople and the Dardanelles,
whereas Great Britain had constantly opposed such ambitions. Only the
German danger incited London to agree, secretly and on paper, to what it
had stubbornly refused for over a century.
Perhaps the Reich inspired its rivals with even greater alarm because its
war goals were not known. At the moment of its first successes, these goals
seemed grandiose and vague. Leagues and private groups dreamed of the
“African belt” or of Mittel Europa. The general staff, as late as 1917-18,
demanded the annexation or occupation of a part of Belgian territory for
strategic reasons. A dominant power which does not proclaim definite ob¬
jectives is suspected of unlimited ambitions. Provinces (Alsace-Lorraine,
Trieste), strategic positions (the Dardanelles, the coast of Flanders), re¬
ligious symbols (Constantinople), such were the explicit stakes of the con-
THEORY
7 2
flicts among the European states. But simultaneously, the result of the con¬
flict would determine the relation of forces, the place of Germany in Europe
and of Great Britain in the world. Is it possible to distinguish, in an ab¬
stract analysis of general scope, the typical goals which states aim at and
which set them in opposition to each other?
i. Eternal Objectives
Let us start from the schema of international relations: the political units,
proud of their independence, jealous of their capacity to make major de¬
cisions on their own, are rivals by the very fact that they are autonomous.
Each, in the last analysis, can count only on itself.
What then is the first objective which the political unit may logically
seek? The response is furnished by Hobbes in his analysis of the state of
nature. Each political unit aspires to survive. Leaders and led are interested
in and eager to maintain the collectivity they constitute together by virtue
of history, race, or fortune.
If we grant that war is not desired for its own sake, the belligerent power
that dictates the peace terms at the end of hostilities seeks to create con¬
ditions guaranteeing that it need not fight in the immediate future and
that it may keep the advantages gained through force. We may say that in
the state of nature, every entity, whether individual or political unit, makes
security a primary objective. The more severe wars become, the more men
aspire to security. In Germany, too, from 1914 to 1918, there was speculation
as to the best methods to insure the nation’s definitive security by disarming
certain of its adversaries or occupying certain key positions.
Security, in a world of autonomous political units, can be based either on
the weakness of rivals (total or partial disarmament) or on force itself. If
we suppose that security is the final goal of state policy, the effective means
will be to establish a new relation of forces or to modify the old one so
that potential enemies, by reason of their inferiority, will not be tempted
to take the initiative of an aggression.
The relation between these two terms —security and force —raises many
problems. On a lower level we may first observe that the maximization of
resources does not necessarily involve the maximization of security. In
Europe, traditionally, no state could increase its population, its wealth and
its soldiers without exciting the fear and jealousy of other states, and
thereby provoking the formation of a hostile coalition. In any given system
there exists an optimum of forces; to exceed it will produce a dialectical
reversal. Additional force involves a relative weakening by a shift of allies
to neutrality or of neutrals to the enemy camp.
If security were, by evidence or necessity, the preferential objective, it
would be possible to determine rational behavior theoretically. It would he
necessary, in each circumstance, to determine the optimum of force and to
act in consequence. A more serious difficulty appears as soon as we raise
POWER, GLORY AND IDEA
73
questions as to the relation between these two objectives, force and security.
We concede that man, whether individual or collective, desires to survive.
But the individual does not subordinate all his desires to his desire for life
alone. There are goals for which the individual accepts a risk of death. The
same is true of collective units. The latter do not seek to be strong only in
order to discourage aggression and enjoy peace; they seek to be strong in
order to be feared, respected or admired. In the last analysis, they seek to
be powerful—that is, capable of imposing their wills on their neighbors and
rivals, in order to influence the fate of humanity, the future of civilization.
The two objectives are connected: the more strength he has, the less risk
a man runs of being attacked, but he also finds, in strength as such and in
the capacity to impose himself upon others, a satisfaction which needs no
other justification. Security can be a final goal: to be without fear is a fate
worthy of envy; but power, too, can be a final goal: what does danger mat¬
ter once one has known the intoxication of ruling?
But on this level of abstraction, the enumeration of objectives still does
not seem to me to be complete: I would add a third term, glory. In the
essay entitled “On the Balance of Power,” David Humcfi-I explains the be¬
havior of the Greek city-states in terms of the spirit of competition rather
than the calculations of prudence: “It is true, that Grecian wars are re¬
garded by historians as wars of emulation rather than of politics; and each
State seems to have had more in view the honor of leading the rest, than
any well-grounded hopes of authority and dominion.” Opposing jealous
emulation to cautious politics, Hume thus formulates the antithesis that we
shall call the struggle for glory and the struggle for power.
When the struggle is joined, there is a danger that military victory in
itself will become the goal, causing political objectives to be forgotten. The
desire for absolute victory, that is, for a peace dictated without appeal
by the victor, is often more the expression of a desire for glory than of a
desire for force. Dislike of relative victories, that is, of a favorable peace
negotiated after partial successes, derives from the amour-propre that ani¬
mates men once they measure themselves against each other.
It might be objected that glory is merely another name or another aspect
of power: it is, so to speak, power recognized by others, power whose fame
spreads across the world. In a sense this objection is valid and the three
objectives might be reduced to two: either the political units are in quest of
security and of force, or they seek recognition by imposing their wills, by
gathering the conqueror’s laurels. One of the two goals, force, is material,
the other is moral, inseparable from the human dialogue; it is defined by
grandeur, consecrated by victory and the enemy’s submission.
The ternary division, however, seems to me preferable because each of
the three terms corresponds to a concretely defined attitude while it also
expresses a specific notion. Clemenceau sought the security, Napoleon the
0 Sce Lelow, |Chapter v[ for a fuller analysis of Hume’s essay.
THEORY
74
power, Louis XIV the glory of France (or each his own).0 In 1918 any
rational chief of state would have proposed the same goal: to spare France
the recurrence of a war as severe as the one that an immense alliance had
just brought to a favorable conclusion. Napoleon, at least after a certain
date, dreamed of ruling Europe: he was not content with the honor of
being universally celebrated as a great war leader; even Clausewitz’s hom¬
age—“the God of war himself”—would not have satisfied him. He was am¬
bitious for reality, not for appearances, and he knew that in the long run
no state commands others if it does not possess the means of constraining
them. Louis XIV probably loved glory as much as power. He wanted to be
recognized as the first among monarchs, and he made use of his force in
order to seize a city and fortify it, but this half-symbolic exploit was still a
way of showing his force. He did not conceive of a disproportionately en¬
larged France, furnished with resources superior to those of her allied rivals.
He dreamed that the names of Louis XIV and of France would be trans¬
figured by the admiration of nations.
This first analysis would be more dangerous than useful if it were not
filled out by another. Indeed, if we abide by these abstract notions, we will
be inclined to dismiss glory as irrational^ to condemn the indefinite ac¬
cumulation of force as contradictory (the loss of allies more than offsetting,
at a certain point, the increase of one’s own forces). From this angle, we
would arrive at the allegedly unique objective of security. Let us abandon
such abstract analyses and consider a political unit—that is, a human col¬
lectivity occupying a fragment of space. If we suppose that this collectivity
is comparable to a person, with an intelligence and a will of its own, what
goals is it liable to choose?
A collectivity occupies a certain territory: it can logically consider the sur¬
face of the earth at its disposal as too small. In rivalry among peoples, the
possession of space was the original stake. Secondly, sovereigns have often
estimated their greatness according to the number of their subjects: what they
desired, beyond their frontiers, was not territory, but men. Lastly, the armed
prophet is sometimes less anxious to conquer than to convert: indifferent to
the wealth of the earth and what it contains, he does not calculate the num¬
ber of his workers or soldiers; he seeks to spread the true faith, he wants the or¬
ganization corresponding to his interpretation of life and of history to en¬
compass gradually all of humanity.
Here again, this ternary series seems to me complete. All the goals that
states determine for themselves, in historical circumstances, necessarily refer
to one of the three terms we have just listed: space, men and souls. Why
should societies fight if not to extend the territory they cultivate and whose
wealth they exploit, to conquer men who are alien today, slaves or fellow
0Which does not exclude the fact that each also desired the objectives suggested hy
the two other terms.
Hilt would be wrong to do so; man does not live by bread alone.
POWER, GLORY AND IDEA
75
citizens tomorrow, or to insure the triumph of a certain idea, whether reli¬
gious or social, whose universal truth the collectivity proclaims simultaneously
with its own mission?
Concretely, these objectives are difficult to separate. Unless he exterminates
or drives out the inhabitants, the conqueror takes possession of both space
and the men who occupy it. Unless conversion takes place by the mere force
of proselytism, the prophet does not disdain to govern men before administer¬
ing the salvation of souls. It remains no less true that in certain cases the
three terms are distinct: the Crusaders first sought to liberate the Holy Land,
not to convert the Moslems. The Israelis wanted to occupy the Palestinian
space that had been the Kingdom of David, they were not interested in either
conquering or converting the Moslems of Palestine. The sovereigns of mo¬
narchical Europe collected provinces—land and men—because the power and
prestige of princes was measured by possessions. As for the conversion of the
infidel, perhaps it has never been the exclusive goal of any state. Only un¬
armed prophets dream of pure conversion, but, as Machiavelli said, they per¬
ish. Though states are sometimes prophetic, they are always armed. Not that
an idea is an instrument or a justification of the desire to conquer space or
men. In the minds of religious or ideological leaders, the triumph of the faith,
the spread of an idea, may be conceived, in all sincerity, as the true goal of
action. It is in the eyes of the unbelievers that this goal seems a camouflage
for imperialism: historians and theoreticians, also unbelievers, adhere all too
easily to this cynical interpretation.
What are the relations between the abstract series and the concrete series?
It would be as arbitrary to subordinate the second to the first as to decree the
opposite. The increase of space, the augmentation of material and human
resources are, certainly, elements of security and power, sometimes even the
objectives of glory. This does not mean that the conquest of a province can
never be desired for itself. The French did not regard the return of Alsace-
Lorraine to the mother country as a means to some ulterior goal, but as a good
in itself, which required no other justification. Without Alsace-Lorraine,
France was mutilated: with Strasbourg and Metz, she recovered her integrity.
Down through the centuries, regions and cities and the men who populate
them have assumed a historical significance, a symbolic value. The question
is no longer whether the Moslems of Palestine or the Israelis could have
found elsewhere a territory as fertile and resources that would have been
equal or superior. It was here, around the Sea of Tiberias and on the plain
of Jerusalem, it was here and in no other place on the planet that certain
Jews (who no longer believed in God and in the “covenant”) wanted to cre¬
ate anew a collectivity that would proclaim itself the heir of a semi-legendary
past.
In our times, no guarantee of order and justice suffices to disarm national
claims: active minorities leading various populations seek to belong to the
political unit of their choice. The Cypriots wanted a fatherland, which
THEORY
76
could not be Great Britain or the British Empire: fair administration, auton¬
omy, a relatively high standard of living—nothing could compensate for the
absence of a political community. Of the two aspirations, not to be uprooted
and not to be deprived of a fatherland, it is the first that has ultimately
yielded in Europe: transfers of populations have in a sense signified the
primacy of the nation over the territory.
In each series, abstract or concrete, the third term, glory or idea, stands
apart. Not that these two terms correspond to each other: on the contrary,
glory is an empty notion, and exists only in human consciousness, perhaps
especially in the consciousness of the man who desires to possess it. The man
“full of glory” is the man who is satisfied with the idea that he believes others
have of him. Therefore it is precisely the “vainglorious” man who is a char¬
acter of ridicule. Even if he is not mistaken as to the sentiments he inspires,
the man “full of glory” should be unaware of his fortune or indifferent to
it in order to be entirely worthy of it. But thereby, the goal itself retreats pro¬
gressively as he approaches it. Never will the exploits performed satisfy the
doubts of the man who aspires to glory.
An idea—whether it is Christianity or communism, tire divinity of Christ
or a certain organization of society—is, on the contrary, quite definite. Per¬
haps the inquisitors will never be sure of the sincerity of conversions. Perhaps
the members of the Presidium will never eliminate the “capitalist” tendencies
of the peasants, perhaps deviations will always appear, continually renewed
upon the expulsion of the preceding deviationists. At least an idea has a
specific content, whereas glory cannot be grasped since it is linked to the
dialogue of men.
Yet in essence this objective too is situated in infinity. Where truth is
concerned, nothing is done so long as something remains to be done. The
religions of salvation have a universal vocation, they are addressed to human¬
ity since they are addressed to each man. Once a prophet takes arms to prop¬
agate them, his enterprise will never know an end unless it covers the entire
planet. Wars for glory and wars for an idea are human in a different way
from wars for land and its riches. Crusaders are sublime and dangerous. The
nobles who fight for prestige can never be through fighting. If the goal is to
conquer in order to be recognized as a conqueror or to conquer in order to
impose the truth, it suffices that the determination to win be the same on each
side for the violence to proceed to extremes. The most humane wars in origin
are also, frequently, the most inhumane, because they are the most pitiless.
Hence we are tempted to constitute a third ternary series which, following
the Platonic model, would be that of body, heart and mind. Whether it is a
question of land or men, of security or force, the stake is ultimately material:
the political units seek to enlarge their space or to accumulate resources in
order to live free of danger or with the means to avert it. But neither se¬
curity nor force satisfies the aspirations of communities : each desires to prevail
over the others, to be recognized as first among its rivals. Political units have
POWER, GLORY AND IDEA
77
theii amour-fro-pre, as people do; perhaps they are even more sensitive. Hence
they sometimes prefer the intoxication of triumph to the advantages of a
negotiated peace. Sometimes the desire for glory will be satisfied only by the
diffusion of an idea, of which each community wants to be the unique in¬
carnation. The mind, finally, animates the dialectic of violence and drives it
to extremes, once it links its destiny to that of a state, that is, of a human col¬
lectivity in arms.
Of course, the demand for security and force also leads to extremes. In the
last analysis, a political unit would feel entirely safe only if it had no further
enemy, in other words, if it had been enlarged to the dimensions of a uni¬
versal state. But the desire for security and force does not transform itself
into a demand for unlimited power, unless amour-fro'pre or faith arouses and
finally overwhelms the calculations of interest. Anxious only to live in peace,
neither Pyrrhus nor Napoleon nor Hitler would have consented to so many
certain sacrifices in the hope of an uncertain gain.
Conquerors have sometimes justified their undertakings in terms of the
prosperity their people would enjoy after victory. Such Utopias served as an
excuse, not an inspiration. These leaders desired power as an instrument of
their glory, with a view to the triumph of an idea for its own sake, never in
order that men might know “the good life.”
2. Historical Objectives
Like the theory of power, this theory of objectives has a suprahistorical
value, while it also permits us to comprehend historical diversity. The objec¬
tives of states refer, in every century, to the terms of the two ternary series or
even, if one prefers the simplified formula, to the three terms of the last ab¬
stract-concrete series. But many circumstances—of military or economic tech¬
nique, of institutional or ideological origin—intervene to limit and specify the
objectives statesmen actually select.
Let us start with the first term, the most constant stake of human conflicts:
space. At the dawn of history as on the threshold of the Atomic Age, human
groups dispute the territory on which some are established and which others
desire. Collectivities distribute territory among their members and legalize in¬
dividual ownership. But the sovereignty of the collectivity itself over the
whole of the territory is not thereby admitted by the other collectivities. Dur¬
ing the first millenniums of the historical phase, the tribes retreated before the
invaders from the east, to become conquerors in their turn with regard to the
populations settled farther west. The horsemen of the steppes established their
dominion over the sedentary populations and created hierarchic societies, the
warriors constituting a superior class superimposed upon the mass of laborers.
In modem times the stmggle for land has lost its primeval simplicity and
brutality, but is no less cruel when it breaks out. Israelis and Palestinian Mos¬
lems cannot form a single collectivity and cannot occupy the same territory:
one or the other is doomed to suffer injustice. In North Africa the French
THEORY
78
conquest of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries signified partial expro¬
priations from the Berber or Arab populations, the French settlers receiving
lands belonging to tribes, villages or families. Tunisian or Moroccan inde¬
pendence brought about a more or less rapid expropriation of French colons.
The Algerian War, in a sense, had as its stake the land that both Moslems
and French regarded as their own, and upon which they were temporarily
obliged to coexist, both demanding sovereignty—the former under the banner
of independence, the latter under that of integration.
For the French who were established across the Mediterranean, Algeria
was the land on which their fathers lived, and therefore, so to speak, the
fatherland. But for France, what has been, what is the significance of Algeria?
Why had Franck desired, since 1830, to extend her sovereignty over a ter¬
ritory which she had never occupied in the course of past centuries? It is
difficult to answer, because the very statesmen or military leaders who de¬
termined and executed the conquest either did not know why they acted
or else were divided as to their motives.
Some emphasized the threat of the Barbary Coast pirates to navigation,
and the security that possession of the Algerian coast would assure to Medi¬
terranean shipping. Let us say that they emphasized a military motive. Others
favored the possibilities of colonization and hinted at a French Empire of a
hundred million men on both shores of the Mediterranean. Let us say that
they dreamed of an enlargement of French space and an increase of French
popidatior^ During the last years Frenchmen cited the many economic ad¬
vantages of French sovereignty over Algeria, which constituted a reserve of
manpower, a customer of and purveyor to the metropolitan economy, a source
of raw materials and, particularly since 1956, of petroleum. Let us say that
economic advantages are invoked here. In other words, this example permits
us to discern the three typical arguments in favor of conquest: military or
strategic importance, spatio-demographic advantage, spatio-economic profit.
Each of these arguments is subject to the law of change. The military,
demographic or economic value of a territory varies with the techniques of
combat and production, with human relations and institutions. The same po¬
sitions are or are not strategically important, depending on the state of interna¬
tional relations (with the Russian army established two hundred kilometers
from the Rhine, the old frontier between Germany and France is of no
significance in military terms), and on armament (the Bosphorus and the
0When we use such an expression we personify a political unity, we introduce no
particular metaphysic: it is clear that men, in the name of France, have taken the
decision. But the very object of this book implies that we consider states as endowed
with intelligence and will.
DD“May the day soon come when our fellow citizens, close-pressed in our African France,
will overflow into Morocco and Tunisia, and finally establish that Mediterranean em¬
pire which will not only be a satisfaction for our pride, but which will certainly, in
the future state of the world, be the last resource of our greatness.” This text occurs at
the end of La France nouvelle, by Prevost-Pradol.
POWER, GLORY AND IDEA
79
Suez Canal have lost most of their value since they are too easily “closed” by
atom bombs, too easily “crossed,” too, by air transport). With Algeria inde¬
pendent, the security of Mediterranean shipping will not be threatened by
the Barbary pirates.
The demographic argument is presented in two radically different forms.
Space is still precious when it is empty or sparsely populated. We cannot
overestimate the historical influence of the fact that after the sixteenth cen¬
tury Europeans had at their disposal the empty spaces of America. In the
nineteenth century, when mortality was diminishing and the old birth rate
was being lowered only slowly, millions of Englishmen, Germans and Scan¬
dinavians, then Italians and Slavs were able to cross the Atlantic and occupy
the immensities of North America. Numbering sixty-five thousand at the
period of the Treaty of Paris, there are now over five million French Ca¬
nadians, less than two centuries later. Even today, if the objective of states
is that their populations should “increase and multiply,” the occupation of
empty space is the ideal means (whence the—truly diabolical—temptation to
empty space in order to reserve it for the victors: Elitler would not have
resisted the temptation).
On the other hand, the occupation of an already populated space raises
problems that vary according to the centuries. Princes once tended to measure
their greatness by the number of their provinces and their subjects. When the
number of men increased, so did that of laborers and soldiers. In the centuries
when underpopulation, a shortage of men, was feared, the extension of sover¬
eignty over inhabited lands passed for advantageous or beneficial. This
traditional conception was called into question by the liberal economists, ac¬
cording to whom commerce could and should ignore frontiers. The assumption
of sovereignty imposed administrative expenses upon the metropolitan coun¬
try without affording it any additional profit®
The anti-colonial argument of the liberals, which had wide influence in
England in the last century, but did not prevent the expansion of the
British Empire, was opposed by the apparent soundness of traditional ideas
and several phenomena originating in the industrial era. How could anyone
doubt that conquest was profitable, a proof and symbol of greatness, when it
was cheap in military terms and when the metropolitan country found in its
empire both raw materials at low prices and protected markets? Imperialists
and the Marxists were fundamentally in agreement as to the benefits of the
colonies: higher rates of profit, guaranteed outlets for manufactured products,
insured supply of raw materials. The only difference between the two lay in
the judgment of value set upon the enterprise and the goal attributed to it.
Marxists denounced an exploitation that was, in their eyes, the cause and goal
of imperialism; the imperialists justified by its civilizing mission an enterprise
whose advantages for the colonizing state they were not ashamed to proclaim.
The liberal argument again found an audience after the Second World
03 See below, Part II, Chap. IX.
8 o
THEORY
War, following the convergence of political motives and economic motives.
Either the colony did not include a European population, in which case the
principle of equality of peoples established the right to independence. Or else
the colony included a European population, in which case the principle of
individual equality forbade treating the natives as inferiors, and led to the
power of the greater number—that is, of the indigenous peoples—by means
of universal suffrage.
The imperial state discovered, at the same moment, that a “civilizing mis¬
sion” was expensive when taken seriously. Certain individuals, certain com¬
panies benefited from the colonial situation, but the balance-sheet for the
collectivity ceased to be positive, insofar as the creation of an administrative
and educational infrastructure and the improvement of the standard of living
figured among the obligations of the metropolitan country.
Between the advantage of possessing the territory and the cost of assuming
responsibility for its population, the European states, Great Britain first of all,
have chosen decolonization (or, more precisely, Great Britain has chosen,
France has gradually been forced to choose). The transfer of sovereignty in¬
volved diplomatic and military risks: instead of commanding, the ex-imperial
state was henceforth obliged to negotiate. The military forces of India were
no longer at the service of British interests in the Middle East. But, on the
military level too, the abandonment of sovereignty was less costly than a war
against nationalism. France has been weakened more by the Indo-Chinese
War than it would have been by an agreement with Ho Chi Minh, concluded
in 1946. Great Britain would have been weakened more by resistance to
Indian nationalism, even had such resistance been victorious over a genera¬
tion, than it has been by the transfer of sovereignty to the Congress Party
and the Arab League.
However summary, these analyses have permitted us to define two of the
fundamental factors in the historical transformation of goals: the techniques
of combat and -production change and, thereby, modify the strategic value
of positions, at the same time that the economic value of various natural and
human resources of the territory, in other words the modes of organization of
collectivities, authorize or exclude, in every period, certain modes of domina¬
tion. Conquerors, down through the ages, have rarely acknowledged that
victory imposed duties to a greater degree than it conferred rights. Superiority
of arms was equivalent to the superiority of a civilization. The conquered
were always wrong, and subjection seemed the legitimate sanction of defeat.
The chapter in which Montesquieu deals with conquest already belongs to
an age in which the judgment of arms no longer passed for the just verdict
from the tribunal of history or Providence^
0“lt is a conqueror’s responsibility to repair a part of the harm he has done. I there¬
fore define the right of conquest thus: a necessary, legitimate but unhappy power,
which leaves the conqueror under a heavy obligation of repairing the injuries done to
humanity.” ( L’Esprit des lois, X, 4 .)
POWER, GLORY AND IDEA
8 l
The doctrine of empires depends on concepts involving relations among
governed and governing, and among various populations, even more than on
concepts involving war and the privileges of force. When citizenship was
limited to a small number within the city-state, when only nobles bore arms
and owned laborers as property, no limit could rationally be set on the enter¬
prises of conquest: the number of subjects and slaves could increase without
a proportionate increase in the number of citizens. The ruling people re¬
mained free to accord or refuse citizenship—the Roman Empire long tolerated
a considerable number of populations subject to Rome, but not integrated
within the Roman civilization. Similarly, the kings of France and Prussia
were persuaded to increase their forces as their territories enlarged and the
number of their subjects increased. It was assumed that the desire of men
to obey one master rather than another did not count and, most of the time,
did not exist. The religious conflicts that had drenched Europe in blood con¬
firmed the merits of the old political wisdom: it is best to keep men from
meddling in their own business. In order to re-establish peace in Europe, it
had been necessary to order each and every man to believe in the truths of
the Church acknowledged by the prince.
The case was altered after the French Revolution, when two new ideas
gradually won men’s minds: the juridical equality of the members of the
collectivity; the aspiration of the governed to belong to a community of their
choice, a community of their own.
The first idea, carried to its logical consequences, implied the elimination
of the distinction between victors and vanquished within the collectivity, as
of the distinction between orders, i.e., between nobles and commoners. “Thus
a conqueror who reduces a conquered people to slaver}' ought always to re¬
serve to himself the means (for means there are without number) of restor¬
ing that people to their liberty.’01n the democratic age, we would say that
imperial domination finds its outlet either in accession to independence on
the part of the conquered populations, or in the integration of the colonies
with the metropolitan country in a multinational (more or less federal or cen¬
tralized) complex. The choice itself between these two outcomes is deter¬
mined less by the desires of statesmen than by the nature of the metropolitan
country. It is difficult for a strictly national state, like France, to become the
nucleus of a multinational community. A state with universal pretensions, like
the Soviet State, can attempt a policy of integration on a grand scale.
The second idea, intimately related to the first, is that self-determination
of the governed cannot be repressed, and should not be constrained by force.
The national idea, it is true, oscillates between two formulas, that of na¬
tionality embedded within the historical, if not the biological, being of
populations, and that of the voluntary decision whereby each man (or
each group) must determine the political collectivity to which he (or it) will
&hil, X, 3 .
82
THEORY
belong. According to the first formula, Alsace was more or less German in
1871; according to the second, it was French.
The national ideal is not entirely new, nor did the authentic citizens of the
city-states or monarchies obey just any prince. However, even the nobles
could pass from the service of one sovereign to that of another without
creating the scandal of treason. The extension of citizenship to all members
of the collectivity profoundly transformed the meaning of the national idea.
If all the subjects became citizens, or if the citizens refused to obey just any
master because they sought to participate in the state, political units could
no longer take for their objective the conquest of just any territory or just any
population. Moreover, the violation of this prohibition was generally “pun¬
ished” by the difficulty and the cost of governing recalcitrant populations.
In other words, the concrete objectives that political units choose do not
evolve with the techniques of combat and production alone, but also with
historical ideas associated with the organization and government of the col¬
lectivities. In the long run a state does not apply two philosophies, one in¬
ternally, the other externally. It does not keep both citizens and subjects un¬
der its orders indefinitely. If it seeks to keep subjects externally, it will end
by turning its own citizens into subjects.
The concrete objectives of states, in a given period, are still not precisely
defined by the state of techniques (of combat and of production) and his¬
torical ideas. We must also take into account what we shall call, with the
theoreticians of international law, custom. The conduct of states with regard
to each other, the procedures they consider legitimate, the cunning or the
brutality from which they abstain, are not directly determined by the organi¬
zation of the army or of the economy. Strategic-diplomatic conduct is a matter
of custom. Tradition bequeaths, from generation to generation, great or re¬
mote goals which statesmen sometimes refuse to forget, against all reason. In
1917, when the government of the Third Republic, in a secret agreement
with the Tsar’s government, upheld the Russian claims to the Dardanelles as
compensation for Russian support of its own claims to the left bank of the
Rhine, the custom of bargaining and traditional natural frontiers prevailed
over the techniques and ideas of the period. Perhaps economic and ideological
rationality prevail over the habits of the past and the passions of circum¬
stances, but they prevail only in the long run.
3. Offensive and Defensive
The two concepts of offensive and defensive , Clausewitz writes, are the
two principal concepts of strategy. Are they, and in what sense, the key con¬
cepts of foreign policy, that is, of diplomatic-strategic conduct?
When the negotiators, in the disarmament conferences, sought to distin¬
guish “offensive weapons” from “defensive weapons,” they were unable to
surmount the ambiguities: an aggressor nation can utilize defensive weapons,
POWER, GLORY AND IDEA
83
as a state under attack can utilize offensive weapons—supposing that these
notions, which have a meaning on the level of tactics or strategy, are valid
when applied to weapons.
What political meaning attaches to these notions, which originally concern
the conduct of operations or engagements? On the highest level of abstraction
I have distinguished offensive -power and defensive power —that is, the ca¬
pacity of a political unit to impose its will on others and the capacity of a unit
not to let the will of others be imposed upon it. In the diplomatic realm, the
defensive consists, for a state, in safeguarding its autonomy, maintaining its
own manner of life, not accepting subordination of its internal laws or of its
external action to the desires or decrees of others. The states called "small
powers” generally have—can only have—defensive ambitions. They seek to
survive as such, as seats of free decisions. On the other hand, the nations
called “great powers” desire to possess the capacity that we have called offen¬
sive—in other words, the capacity to act on other political units, to convince
or constrain them. The great powers must take the initiative, make alliances,
stand at the head of coalitions. A state of the first rank which makes use only
of its “defensive power” adopts an attitude of “isolationism,” it foregoes
participating in competition, it refuses to enter the system, it desires to be
left in peace. Isolationism—that of Japan in the eighteenth century or that of
the United States after the First World War—is not always praiseworthy in
itself. That of Japan had no serious consequences for other states, but that of
the United States distorted the calculations of force. Twice Germany ignored
the potential of the remote state which professed to abstain from world poli¬
tics.
On a lower level, an offensive is sometimes confused with a demand, a
defensive with conservation. In a given circumstance, the satisfied states—
generally those that dictated the terms of peace at the end of the last war-
desire the maintenance of the status quo, while the unsatisfied states desire
its modification. In the West, Germany after 1871 was a conservative state,
France a revisionist state, the stake being Alsace-Lorraine. After 1918 France
was totally conservative, while Germany pressed its demands on all diplomatic
fronts and on all frontiers.
The opposition between revision and conservation does not necessarily de¬
termine the distribution of roles and responsibilities at the moment when
hostilities break out. In other words, it is conceivable that the conservative
state will take the initiative in resorting to arms. For example, seeing that
the unsatisfied states are accumulating forces, it foresees the aggression that
it fears or judges inevitable. Montesquieu actually attributes some legitimacy
to these preventive aggressions or conservative offensives. ‘With states, the
right of natural defense sometimes involves the necessity of attacking; as, for
instance, when one nation sees that a continuance of peace will enable an¬
other to destroy it, and that to attack that nation is the only way to prevent its
8 4
THEORY
own destruction.® Israel’s operation in the Sinai, in November 1956, might
have been justified as "preventive aggression.”
The impact of two coalitions brings into conflict, on one side or the other,
conservative states and revisionist states: in 1914 Germany, conservative re¬
garding the territorial status in the west, took the initiative of war against
revisionist France, but within the framework of a generalized war. Lastly, a
state or a camp, without formulating precise demands, may have the sense of
some permanent injustice: in proportion to its force, it does not possess its
fair share of the wealth. It believes itself capable of conquering, and of hold¬
ing a great position upon victory. Before 19x4 Italy and France made more
specific, more assertive demands than Germany. Perhaps Germany was less
opposed to a test by arms than these two states, which were both more de¬
manding and less powerful.
Thus the opposition of the revisionist state and the conservative state is
often deceptive. The propensity to take the initiative in hostilities also de¬
pends first on the relation of forces, then on the chance of success which
each state or each side sees for itself. Conservatism is rarely complete, satis¬
faction rarely total. If the occasion warranted, the "satisfied” state would
modify to its advantage the frontiers of enemy or allied territories. It is not
always the defeated of the last war who start the next.
Similarly, by another paradox, the unsatisfied and aggressive state may de¬
liberately create the appearance of peaceful intentions. In July 1914 the slo¬
gan “localization of the conflict” was bandied by Vienna at the very moment
the Austrian cannon were shelling Belgrade. Not that the state drawing the
sword is necessarily acting in bad faith when it proclaims its desire to limit
the theater^of hostilities or the number of belligerents. If it desires not gener¬
alized war but political success, it has achieved its goals once other states in
the system refrain from entering the conflict. In 1914 Russia could not stop
the Austrian action against Serbia without creating at least the probability of
a generalized war. Before 1939 the conservative coalition could not stop the
unsatisfied Third Reich except by the threat of a generalized war. After the
reoccupation of the left bank of the Rhine, France had lost the opportunity
(which it owed to the Versailles Treaty) of a limited and effective counter¬
attack.
The objectives sought and the role at the origin of the hostilities do not
suffice to determine the character of foreign policy. The final judgment also
depends on the consequences that the victory of a state or a side would pro¬
duce. Did Athens start the Peloponnesian War, and did the Athenians con¬
sciously desire hegemony over the Greek city-states? Was the Germany of
Wilhelm II responsible (and to what degree) for the explosion of 1914?
Whatever the answer given to these questions, it is certain that had Sparta
POWER, GLORY AND IDEA
85
been defeated, Athens would have dominated the whole of the Greek world;
had the Western Allies lost, Germany would have possessed, on the Conti¬
nent, a superiority of forces that would have signified, for the other European
nations, the equivalent of a loss of autonomy. Now, since history offers few
examples of hegemonic states which do not abuse their force, the state to
which victor)? would give hegemony is regarded as aggressive, whatever the
intentions of those governing it.
Still more offensive appears the foreign policy of a state that tends to
overthrow not only the relation of forces but the internal status of states.
Revolutionary France was not necessarily aggressive on the diplomatic level,
she did not have to take the initiative of war; however, she had no choice
but to attack kings and princes at the point where they were most vulnerable,
on the principle of legitimacy itself. A great deal has been written about the
diplomacy of the Republic, and historians have frequently asked how far
it prolonged monarchical diplomacy by continuing its objectives, if not its
methods. Yet insufficient attention has been paid to one piece of evidence
which escaped no contemporary: it was not within the power of men to
decide whether the diplomacy of the Republic was or was not in conformity
with custom. It was in essence revolutionary, insofar as French ideas spread
across Europe and toppled thrones. A state’s policy is revolutionary if its
victory would involve the collapse of traditional states, the ruin of the old
principle of legitimacy.
None of these antitheses—conservative-revisionist, attacked-aggressor, tra¬
ditional-revolutionary—is expressed on the level of strategy by the opposition
between defensive and offensive. Even when the state is aggressive or revo¬
lutionary, the military leader can order his generals to remain on the defen¬
sive, temporarily if forces are not mobilized, permanently if he pins his hopes
on the enormous extent of his territory or the patience of his population.
Initiating hostilities does not imply the choice of a given strategy. Ger¬
many, even if she had been the victim of an aggression in 1914, would have
had to apply the Schlieffen Plan—to attack France during the first phase of
the conflict in order to put her hors de combat before turning against Rus¬
sia. France, who regarded herself as attacked, launched her troops into
Alsace. Strategy, whether offensive or defensive, on the whole or on a given
front, is not determined by state policy alone—the initiatives it has taken
and the objectives it seeks—it is also a function of the relation of forces,
the order of hostilities and the judgments of the military leaders as to the
respective merits of the two ways of “using engagements in the service of
the war.”
We find here the formulas complementary to those we analyzed in the
first chapter. On the lowest tactical level the action of the soldier, the
company, the battalion, the regiment obeys strictly military considerations.
The day a battle is fought, the leader seeks to win it, although he takes
greater or less risks, aims at a more or less complete success, depending on
86
THEORY
the total circumstances and the goals of each side. On the other hand, the
establishment of the plan of war depends, in theory and in practice, on
both the state’s policy and the relation of forces or the geography of the
conflict. But if the military leader must always take political considerations
into account, there is no correspondence between the various meanings of
the diplomatic offensive and defensive, as we have just distinguished them,
and the two modes of strategy distinguished by Clausewitz.
In the Far East, Japan from 1931 or 1937 clearly pursued an aggressive
and revolutionary policy. She had constituted the Empire of Manchukuo
out of Manchuria, which she had cut off from China; she attempted, and
made no mystery about it, to create a “new order,” which would embrace
Asia from Mukden to Djakarta. It was Japan that took the initiative in
hostilities against China in X937, against the United States, Great Britain
and the Dutch possessions in I94X. Yet the strategy adopted was offensive-
defensive: during the first phase, taking advantage of a local and temporary
superiority, Japanese admirals and generals counted on winning brilliant
successes and securing territorial stakes; during the second phase, they ex¬
pected to remain on the defensive and wear down the United States’ will
to win. This combination of a policy of conquests and an offensive-defensive
strategy leading to a negotiated peace had, from the first, little chance of
success. A state rarely achieves such grandiose designs if it has not achieved
a total victory, in military terms. But it remains true that a revisionist, con¬
quering, revolutionary state may adopt a defensive strategy, relying on at¬
trition, both physical and moral, of its adversaries, without seeking to defeat
or disarm them.
On the other hand, a state without ambitions of conquest, without re¬
sponsibility in the initiation of hostilities, occasionally aims at a victor}? of
annihilation, and prefers, to indirect methods and oblique operations, a
brutal onslaught against the enemy’s strength. Must we say that the military
leader who seeks absolute victory, while he plans limited objectives, acts in
an irrational manner? Such a conclusion would be false. It all depends on
whether the enemy is prepared to yield before exhausting its means of
resistance: Hitler would have continued to the very end of the struggle,
even without hope. An absolute victory in military terms, even if it is not
indispensable for certain political achievements, adds to the prestige of
anus and thereby constitutes a contribution to the victor’s diplomacy. Lastly,
after the initiation of hostilities, it is natural that the military leaders should
try to win an absolute victory, whatever the advantage their nation’s foreign
policy intends to derive from it.
The choice of an offensive or defensive strategy, the desire for a total or
limited victory, the preference for direct assault or for indirect advance—
none of these decisions is separated from, but none is entirely determined
by, policy. One can win an absolute victory by wearing the enemy down,
one can annihilate the enemy forces in order to dictate the terms of a mod-
POWER, GLORY AND IDEA
8 ?
erate peace, one can count on the enemy’s lassitude to retain one’s conquests
—which does not alter the fact that, in general, the aggressive state takes
the offensive, that the revolutionary state adopts a strategy of annihilation
and seeks an absolute victory. The complexity of relations among sovereign
states, the many interpretations of offensive or defensive policy, and the
combination of the strategic and diplomatic meanings of these terms, had
persuaded seventeenth- and eighteenth-century authors not to introduce a
juridical discrimination between aggressor and victim and to accord all
belligerents the advantage of legality. Conceptual analysis shows at least the
reasons for this discretion.
The War of 1914 breaks out. The murder at Sarajevo was the occasion:
to what degree was it the cause? Did the historical circumstances, the rivalry
of states, the race for arms make the explosion inevitable sooner or later? If
the event—assassination, ultimatum—had been merely the occasion, with what
right do we attribute to a state and certain men a responsibility that devolves
upon the total circumstances?
Apparent cause and underlying causes do not necessarily agree. Many
authors have asserted that the commercial rivalry between Great Britain and
Germany, of which there was no question in July 1914, was a more active
cause of the war than the violation of Belgian neutrality. Should we say
that this violation was the pretext invoked by the English statesmen or the
motive of their decision?
It is not enough to have distinguished occasion and cause, pretext and
motive, to weigh merits against faults. Once arms speak, the outcome is
more important than the origin. What objectives do the belligerents seek?
What are the probable results of the victory of one side or the other? In
short, what are the stakes of the war?—stake being defined as the divergence
between the two worlds, the one that Athens would control or the one Sparta
would control, the one the Second or Third Reich would govern, and the
one the Russians, the English and the Americans would govern. In this
sense the stake is never entirely determined in advance, although what is “at
stake” is more or less vaguely perceived by the actors.
The stake itself is not the last word in the analysis. Perhaps peoples do
not fight for the motives attributed to them. Perhaps the true causes are
buried in the collective unconscious. Perhaps aggressiveness is a function
of the number of men or of the number of young men. Perhaps sovereign
states are condemned to fight each other because they fear each other.
The doctrinaires of European public law who receive the approbation of
Karl Schmitt^ recommended to the prince moderation and peace, but being
aware of the uncertainty of human judgments and the ambiguity of political
actions, they urged princes not to confuse law and morality. The aggressor,
ElilDer Nomos der Erde im Vdlkerrecht des Jus Europaeum, Cologne, 1950.
88
THEORY
supposing he is known without the shadow of a doubt, would be morally
culpable: he would nonetheless remain a legal enemy and not a common-
law criminal.
4. The Indeterminacy of Diplomatic-Strategic Behavior
Human behavior can always be translated in terms of means and ends,
provided that the action is not a simple reflex and that the actor is not
insane. What I have said, what I have done cannot fail to have—in my
eyes, if not in other people’s—certain consequences: nothing keeps us from
considering after the fact the consequences as the ends and the steps that
have preceded them as the means. The means-ends schema, zweckrational
according to Max Weber’s concept, is nonetheless not the necessary ex¬
pression of the psychical mechanism or even of the logic of action. If we
have referred to means and ends in the course of the two preceding chap¬
ters, it is merely to specify the nature of diplomatic-strategic behavior and,
thereby, the character and limitations of the theory of international rela¬
tions.
We started with the opposition between economic behavior and diplo¬
matic-strategic behavior; the former has a relatively determined objective
(although it assumes, depending on circumstances and persons, a different
content), that is, the maximization of a quantity which, on the highest
level of abstraction, would be called value or utility; the latter has no other
initial characteristic than that of occurring in the shadow of war and, con¬
sequently, of being thereby obliged to take the relation of forces into ac¬
count. The plurality of means and ends, which we have analyzed in the
course of the preceding chapters, permits us to grasp more clearly the op¬
position of these two kinds of behavior.
The theoretician of economics is careful not to claim that he imposes or
even that he knows from the outside the goals that individuals seek to
achieve. He attributes to individuals a scale of preferences or transitive
choices: if a person prefers A to B and B to C, he will not prefer C to A. It is
by their choice that economic subjects manifest preferences, whose equal ra¬
tionality (or irrationality) the economist admits by hypothesis. The man
who prefers leisure to increased revenue is not more rational than the mil¬
lionaire who ruins his health to accumulate profits. Theory overcomes the
chaos of individual choices by means of money, a measurement of values and
a universal means of acquiring goods. The maximization of monetary rev¬
enues is regarded as a rational goal since the individual is free to make
what use he will of the quantity of money acquired. Money is only a means
of buying merchandise, the choice of this merchandise depends on each
man: the theoretician, without violating the intimacy of a conscience, while
respecting the diversity of tastes, reconstructs the economic system step by
step, limiting himself to positing that the subject, in order to maximize bis
satisfactions, seeks to maximize the monetary means of realizing them. When
POWER, GLORY AND IDEA
89
the behavior of an individual is in question, the economist has no other
definition of interest than the scale of preferences, variable from individual
to individual, or the maximization of the utility measured by monetary
quantities.
In shifting from individual interest to collective interest, economists have
encountered many difficulties, which have often been discussed. To keep
to the major one, any determination of collective interest, if we continue to
refer to individual preferences, requires a comparison between the satisfac¬
tions of some and the dissatisfactions of others. It is tempting to assume
that the poor man whose income increases somewhat derives a satisfaction
therefrom which is greater than the dissatisfaction of the rich man whose
income somewhat decreases. By such reasoning we justify the transfer of
revenues from the richer to the poorer classes, and the tendency to reduce
the inequality of income. I myself share this way of thinking and the moral
ideas that inspire it, hut such reasoning is not rational, in the sense of the
evident or the demonstrated, as certain mathematical propositions or even
propositions relative to the Walrasian schema of equilibrium are rational. The
comparison of one individual’s satisfactions or dissatisfactions with an¬
other’s has no psychological meaning, in that it introduces a mode of con¬
sideration radically alien to that which is expressed in the theory of in¬
dividual economic behavior. Pareto, to my way of thinking, was not wrong
in considering that only the point of the maximum of interest for a col¬
lectivity is the object of a rational determination. As long as it is possible to
increase the satisfactions of some without diminishing those of others, it is
legitimate to disregard the conflicts between individuals and groups. No
one is harmed and some receive benefit. With the condition that he ignores
the dissatisfaction occasioned to some by the spectacle of the fortune of
others, and that he neglects the consequences of the redistribution of in¬
come, the statesman can claim kinship with science so long as he strives
to attain the maximum of interest for the collectivity.
Pareto himself did not consider that this maximum of interest for the col¬
lectivity was, thereby, the maximum of interest of the collectivity. Consid¬
ered as a unit, the collectivity does not necessarily intend to insure the
greatest possible number of its members the greatest possible number of
satisfactions. It may have power, prestige or glory as its objective. The sum
of individual satisfactions is not equivalent to the advantage of the political
unit as such. Yet diplomatic-strategic behavior, by definition, acts as a func¬
tion of the interest of the collectivity, to use Pareto’s language, or again as
a function of the “national interest,” to use the language of the theo¬
reticians of international relations. Is this interest, in abstract terms, sus¬
ceptible of a rational definition which could serve as a criterion or an ideal
for a statesman? The three preceding chapters, it seems to me, dictate a
negative answer to this question.
To give a “rationalizing interpretation” of diplomatic-strategic behavior,
9 °
THEORY
and to elaborate a general theory of international relations comparable to
economic theory, many authors have made the concept of power or Macht
a fundamental one, equivalent to the concept of value (or utility). But, as
a matter of fact, this concept cannot fulfill this function.
Let us suppose that we understand by power the potential of resources:
the latter could not in any way be considered as a rationally imposed ob¬
jective. Or else we are concerned with resources that can be mobilized for
external rivalry: in this case, to take the maximization of potential as the
one supreme goal would be equivalent to granting absolute primacy to force
or collective power. But a collectivity that extends its territory, increases its
population, becomes different: it declines or it flourishes. The classical
philosophers have always believed that there was an optimum dimension for
political units. With what right would the theoretician of foreign policy
justify those obsessed by power, or incriminate those whose supreme goal
was the coherence or efficacy of the state?
Suppose we meant by power not the potential of resources but force,
that is, the resources actually mobilized with a view to the conduct of
foreign policy? With what right would the maximizing of the degree of
mobilization be an obvious or rational objective? In every period, in response
to external danger and popular sentiment, the chief of state tries to deter¬
mine the appropriate degree of mobilization. Here, too, there is no reason
for subordinating everything to the exigencies of diplomatic-strategic mo¬
bilization.
Might we, finally, define power as the capacity to impose one’s will on
others? In that case, power is not a final goal, either for the individual or
for collectivities. Policy is always ambitious, it aspires to power because
political action involves, in essence, a relationship among human beings,
an element of power. Yet grand policy wants such power not for itself,
but to carry out a mission. Similarly, a collectivity does not desire power
for itself, but in order to achieve some other goal—peace, glory—so as to
influence the future of humanity, through the pride of propagating an idea.
In other words, for a collectivity to maximize resources or force is to
maximize its means of acting on others. One cannot suppose, even in a
simplifying hypothesis, that a collectivity has no other objective than to
possess the maximum means of acting on others. To maximize effective
power is to maximize a reality difficult to grasp (the collectivity that most
influences others is not always the one that most consciously attempts to
impose itself upon them); it is also to distort the intrinsic meaning of
diplomatic-strategic action. Effective power may well constitute the ambition
of certain men or of certain peoples: it is not in itself a rational objective.
We may disregard the objection that economic subjects do not seek to
maximize utility any more than “diplomatic subjects” seek to maximize power.
There is a radical disparity between the two cases. Of course, homo
economicus exists only in our rationalizing reconstruction, but the relation
POWER, GLORY AND IDEA
9 1
between homo economicus and tbe concrete economic subject differs fun¬
damentally from the relation between the ideal-type diplomat (defined by
the search for the maximization of resources, of force or of power), and the
historical diplomat. The two “economic men”—one of theory and the other
of practice—resemble each other as a retouched photograph resembles a
snapshot. The theoretical economicus is more true to himself than the prac¬
tical one; he has perfect information and makes no errors in calculation. But
if either seeks the maximization of the same quantity (monetary income,
production, long- or short-term profit), the former’s perfect calculations help
us to understand, and sometimes to correct, the latter’s imperfect calcula¬
tions. The diplomaticus of theory, who would have as his goal the maximi¬
zation of resources, of actual forces, or of power, would not be an idealized
portrait of the diplomats of all ages, he would be the caricatured simplifica¬
tion of certain diplomatic personages at certain periods.
The calculation of forces, which the ideal diplomat cannot avoid, is
neither the first nor the last word of diplomatic-strategic behavior. Sympa¬
thies and hostilities at a given moment do not all result from the relation of
forces: the diplomat attempts to maintain an equilibrium, but certain sympa¬
thies or hostilities are given as irreducible. He does not first of all seek the
maximization of his resources, he desires such and such a province, such and
such a strategic position, such and such a symbolic city. The eventual sub¬
ordination of the abstract objective of force to the concrete and immediate
objective is contrary neither to the logic of human action nor to the logic
of rivalry among states. To drive the infidels out of the Holy Land, for a
man who believes in Christ and the Passion, is an enterprise reasonable in
a different way than the pursuit of force for its own sake. Even the desire
for revenge is not more irrational than the will to power. Political units are
in competition: the satisfactions of amour-propre, victory or prestige, are no
less real than the so-called material satisfactions, such as the gain of a
province or a population.
Not only are the historical objectives of political units not deducible from
the relation of forces, but the ultimate objectives of such units are legiti¬
mately equivocal. Security, power, glory, idea are essentially heterogeneous
objectives which can be reduced to a single term only by distorting the
human meaning of diplomatic-strategic action. If the rivalry of states is
comparable to a game, what is "at stake” cannot be designated by a single
concept, valid for all civilizations at all periods. Diplomacy is a game in
which the players sometimes risk losing their lives, sometimes prefer victory
itself to the advantages that would result from it. Quantitative expression
of the stakes is thereby impossible: not only do we not know in advance
what the stake is (what the victor would do) but, for the warrior, victory
suffices in itself.
The plurality of concrete objectives and of ultimate objectives forbids a
rational definition of “national interest,” even if the latter did not involve, in
92 -
THEOBY
itself, the ambiguity that attaches to collective interest in economic science.
Collectivities are composed of individuals and groups, each of which seeks
its own objectives, seeks to maximize its resources, its share of the national
income or its position within the social hierarchy. The interests of these
individuals or of these groups, as they express themselves in actual behavior,
are not spontaneously in accord with each other, and added together they do
not constitute a general interest. Even on the economic level, the general
interest is not deduced from private or collective interests by some mysterious
calculation of average or compensation. Rate of growth, distribution of re¬
sources between consumption and investment, proportion allotted to welfare
and proportion devoted to external action are determined by decisions that
wisdom may inspire but that science cannot determine.El
A fortiori, the national interest is not reducible to private interests or
private-collective interests. In a limited sense this concept is useful, it
rouses the citizens to an awareness of the political unit of which they are
temporary members, which has preceded them and will survive them. It
reminds present-day leaders that security and greatness of the state must be
the objectives of “diplomatic man,” whatever their ideology.
It does not follow from this that national interest might, can or should be
defined apart from the internal regime, the aspirations characteristic of the
different classes, the political ideal of the state: the collectivity does not
always change objectives when it changes its constitution, historical idea or
ruling elite. But how can the political units maintain, through revolu¬
tions, the same ambitions and the same methods?
Of course, formally, the conduct of all diplomats offers similarities. Any
statesman seeks to recruit allies or to reduce the number of his enemies.
Revolutionists spontaneously resume, after a few years, the projects of the
regime they have overthrown. Such incontestable continuity results from the
national tradition, imposed by the imperatives of the calculation of forces.
It remains to be shown that statesmen, inspired by various philosophers,
act the same way in the same circumstances, and that different parties, to be
rational as diplomatic men, must calculate the national interest in the same
manner. Now, such a demonstration seems inconceivable to me, and the
hypothesis itself absurd El
How could democrats, fascists and Communists between the two wars
have sought the same objectives? Any elite in power hopes for the reinforce¬
ment both of its regime and of the state for which it is responsible. But as
Hitler’s victory would involve the spread of totalitarian regimes, the demo¬
crats in any other European country could only have favored the Third
Reich by sacrificing themselves on the pretext that their fatherland would
EUThe only science that might eventually substitute foi wisdom would be that which
has been developed in the theory of games; it would formulate the rules according to
which a general will is revealed in the contradictions among individual wills.
EUSee below, Chap. X.
POWER, GLORY AND IDEA
93
be stronger in a National Socialist Europe. Can we characterize the decision
of statesmen who accept their own death in the hope that their nation will
be stronger under other masters as incontestably rational? Does logic demand
setting the strength of the state above the freedom of its citizens?
Should a German of good family have desired the triumph of Hitler’s
Germany, which in his eyes betrayed the true Germany? When each state
or each camp embodies an idea, the individual risks being torn between
his allegiance to a community and his commitment to his ideal. Whether he
chooses the physical fatherland or the spiritual fatherland, he cannot be
approved or condemned by the logic of politics alone. The national interest
of political unity as such seems concretely determined only in circum¬
stances where rivalry is reduced to a pure competition whose stake is limited
and in which none of the combatants risks his existence or his soul.
If diplomatic behavior is never determined by the relation of forces alone,
if power does not serve the same function in diplomacy as utility in econ¬
omy, then we may legitimately conclude that there is no general theory of
international relations comparable to the general theory of economy. The
theory we are sketching here tends to analyze the meaning of diplomatic
behavior, to trace its fundamental notions, to specify the variables that must
be reviewed in order to understand any one constellation. But it does not
suggest an “eternal diplomacy,” it does not claim to be the reconstruction of
a closed system.
We have given this first part of our work the title “Concepts and Sys¬
tems.” The elaboration of concepts relative to the behavior of units taken
individually leads us to the description of typical situations.
chapter IV
On International Systems
I call an international system the ensemble constituted by political units
that maintain regular relations with each other and that are all capable of
being implicated in a generalized war. Units taken into account, in their
calculation of forces, by those governing the principal states, are full-fledged
members of an international system.
I have hesitated to use this term system to designate an ensemble whose
cohesion is one of competition, which is organized by virtue of a conflict,
and which exits most powerfully on the day when it is lacerated by re¬
course to arms. A political system is defined by an organization, by the
reciprocal relations of the parties, by the cooperation of elements, by the
rules of government. To what degree do we find the equivalent in the case
of an international system?
The following pages will attempt to offer answers to these questions. Let
us say, for now, that the term system seems useful as it is employed in the
expression party system. In this case, too, the term designates the ensemble
constituted by the collective actors in competition. Party competition, it is
true, is subject to the rules of a constitution, for which international law
does not offer an exact equivalent. But the number, respective size, and
means of action of political parties are not provided for by the legal texts:
parties are opposing units par excellence. The difference from international
actors remains essential as long as parties regard the vote, and states regard
bombs or missiles, as the ultima ratio. When parties no longer disdain ma¬
chine guns, or if states should some day be assimilated into a universal
empire, the national and international actors tend, or would tend to become,
identified with each other.
An international system, like a party system, involves only a small number
of actors. When the number of actors increases (there are more than a hun¬
dred states in the United Nations), that of the chief actors does not increase
proportionally, and sometimes does not increase at all. We note two super-
ON INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS
95
powers in the world system of 1950, at most five or six great powers, actual
or potential. Therefore, the principal actors never have the sense of being
subject to the system in the manner in which an average-size firm is subject
to the laws of the market. The structure of international systems is always
oligopolistic. In each period the principal actors have determined the system
more than they have been determined by it. A change of regime within one
of the chief powers suffices to change the style and sometimes the course
of international relations.
1. Configuration of the Relation of Forces
The first characteristic of an international system is the con figuration of
the relation of forces , a notion that itself involves several aspects: what are
the limits of the system? what is the distribution of forces among the various
actors? how are the actors situated on the map?
Before the present period—more precisely before 1945—no international
system included the entire planet. Scarcely more than a century ago, the
ambassador of Her Britannic Majesty had difficulty obtaining an audience
from the Emperor of China, refused to submit to rites he regarded as hu¬
miliating (genuflection), and, to offers of commercial relationships, received
this scornful response: What could his remote little country produce which
the Middle Empire was not capable of producing as well or better? At the
time, there were two reasons that combined to exclude China from the
European system: physical distance prohibited China from taking military
action in Europe, while limiting European military capacity in the Far
East; moral distance between the cultures made dialogue difficult, re¬
ciprocal comprehension impossible.
Which of these two criteria, politico-military participation or communica¬
tion, is the more important in defining membership in a system? The first,
it seems to me. Only the actors performing in the plays belong to a troupe.
Performance, for the international troupe, is generalized war, potential or
real: it matters little whether one of the actors speaks a somewhat different
language. Certainly during the historical periods when a system has ex¬
isted, in other words, when relations have not been merely occasional and
anarchic, the actors belong for the most part to the same zone of culture,
worship the same gods, respect the same prohibitions. The Greek city-states,
like the European nations, were aware of both their fundamental kinship
and the permanence of their rivalry. But the Persian Empire, which the
Greeks considered as alien—barbarian—and the Turkish Empire, whose
Islamic faith the Christian sovereigns could not ignore, were involved in
the conflicts and the calculations of the Greek city-states or the European
monarchies. They were an element in the relation of forces, although they
were not an integral part of the transnational cultural ensemble.
Uncertainty of limits does not involve merely the duality of the diplomatic
THEORY
96
or military participation and of the community of culture. It also involves the
enlargement, sometimes rapid and unforeseeable, of the diplomatic field, as a
function of technology and of political events. By subjecting the Greek city-
states to their law, the Macedonian kings created a political unit whose re¬
sources made distant undertakings possible. The international system was
extended as the units themselves enlarged, and thereby became capable of
including, in thought and in action, a larger historical space.
Before 1914 the European states neglected the eventuality of United States
intervention. The United States was not, apparently, a military power, and
did not play a part on the European stage. It is not without interest to reflect
on this error, which falsified calculations.
Economically, the United States had been, for centuries, inseparable from
Europe. European history would have been quite different if, in the nine¬
teenth century, the Old World’s surplus population had not found rich and
empty lands to cultivate across the Atlantic. Great Britain, because of her
mastery of the seas, had possessed, during the great wars of the Revolution
and the Empire, at least a share of the resources of the other continents. The
European conquests since the sixteenth century should have shown that
henceforth distance was no longer an insurmountable obstacle to military
action. At the beginning of the nineteenth century, progress in means of
transportation seemed limited to maritime services. Great Britain had estab¬
lished herself in India, but it took Napoleon almost as long as Caesar to go
from Rome to Paris. In the nineteenth century and at the beginning of the
twentieth, on the other hand, the means of land transportation developed to a
remarkable degree, due to the railroad, and then to the internal-combustion
engine. Such progress made ignorance of the elementary rule of reciprocity
still more unjustifiable: if European military forces could be present in India
or in Mexico, why should American military force not be present in the Old
World?
This unawareness of the possible return to Europe, in uniform, of the
European emigrants settled across the Atlantic seems to me to have had many
causes. The Spaniards had required few expeditionary forces to conquer Cen¬
tral and South America. The Europeans, at the very period when they ruled
the world, reserved for the struggles that retrospectively seem to us quite
fratricidal, the majority of their resources. It was difficult for them to imagine
transporting mass armies across the Atlantic. Experts tended to overestimate
the importance of the officers’ corps and still more of the aristocratic class
from which this corps was, or was supposed to be, recruited. The stereo¬
typed image, “a commercial state or a military state,” prevented a recognition
of the new fact of the approximate proportionality between industrial po¬
tential and military potential. Further, why should the II nited States, hostile
to “entanglement” from the beginning of its existence, eager to keep out of
European conflicts, participate in a war whose origin was obscure and whose
ON INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS
97
stalce was ambiguous? This latter reasoning was not radically false, but it did
not take into account the possibility that the first battles would not decide the
results and that the hostilities would extend over several years. In other
words, statesmen and generals were wrong to overlook the fact that materially
the United States could send a great army to Europe. Failing to anticipate the
war’s amplification due to the draft, to industry, and to the approximate
equality of forces, they were surprised when the conflict’s dynamism involved
the United States in battle and extended the European diplomatic field to
America.
This field, whose limits are traced by the techniques of transportation and
combat at the same time as by relations among states, is divided into political
units and groupings of units (temporary alliances or permanent coalitions).
The geography of the diplomatic field is not modified, or is modified only
slowly. On the other hand, the strength of each unit and the groupings are
modified, sometimes rapidly. Therefore the so-called constants imposed by
geography are often deceptive. It is not geography, but the projection on a
map of a certain relation of forces which suggests the idea of friendship or
hostility, original or permanent. Once this relation of forces changes, another
policy becomes reasonable. Early in this century, French textbooks of diplo¬
matic history extolled the wisdom of an alliance with a state on the other
side of the potential enemy, a tradition that seemed dictated by geography
and was actually suggested by a configuration of the relation of forces. A
European state would have to be stronger than France to justify this kind of
alliance, which aimed at re-establishing equilibrium and creating a threat of
war on two fronts. Such an alliance with Poland or the Soviet Union against
the Bonn Republic, or tomorrow against a unified Germany (extended to
the Oder-Neisse Line), would be senseless. Even a reunified Germany would
be weaker than Western Europe (France supported by the Anglo-American
nations), or the Soviet bloc. Why should France attempt to weaken further,
by surrounding it, a neighbor not to be feared?
Of course, the geographical distribution of alliances exerts an influence on
the course of diplomacy. According to the space they occupy, the political
units have different resources, different objectives, different dreams. Alliances
have a relation to the respective positions of states—the most powerful ally
is less alarming if it is remote. If it is not a “permanent ally,” a neighboring
state easily becomes an enemy. Nevertheless, the essential aspect of a system
is the configuration of the relation of forces, space itself assuming a diplo¬
matic significance only as a function of the localization of great and small
powers, of stable and unstable states, of sensitive points (in military or po¬
litical terms), and pacified zones.
To define what we mean by the configuration of relation of forces^ it is
01 n German, Gestaltung der Kraftverhaltnisse.
THEORY
98
simplest to contrast two typical configurations, the multipolar configuration
and the bipolar configuration. In one case, diplomatic rivalry occurs among
several units, which all belong to the same class. Various combinations of
equilibrium are possible; reversals of alliance belong to the normal process
of diplomacy. In the other, two units outclass all the rest, so that equilibrium
is possible only in the form of two coalitions, the majority of medium and
small states being obliged to join the camp of one great power or the other.
Whatever the configuration, political units constitute a more or less official
hierarchy, essentially determined by the forces that each is supposed capable
of mobilizing: at one extreme, the great powers, at the other, the small states,
the former claiming the right to intervene in all affairs, including those of
states not concerning them directly, the others having no desire to intervene
outside their narrow sphere of interest and action, sometimes even resigned
to submitting to the decisions, regarding a subject that concerns them di¬
rectly, taken in concert by the great powers. The latter’s ambition is to in¬
fluence and control circumstances, that of the small states to adapt themselves
to circumstances which, essentially, do not depend on them. Such a contrast,
of course, is oversimplified and expresses opinions rather than the reality: the
manner in which the small states adapt themselves to circumstances contrib¬
utes to the form circumstances actually assume.
The distribution of forces in the diplomatic field is one of the causes that
determine the grouping of states. In an extreme case, two states that have no
real motive for dispute can become hostile to each other by a “fatality of po¬
sition.” Two dominant states are almost inevitably enemies (unless they are
closely united), merely because an equilibrium exists only on condition that
each of the two belongs to the opposite camp. When the rivalry' itself creates
the hostility, the mind or the passions subsequendy find countless means of
justifying it. In war, too, fury is sometimes the result of the conflict itself,
not of the conflict’s stake.
This is an extreme case. Alliances axe not the mechanical effect of the re¬
lation of forces. Simplifying, one might say that some great powers are in
conflict because of the divergence or contradiction of their interests or their
claims; other powers, great or small, join one side or the other, either out of
interest (they hope to gain more from the victory of one camp than from that
of the other), or emotional preference (the sympathies of the population in¬
cline to one side more than to the other), or a concern for equilibrium. Great
Britain had the reputation of taking a position exclusively for this last reason.
Generally indifferent to details of the map of the Continent, her only aim
was to forestall the hegemony or empire of a single power. This pure policy
of equilibrium was logical, for Great Britain had sought neither territory nor
population on the Continent (since the Hundred Years’ War). It was so
important to England’s security and prosperity to keep Continental forces
from uniting against her that British diplomacy could not indulge itself in
the luxury of ideological considerations. But to be reasonable, she had to ap-
ON INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS
99
pear both honorable and cynical: to keep her promises to allies during hos¬
tilities, and never to regard an alliance as permanent.
If the policies of the Continental states did not seem as detached from
ideological or affective contingencies as the policy of the island state, it was
not the fault of statesmen, but of circumstances. The European monarchs
disputed provinces and positions of vantage. Invasions often left bitter mem¬
ories. Even in the period of dynastic wars, sovereigns did not switch ally and
enemy with complete freedom. After the annexation of Alsace-Lorraine, no
French government, however authoritarian, would have agreed to a complete
reconciliation with Germany.
Alliances and hostilities are determined, sometimes by the mere relation of
forces, sometimes by a dispute with a specific stake, most often by a com¬
bination of these two factors. With regard to lasting hostilities or alliances,
the opposition of interests or the convergences of aspirations are primary.
The long period of wars between France and Great Britain was controlled in
part by the inevitable hostility of the island state to the chief state on the
Continent, but at the same time, the colonial enterprises of France and Eng¬
land were in conflict on remote territories and on the seas: logically, Eng¬
land’s constant goal should have been the destruction of the French fleet or,
at least, the incontestable superiority of the English fleet, so that mastery of
the seas might guarantee the expansion and security of the British Empire.
In the twentieth century the mere calculation of forces does not account for
British policy. After all, in the abstract, England could have sought allies on
the Continent to forestall American hegemony: yet such a thing was out of
the question. To London, American hegemony still seemed to retain some¬
thing of English hegemony about it, whereas German hegemony would have
been felt as alien, humiliating, unacceptable. A change from the pax Britan-
nica to the pax Americana did not involve a change of universe, and pride,
rather than the soul itself, suffered. A pax Germanica could not replace
the pax Britannica without England resisting to the death: only a military
catastrophe could have cleared the path from one to the other.
In the last analysis, nations do not fight each other only to maintain a po¬
sition of strength.
2. Homogeneous and Heterogeneous Systems
The conduct of states towards each other is not controlled by the relation
of forces alone: ideas and emotions influence the decisions of the actors. A
diplomatic circumstance is not completely understood so long as we limit
ourselves to describing the geographical and military structures of the alli¬
ances and hostilities, to situating on the map the points of strength, the lasting
or occasional coalitions, the neutral powers. We must also grasp the determi¬
nants of the behavior of the principal actors—in other words, the nature of
the states and the objectives sought by those in power. Thus the distinction
between homogeneous systems and heterogeneous systems seems to me funda-
IOO
THEORY
mentallDz call homogeneous systems those in which the states belong to the
same type, obey the same conception of policy. 1 call heterogeneous, on the
other hand, those systems in which the states are organized according to
different principles and appeal to contradictory values. Between the end of
the wars of religion and the French Revolution, the European system was
both multipolar and homogeneous. The American-European system, since
1945, is both bipolar and heterogeneous.
Homogeneous systems afford, on first analysis, greater stability. Those in
power are not unaware of the dynastic or ideological interests that unite them,
despite the national interests that set them against each other. The recognition
of homogeneity finds its extreme and formal expression in the formula of the
Holy Alliance. Against the revolutionaries, the rulers of the sovereign states
promised each other mutual support. The Holy Alliance was denounced by
liberals as a conspiracy of kings against peoples. It had no “national justifica¬
tion,” since the change of regime did not involve, in the last century', an over¬
throw of alliances: a victory of the revolution in Spain would perhaps have
endangered the Bourbons, not France. At present, each of the two blocs tends
to revive, for internal use, a Floly Alliance formula. Soviet intervention in
Hungary was equivalent to proclaiming the right of Russian armies to in¬
tervene in every Eastern European nation to repress counterrevolution (as a
matter of fact, any insurrection against the so-called socialist regime). In the
West, too, the regimes are virtually allied against revolution. The Floly Alli¬
ance against counterrevolution or revolution is in the end necessary to the
survival of each of the two blocs.
The homogeneity of the system favors the limitation of violence. So long
as those in power, in the conflicting states, remain aware of their solidarity,
they incline to compromise. The revolutionaries are regarded as common ene¬
mies of all rulers, and not as the allies of one of the states or alliances. If the
revolutionaries were to win in one of the states, the regimes of the other
states would also be shaken. The fear of revolution incites military leaders
either to resign themselves to defeat or to limit their claims.
A homogeneous system appears stable, too, because it is foreseeable. If all
the states have analogous regimes, the latter must be traditional, inherited
down through the years, not improvised. In such regimes, statesmen obey
time-tested rules or customs: rivals or allies know on the whole what they can
expect or fear.
Lastly, by definition, the states and those who speak in their name are led
to distinguish between enemy state and political adversary. State hostility
does not imply hatred, it does not exclude agreements and reconciliations after
battle. Statesmen, whether victors or vanquished, can deal with the enemy
all borrow this distinction from a remarkable work by Panoyis Papaligouras: Theorie
de la societe Internationale, a thesis at the University of Geneva, 1941. The book was
called to my attention by Mile. J. Hersch.
ON international systems
IOI
without being accused of tieason by ideologists reproaching them for having
spared the “criminal’® or by “extremists” accusing them of sacrificing the na¬
tional interests to assure the survival of their regimeH
Heterogeneity of the system produces the opposite. When the enemy ap¬
pears also as an adversary, in the sense this term assumes in internal conflicts,
defeat affects the interests of the governing class and not only of the nation.
Those in power fight for themselves and not only for the state. Far from
kings or leaders of the republic being inclined to regard the rebels of the
other camp as a threat to the common order of warring states, they consider
it normal to provoke discord among the enemy. The adversaries of the faction
in power become, whatever their stripe, the allies of the national enemy and
consequently, in the eyes of some of their fellow citizens, traitors. The “Holy
Alliance” situation encourages those in power to subordinate their conflicts
in order to safeguard the common principle of legitimacy. In what we call the
situation of ideological conflict, each camp appeals to an idea, and the two
camps are divided, with a number of citizens on either side not desiring, or
not desiring wholeheartedly, the victory of their own country, if it were to
mean the defeat of the idea to which they adhere and which the enemy in¬
carnates.
This crisscrossing of civil and inter-state conflicts aggravates the instability
of the system. The commitment of states to one camp or the other is jeopar¬
dized as a result of internal rivalries: hence the chief states cannot ignore
them. Party struggles objectively become episodes of conflict among states.
When hostilities break out, a compromise peace is difficult, and the overthrow
of the government or of the enemy regime almost inevitably becomes one of
the goals of the war. The phases of major wars—wars of religion, wars of
revolution and of empire, wars of the twentieth century—have coincided with
the challenging of the principle of legitimacy and of the organization of
states.
This coincidence is not accidental, but the causal relation can be, ab¬
stractly, conceived in two ways: the violence of war creates the heterogeneity
of the system or else, on the other hand, this heterogeneity is, if not the
cause, at least the historical context of great wars. Although we can never
categorically retain one of the terms of the alternative and exclude the other,
internal struggles and inter-state conflicts do not always combine in the
same way. Heterogeneity is not only relative, it can also assume various forms.
In 1914, was the European system homogeneous or heterogeneous? In
many respects, homogeneity seemed to prevail. The states recognized each
other. Even Russia, the least liberal among them, permitted certain oppo¬
nents the right to exist, to criticize. Nowhere was the truth of an ideology
EAs Thorstein Veblen reproached the Allied statesmen in 1918.
LilAs Guillemin and other leftist writers accused the peace party that triumphed in
1871. By continuing a revolutionary war, might not the fate of arms have been
changed?
102
THEORY
decreed by the state or considered indispensable to the latter’s solidarity. Citi¬
zens readily crossed borders and the requirement of a passport, at Russia’s
borders, caused scandal. No ruling class regarded the overthrow of the regime
of a potentially hostile state as its goal. The French Republic did not oppose
the German Empire, any more than the latter opposed the empire of the
Tsars. The French Republic was allied with the empire of the Tsars ac¬
cording to the traditional requirements of equilibrium.
This homogeneity, apparent as long as peace prevailed, revealed many
flaws which war was to enlarge. Within it the two principles of legitimacy,
birth and election, whose conflict had constituted one of the stakes of the
wars of revolution and empire, had concluded a precarious truce. Compared
to today’s fascist or Communist regimes, the Kaiser’s and even the Tsar’s
empires were “liberal.” But the supreme power, the sovereignty, continued
to belong to the heir of the ruling families. The heterogeneity of the absolutist
regimes (the sovereign is designated by birth) and of the democratic regimes
(the sovereign is designated by the people) existed potentially. Of course, so
long as Tsarist Russia was allied with the Western democracies, neither of
the two camps could exploit this opposition to the full. After the Russian
Revolution, Allied propaganda did not hesitate to do so.
More seriously, the relationship between peoples and nations had also not
been stabilized in the nineteenth century. The German Empire and the King¬
dom of Italy had been constituted in the name of the right of nationality.
But in Alsace-Lorraine the Reich had given the national idea a meaning that
the liberals of France and elsewhere had never accepted: was nationality a
destiny that language or history imposed on individuals, or the freedom of
each man to choose his state? Further, the territorial status of Europe, based
on dynastic heritage and the concern for equilibrium, was not compatible
with the national idea, whatever the latter’s interpretation. Austria-Flungary
was a multinational empire like the Ottoman Empire. The Poles were neither
German nor Russian nor Austrian, and they were all subject to an alien law.
Once war was declared, all belligerent states attempted to appeal to the
national idea in order to mobilize its dynamism to their advantage. The em¬
perors made solemn and vague promises to the Poles, as though they vaguely
realized that the partition of Poland remained Europe’s sin. Perhaps, too, the
universalization of the profession of arms suggested to those in power that
henceforth war must have a meaning for those who risked their lives in it.
This heterogeneity of the principle of legitimacy (how are those in power
to be designated? to what state should the populations belong?) did not con¬
tradict the fundamental cultural relationship of the members of the Euro¬
pean community. It did not inspire any of the states with the desire to de¬
stroy the other’s regime. In peacetime each state regarded the other’s regime
as a matter outside its own concern. Out of liberalism, France and Great
Britain gave asylum to the Russian revolutionaries, but they gave them neither
money nor weapons to organize terrorist groups. On the other hand, after
1916 or 1917, to justify the determination to continue the war to absolute
ON international systems
103
victory, to convince the Allied soldiers that they were defending freedom, to
dissociate the German people from their regime, Allied propaganda and di¬
plomacy attacked absolutism as the cause of the war and of the German
“crimes,” proclaimed the right of peoples to self-determination (hence the
dissolution of Austria-Hungary) as the fundamental condition of a just peace,
and finally refused to deal with those rulers responsible for igniting the
holocaust. Semi-homogeneous in 1914, the European system had become ir¬
remediably heterogeneous by 1917 as a result of the fury of the struggle and
the Western powers’ need to justify their determination to win decisively.
Similarly, on the eve of the Peloponnesian War, the Greek city-states
were relatively homogeneous. They had fought together against the Persians,
they worshiped the same gods, celebrated the same festivals, competed in the
same games. Their economic or political institutions belonged to the same
family, were variations on the same theme. When war to the death was
launched between Athens and Sparta, each camp recalled that it appealed to
the authority of democracy or aristocracy (or oligarchy). The goal was less to
encourage the combatants’ ardor than to weaken the adversary and to make
allies within the opposite camp. This heterogeneity, which concerns only one
element of politics, often suffices to transform an inter-state hostility into
passionate hostility. The meaning of a common culture is effaced and the
belligerents are now aware only of what separates them. Perhaps, in fact,
the heterogeneity most inimical to peace or moderation is precisely the kind
that stands out against a background of community.
However, heterogeneity of the Greek city-states during the Peloponnesian
War, or of the European states in 1917 or in 1939 was less well defined than
the heterogeneity of the Greek city-states and the Persian Empire, of the
Greek city-states and Macedonia, of the Christian kingdoms and the Ot¬
toman Empire, and a fortiori, of the Spanish conquerors and the Inca or
Aztec empires, or of the European conquerors and the African tribes. These
examples, in abstract terms, suggest three typical situations: 1. Political units,
belonging to the same zone of civilization, have often had regular relations
with political units that, outside this zone, were clearly recognized as differ¬
ent or alien. The Greeks, as a consequence of their idea of the free man,
regarded the subjects of the Oriental empires with some condescension. Islam
distinguished the Christian kingdoms from the Ottoman Empire without
prohibiting the alliance of the King of France and the Commander of the
Faithful. 2. Spaniards on the one hand, Incas and Aztecs on the other, were
essentially different. The conquistadors triumphed, despite their smaller num¬
bers, because of the resentment of the tribes subject to the ruling peoples of
the empires as well as because of the terrifying effectiveness of their weapons.
They destroyed the civilizations that they neither could nor desired to under¬
stand, without even being aware of committing a crime. 3. Perhaps the re¬
lationship between the Europeans and the African Negroes did not differ,
fundamentally, from the foregoing between Spaniards and Incas. Today’s
anthropologists urge us not to overlook the specific “culture” of those whom
104
THEORY
our fathers called savages, and not to establish a hierarchy of values too hast¬
ily. Nonetheless, I think a distinction is justified between the archaic life
of the African tribes and the pre-Columbian civilizations.
With regard to cruelties or horror, we cannot establish an order of greater
and less, depending on whether we are dealing with wars among related
and heterogeneous units, wars among units belonging to different civiliza¬
tions, wars fought by conquerors against civilizations they were incapable of
understanding, or lastly wars between civilized men and savages. All con¬
querors, whether Mongols or Spaniards, have killed or pillaged. The belliger¬
ents have no need to be alien to each other in order to be fierce: political
heterogeneity, often created or at least amplified by war, is enough. Further,
the conflict between units of the same family or civilization is often more
intense and furious than any other, because it is also a civil and religious
war. Inter-state war becomes civil war once each camp is linked to one of the
factions within some of the states; it becomes a war of religion if the in¬
dividuals are attached to one form of the state more than to the state itself,
if they compromise civil peace by insisting on the free choice of their God or
their Church.
The international systems that include related and neighboring states are
both the theaters of great wars and the space destined to imperial unification.
The diplomatic field is enlarged as the units assimilate a greater number of
the former elementary units. After the Macedonian conquests, the city-states
together constituted one unit. After the conquests of Alexander and of
Rome, the Mediterranean basin as a whole was subject to the same laws and
a single will. As the Roman Empire developed, the distinction between cul¬
tural family and state allegiance tended to disappear. The Empire was in
conflict, on its frontiers, with the “barbarians,” and internally with the rebel
populations or non-“civilized” masses. Earlier adversaries had become fellow
citizens. Retrospectively, most wars seem to be civil wars, since they set in
opposition political units destined to be blended into a superior unit. Before
the twentieth century the Japanese had fought major wars only among them¬
selves, the Chinese had fought among themselves and against barbarians,
Mongols and Manchus. Indeed, how could it have been otherwise? Collec¬
tivities, like persons, are in conflict with their neighbors, who are other, even
if they are physically or morally quite close. Political units must be huge in
order for the neighbor to belong to a civilization that the historian, with the
perspective of centuries, considers authentically other.
After 1945 the diplomatic field expanded to the limits of the planet, and
the diplomatic system, despite all internal heterogeneities, now tends to a
juridical homogeneity, of which the United Nations is the expression.
3. Transnational Society and International Systems
International systems, as we have said, are comprised of units that have
regular diplomatic relations with each other. Now such relations are normally
ON INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS
io 5
accompanied by relations among individuals, who make up the various units.
International systems are the inter-state aspect of the society to which the
f emulations, subject to distinct sovereignties, belong. Hellenic society or Eu¬
ropean society in the fifth century B.c. or in the twentieth century a.d. are
realities that we shall call transnational, rather than inter- or supranational.
A transnational society reveals itself by commercial exchange, migration of
persons, common beliefs, organizations that cross frontiers and, lastly, ceremo¬
nies or competitions open to the members of all these units. A transnational
society flourishes in proportion to the freedom of exchange, migration or com¬
munication, the strength of common beliefs, the number of non-national or¬
ganizations, and the solemnity of collective ceremonies.
It is easy to illustrate the vitality of transnational society by examples.
Before 1914 economic exchanges throughout Europe enjoyed a freedom that
the gold standard and monetary convertibility safeguarded even better than
legislation. Labor parties were grouped into an International. The Greek
tradition of the Olympic Games had been revived. Despite the plurality of
the Christian Churches, religious, moral and even political beliefs were fun¬
damentally analogous on either side of the frontiers. Without many obstacles
a Frenchman could choose Germany as his place of residence, just as a Ger¬
man could decide to live in France. This example, like the similar one of
Hellenic society in the fifth century', illustrates the relative autonomy of the
inter-state order—in peace and in war—in relation to the context of trans¬
national society. It is not enough for individuals to visit and know each other,
to exchange merchandise and ideas, for peace to reign among the sovereign
units, though such communications are probably indispensable to the ulti¬
mate formation of an international or supranational community.
The contrary example is that of Europe and the world between 1946 and
1953 (and even today, although since 1953 a certain transnational society,
over the Iron Curtain, is being reconstituted). Commercial exchanges between
Communist nations and the nations of Western Europe were reduced to a
minimum. Insofar as they existed, they pertained only to states (at least on
one side). The “Soviet individual” had no right to deal with a “capitalist in¬
dividual,” except by the intermediary of public administration. He could not
communicate with him without becoming suspect. Inter-individual communi¬
cations were generally forbidden unless they were the express of inter-state
communications: officials and diplomats chatted with their Western col¬
leagues, but essentially in the exercise of their functions.
This total rupture of transnational society had a truly pathological char¬
acter: subsequently the Soviet Union has been represented in scientific con¬
gresses as in athletic competitions, receives foreign tourists and allows several
thousand Soviet citizens to visit the West each year, and no longer strictly
forbids personal contacts with Westerners. Russian wives of English aviators
have been able to rejoin their husbands. Commercial exchanges have gradu¬
ally broadened. Yet it is doubtful if this restoration of transnational society
io6
THEORY
has modified essentials: heterogeneity, with regard to the principle of legiti¬
macy, the form of the state and the social structure, remains fundamental.
The Christian community has only a limited scope because political faith is
stronger than religious faith, the latter having become a strictly private mat¬
ter; lastly, no organization, whether political, syndical, or ideological, can
unite Soviet and Western citizens unless it is in the open or clandestine service
of the Soviet Union. The heterogeneity of the inter-state system irremediably
divides transnational society.
In every period, transnational society has been regulated by customs, con¬
ventions or a specific code. The relations that the citizens of a nation at war
were authorized to maintain with the citizens of the enemy state were con¬
trolled by custom rather than by law. Conventions among states specified the
status of the citizens of each established on the territory of the other. Legisla¬
tion made legal or illicit the creation of transnational movements or the
participation in those professional or ideological organizations intended to be
supranational.
From a sociological viewpoint, I am inclined to call private international
law the law that regulates this transnational society as we have just charac¬
terized it, that is, the imperfect society made up of individuals who belong
to distinct political units and who are, as private persons, in reciprocal rela¬
tion. It is entirely to be expected that many jurists regard as municipal law
all or part of such private international law. Whether in familial or com¬
mercial relations, the norms applicable to foreigners or to relations among
nationals and foreigners are an integral part of the system of norms of the
state involved. Even if these norms result from an agreement with another
state, an essential modification does not follow: agreements on double taxa¬
tion, for instance, guarantee a hind of reciprocity of treatment, by each of
the signatory nations, of the other’s citizens, at the same time that they
protect the taxpayers of each state against a twofold imposition of taxes. The
consequences of these inter-state conventions take place within the legal
system of each.
On the other hand, the propositions, prohibitions and obligations re¬
corded in the treaties among states constitute elements of public interna¬
tional law. We have, in the two preceding sections, considered the con¬
figuration of the relation of forces, then the homogeneity or heterogeneity
of the systems. The control of international relations is located at the meet¬
ing point of the two previous studies. To what degree and in what sense
are inter-state relations, in peace and in war, subject to law in the same way
that individual relations, in the family and in business, are today and in a
sense always have been®
Inter-state relations, like other social relations, have never been abandoned
ilThere has always been social control; there is not always a juridical elaboration or
a fortiori a written law.
ON INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS
I07
to the purely arbitrary. All so-called higher civilizations have distinguished
between members of the tribe (or the city, or the state) and the foreigner,
and between various kinds of foreigners. Treaties were known from earliest
antiquity—by the Egyptian Empire as by the Hittites. Every civilization has
had an unwritten code that dictated the manner of dealing with ambas¬
sadors, prisoners, or even enemy warriors in combat. What new features does
public international law provide?
States have concluded many agreements, conventions or treaties, some of
which concern transnational society, while others concern both that and
the international system. To the first category belong, for instance, postal
conventions, those conventions relative to hygiene, to weights and measures;
to the second belong questions of maritime law. In the collective interest
of states and not of individuals alone, international conventions control the
utilization of seas or rivers, the means of transportation and of communica¬
tion. The extension of international law expresses the broadening of the
collective interests of transnational society or of the international system, the
increasing need to submit to law the coexistence of human collectivities,
politically organized on a territorial basis, on the same planet, upon the
same seas and under the same sky.
Yet does international law thereby modify the essence of inter-state re¬
lations? Controversies relating to international law® ordinarily occur on
an intermedian’ level between positive law on the one hand and ideologies
or philosophies on the other, a theoretical level that might be called, to
borrow the expression of F. Perroux, “implicitly normative.” The obligations
of international law are those which result from treaties signed by states
or from custom. On the other hand, “the right of peoples to self-determina¬
tion,” “the principle of nationalities,” “collective security” are vague formulas,
ideologies that influence statesmen, eventually even the interpretation jurists
make of positive law. It cannot be said that they serve as the basis of a
system of norms, that they involve, for states, specific privileges or duties.
Now the jurist who seeks to define the nature of international law at¬
tempts to put positive law in a conceptual form, to discover its specific
meaning. But this interpretation is not included in positive law itself. The
latter allows various interpretations. Juridical theory, even more than eco¬
nomic theory, conceals an element of doctrine. It brings to light the meaning
of juridical reality, but this apparent discovery is also an interpretation, in¬
fluenced by the theoretician’s idea of what international law should be.
In the unanimous opinion of jurists, an important, if not the principal,
datum of international law is the treaty. Yet treaties have rarely been
signed freely by all the high contracting parties. They express the relation
of forces; they consecrate the victory of one and the defeat of the other.
ElWe do not add in each case the word ■public. But it is understood that the inter¬
national law to which we henceforth refer is what jurists call public international law.
io8
THEORY
Now the principle of pacta sunt servanda, if it is not the originating norm
or the moral basis of international law, is nevertheless its condition of
existence. But international law thereby tends to assume a conservative
quality. It is the victor of the latest war who invokes the principle against
the claims of the vanquished, the latter having meanwhile reconstituted
his forces. In other words, the stabilization of a juridical order based on
the reciprocal commitments of states would be satisfactory in one of the
two following hypotheses: either if the states had concluded treaties that
were considered equitable by all, or if there existed a claim acknowledged
by all and capable of being satisfied by reference to indisputable criteria of
justice.
It is true that treaties follow the formula pacta sunt servanda with the
words rebus sic stantibus: it remains to be seen whether subsequent changes
justify modification of the treaty. The Western powers have the juridically
incontestable right to occupy a part of the former capital of the Reich.
But their presence there was related to the project of a united Germany.
If this project is abandoned and the division of Germany accepted, is it
advisable to modify the treaties because the context has changed? To this
question there is no juridical answer.
If treaties are the source for international law, it is because the subjects
of the law are states. But by the same token, major historical events, those
by which the states are bom and die, are external to the juridical order.
The Baltic states have ceased to exist, they are no longer subjects of law;
nothing the Soviet Union does on the territories that, in 1939, were subject
to the Estonian or Lithuanian sovereignty any longer relates to interna¬
tional law, at least in the eyes of those of the states that have ceased to
“recognize” Estonia, Lithuania, and Latvia (that is, almost every state).
When a state is crossed off the map of the world, it is the victim of a viola¬
tion of international law. If no one comes to its aid, it will soon be forgotten
and the state that has delivered the coup de grace will be no less welcome
in the assemblies of so-called peaceful nations. Ideologies scarcely permit us
to affirm or deny, in the abstract or even in specific circumstances, that
certain peoples have or do not have the right to constitute themselves into
a nation. In other words, even the unbiased observer often hesitates to
Ebr, if one prefers, they are the creators of this order. Certain modem jurists, H.
Kelsen for instance, deny that the birth and death of states are metajuridical facts.
Granting the theory according to which recognition is more a political than a juridical
act, and by no means a formative one, they affirm that international law describes as
a “state" those cases that merit this designation. “The juridical existence of the new
state does not depend on recognition, hut on the objective fulfillment of certain con¬
ditions assigned by international law for a state to be recognized." (“Theorie generale
du droit international public,” Recueil des cours de VAcademie de droit international,
42, 1932, p. 287.) If we admit this system, we would say that historical events create
conditions of fact which are qualified by international law (and not by the will of
existing states), as the birth or death of a state.
ON INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS
I09
assert that a specific violation of the territorial status quo is just or unjust,
conforms to or violates, in the long or short run, the interest of the nation
directly involved, or of the international community.
The laws of states come into effect, one might say, the day the states
themselves are recognized. Non-organized rebels do not benefit from any
legal protection. The legitimate authority treats them as criminals and must
treat them as such if it wishes to preserve itself. If the rebels are organized
and exercise authority over a part of the territory, they obtain certain bel¬
ligerent rights; the situation becomes that of a civil war and, in practice,
the distinction tends to be effaced between “legitimate authority” and “reb¬
els,” which appear as two rival governments, the outcome of the war de¬
ciding the legality or illegality of the belligerents. International law can
merely ratify the fate of arms and the arbitration of force. In a few years
the Algerian FLN changed from a band of “rebels” to “a government in
exile.” In a few more, in the name of national sovereignty, it functioned
freely within the frontiers of an independent Algeria.
Jurists have elaborated the rules that are to be imposed upon states or
that the latter ought to impose in case of civil war. In fact, practice varies,
even in modem times, as a result of many circumstances. There are, as we
have seen, two extreme cases: the homogeneous system can lead to the
Holy Alliance, to the common defense of the established order, to the re¬
pression by the French army of the Spanish Revolution of 1827 or by the
Russian army of the Hungarian Revolution of 1848. On the other hand, in
a heterogeneous system, each camp supports the rebels opposing a regime
favorable to the enemy camp. The rules of “non-intervention” weTe elab¬
orated and more or less applied during intermediate periods, when neither
powers nor revolutionaries had partisans across the frontiers. If there exists
neither a popular nor a royal 'Internationale, states abstain from siding with
the sovereign or the rebels, because in fact the victory of the one or the
other does not profoundly affect them.
Juridical norms need to be interpreted. Their meaning is not always
evident and their application to a specific case leads to controversy. Now
international law does not determine the organ that, in regard to inter¬
pretation, holds the supreme power. If states have not promised to submit
their cases to the International Court of Justice^ each signatory actually
reserves the right of interpreting the treaties in its own way. As states have
different juridical and political conceptions, the international law to which
they subscribe will involve contradictory interpretations, will be split, in
fact, into many orders, based on the same texts but leading to incompatible
results.
Moreover, states need only fail to “recognize” the same states or the same
governments, to reveal the scope of these incompatible interpretations. Sup¬
posing that states agree on their conduct with regard to “rebels” or “legal
GDOr if they remain judges of the application of such a promise.
110
THEORY
government,” it is enough that a group of men be rebels in the eyes of
some and, in the eyes of others, represent the legal authority, for the
juridical order, embracing a heterogeneous system, to reveal its internal con¬
tradiction. States will not attach the same descriptions to the same situa¬
tions of fact. The FLN was treated as a “band of rebels” by some, as a legal
government by others. The government of the German Democratic Re¬
public is a “so-called government” or an “authentic government.” The cross¬
ing of the 38th Parallel by the North Korean armies was a "civil-war
episode” or an “act of aggression.”
It will be objected that such interpretations are not probable to the same
degree, and there is no denying the fact. The Korean demarcation line
had been drawn by agreement between the Soviet Union and the United
States. The FLN “rebels” exerted no regular power over any part of the
Algerian territory in 1958. Objectively, to an observer applying traditional
criteria unburdened by ideology, one interpretation would be preferable to
another. But why should states apply this interpretation if it is not favorable
to their undertakings? States are anxious to maintain the juridical order
that suits their common interest when they recognize each other’s regimes.
But this reciprocal recognition is limited, in a heterogeneous system, by
ideological rivalry. Each camp seeks not necessarily to destroy the states in
the other camp, but to weaken or overthrow their regimes: juridical in¬
terpretation, even when it is concretely improbable, is utilized as an in¬
strument of subversive war, a means of diplomatic pressure.
Lastly, supposing that the community of states is in agreement as to the
true interpretation (in Hungary, the legal government was that of Imre
Nagy, the insurrection was staged by the people and not by foreign agitators
or American agents), it is still necessary to punish or constrain the state
violating the law. Here, too, international law differs, on an essential point,
from municipal law. The only effective sanction against the state that has
committed the illicit act is the use of force. The guilty state also possesses
arms, it does not agree to submit to the judgment of an arbitrator or to the
vote of an assembly. Hence an effort to enforce the law will involve a
risk of war. Either Gribouille or Gandhi: to punish the violators of the
law, a war is precipitated which it was the law’s function to forestall; or
else the injustice is merely proclaimed and endured, although the con¬
querors are usually less sensitive to non-violence than the British of the
twentieth century.
Does this international law, which involves neither indisputable inter¬
pretation nor effective sanction, which applies to subjects whose birth and
death it is limited to certifying, which cannot last indefinitely but which
cannot be revised, does this international law belong to the same genre as
municipal law? Most jurists reply in the affirmative, and I shall not con¬
tradict them. I prefer to show differences between kinds rather than deny
membership in the same genre.
ON INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS
III
4. Legalize War or Outlaw It?
The very title of Grotius’ famous work, De Jure Belli et Pads, does not
treat the entire substance of international law, but certainly covers its prin¬
cipal objects. Yet this formula suffices to suggest the dilemma confronting
jurists and philosophers: Must international law legalize war or, on the
contrary, proscribe it? Must it foresee or exclude the possibility of war?
Must it limit or outlaw war?
Before 1914 the answer, given by history, was unambiguous. European
public international law had never taken the outlawing of war as its object
or principle. Quite the contrary, it provided the forms in which war must
be declared, it forbade the use of certain means, it regulated the modes of
armistice and the signing of peace, it imposed obligations upon the neutral
powers with regard to the belligerents, upon the belligerents with regard
to civilian populations, prisoners, etc. In short, it legalized and limited war,
it did not make it a crime.
War being legal, the belligerents could regard each other as enemies with¬
out hating or vituperating each other. States fought, not persons. No doubt
a war’s legality did not settle the moral question of discovering whether or
not it was just. But the belligerent, even when responsible for an unjust
war, still remained a legal enemy®
Why did the classical jurists maintain moral judgments as to the respective
conduct of states in conflict side by side with juridical judgments which
legalized the conflicts for both sides? The reason was clearly indicated in
the works of the seventeenth and above all the eighteenth century: granted
that monarchs, if they are wise and virtuous, should not wage war for
glory or amusement, covet lands or wealth that do not belong to them,
yet how could sovereigns neglect the requirements of their security? If a
prince accumulates so many forces that he will soon be in a position to
crush his neighbors, will the latter passively suffer the destruction of an
equilibrium that is the only guarantee of security in inter-state relations?
The classical jurists were not only aware of the ambiguities we have
analyzed above, the necessary distinction between initiating hostilities and
aggression, between the responsibility for origins and the responsibility for
the stakes; they admitted the moral legitimacy of action dictated hy the
requirements of equilibrium, even if this action were aggressive. They
would have subscribed, with varying degrees of reservation, to Montes-
GDFor instance, Emer de Vattel, in Le Droit des gens ou principes de la loi naturelle
appliques a la conduite et aux affaires des nations et des souverains (1758), Book III,
Chap. 3, paragraph 39: “However, it may happen that the contenders are each acting
in good faith; and in a doubtful cause it is still uncertain on which side the right may
be. Since, then, the nations are equal and independent and cannot make themselves
judges of each other, it follows that in any case susceptible of doubt, the arms of both
sides making war must equally pass as legitimate, at least as to external effects and
until the cause is decided.” Or again, more concisely: “War in form, as to its effects,
must be regarded as just on either side." (Book III, Chap. 12, paragraph 190.)
112
THEORY
quieu’s formula quoted above, according to which "the right of natural
defense sometimes involves the necessity of attacking.” Hence it became
difficult to establish with certainty which was the true aggressor (and not
the apparent aggressor). The morality of equilibrium involved a kind of
casuistry and did not exclude recourse to arms.
Rousseau and Hegel alike have furnished extreme expressions of the key
ideas of this European law of nations. In the Contrat social, Rousseau
writes: “War is not a relation between man and man, but between state and
state, in which individuals are enemies only occasionally, not as men nor
even as fellow citizens, but as soldiers. Not as members of their nation,
but as its defenders. Lastly, each state may have as its enemy only other
states, and not men, since among things of different natures, no true relation
can be deduced.” In a purely inter-state war, individuals have no motive
for hating each other, and a victorious state must cease doing harm to the
subjects of the enemy state, once the latter admits defeat. Violence is
limited to the clash of armies.
Still more radical are Hegel’s texts, in the last part of the Philosophy of
Law. “International law results from relations of independent states. Its con¬
tent in and for itself has a prescriptive form because its realization depends on
distinct sovereign wills.” Such a formula is equivalent to suggesting that
because of the plurality of sovereign states, the concrete obligations of in¬
ternational law cannot be enforced by sanctions: they remain prescriptive,
like morality.
“The basis of international law as a universal law which must be valid
in and for itself among states, insofar as it differs from the specific content
of contracts, is that treaties must be respected. Pacta sunt servanda. For it is
upon them that the obligations of states in relation to each other rest. But
since their relation has their sovereignty as its principle, they are, in re¬
lation to each other, in the state of nature and do not have their law in a
universal will authoritatively established over and above them, but their
reciprocal relation has its reality in a particular will.” The formula is pre¬
cisely the one suggested by the analyses of the preceding section. Inter¬
national law consists of commitments made, implicitly or explicitly, by states
to each other. Since states do not lose their sovereignty the day they
make these commitments, war remains possible either because the parties
EHVattel has reservations as to Montesquieu’s formula, preferring confederations to
preventive war in order to maintain equilibrium, yet he writes CBook III, Chap. 3,
paragraph 42): “It is unfortunate for the human race that one can almost always
presume the will to oppress where one finds the power to oppress without punishment.
... It is perhaps unprecedented that a state should receive some notable increase in
power without giving others good cause for complaint. . . And lastly this formula
on the legitimacy of preventive attack: “One is justified in forestalling a danger by
reason of both the degree of appearance and the greatness of the evil by which one
is threatened.”
ON international systems
”3
are not in agreement as to the interpretation of the treaties, or because
one or the other desires to modify its terms.
"On the other hand, even in war as a non-juridical situation of violence
and contingency, there exists a connection in the fact that states recognize
each other as such. In this connection they are valid for each other as
existing in and for themselves. So that in war itself, war is determined as
necessarily transitory.” War is the juridical state, foreseen in advance, that
suspends most of the obligations that states contract toward one another
in peacetime, but that do not thereby lose all legal character. The bellig¬
erents do not employ any and all means, and when violence breaks out
they do not forget the future restoration of their juridical relations (a
valid proposition, on condition that the very existence of the state is not the
stake of the hostilities).
This classical conception had always seemed unsatisfactory to some phi¬
losophers; it was scarcely compatible with the obligatory character of law,
and it became unacceptable to popular opinion after the First World War.
So many dead, so much material destruction, so many horrors could no
longer be accepted as in accord with the course of human events. War must
no longer be an episode in inter-state relations, it should be outlawed, in
the true sense of the word. The victors having decreed that the van¬
quished were responsible for the outbreak of hostilities, the initiation of
hostilities was regarded, retrospectively, as criminal. A League of Nations
was established whose task was to maintain the peace. Ten years later, at
the instigation of the United States, the Kellogg-Briand peace pact pro¬
claimed still more formally the illegality of war as a political instrument.
The juridical system of the League of Nations and of the Kellogg-
Briand peace pact collapsed because the dissatisfied states sought to modify
the established order and because the international organ did not have
the means either to impose by peaceful methods the changes justice eventu¬
ally required or to stop the revolutionary states. When Japan transformed
Manchuria into Manchukuo and was condemned by the League of Na¬
tions, she left Geneva. The aggression was flagrant, but what could the
League do if the states with power were determined not to use it? Similarly,
Germany left Geneva when it did not obtain satisfaction in the matter of
disarmament.
The Italian iivasion of Ethiopia did not differ much from other European
undertakings in Asia or Africa. But since Ethiopia had been admitted to
the League of Nations, since the principle of equality of nations, whether
great or small, civilized or barbarian JlB had been proclaimed, the Italian
conquest could not be tolerated without destroying the very foundations
of the juridical order bom of the First World War and French policy.
Ell Supposing that one can still, according to the ideas of our epoch, distinguish the
one from the other.
THEORY
II 4
Sanctions were voted and partially applied, but the League refrained from
applying the sanction that had the greatest likelihood of being effective
(petroleum). Yet let us recall, the member states of the League of Nations,
even the two major ones alone (France and Great Britain), outclassed
Italy, which Germany, then rearming, could not support. The risk that
Italy would answer the threat of force with force was slight, so striking
was the disparity between the aggressor’s resources on the one hand, and
those of the conservative powers on the other. Either because Paris or
London did not wish to upset the Fascist regime, or because they wished
to avoid any risk of war whatever, only those sanctions that could neither
paralyze Italy nor provoke a military rejoinder from her were applied.
Whatever the motives of statesmen, it was apparent that governments and
peoples were not accepting the sacrifices of conflict for a cause that would
not have been or would not have seemed strictly national. If the inter¬
national law that forbids aggressions and conquests has its origin in trans¬
national society, the latter did not exist or existed only ineffectually, judging
by the emotions and desires of men.
Juridical formalism, seeking to exclude war as a means of settling dif¬
ferences or modifying territorial status, has not been abandoned in the
wake of failure, landmarked by the wars in Manchuria, Ethiopia, China,
and finally the double, generalized war in Europe and the Far East. In
1945 an attempt was made to use the international law outlawing war to
punish the Nazi leaders. During the Nuremberg trials “the conspiracy
against peace” was only one of the indictments made against the leaders of
the Third Reich, and war crimes do not concern us in the present context.
On the other hand, the attempt to shift from aggression, an international
crime, to the determination and punishment of the guilty illustrates an
aspect of the problem that appears once international law tries to deduce
all the consequences of “outlawing war.”
Among the belligerents, one—state or bloc—is juridically criminal. What
is the result of this “incrimination” of war that was once merely called unjust?
Optimistically, let us suppose that the criminal state is defeated. Flow is it
to be punished, and where are the criminals? Suppose we punish the
state itself—in other words, amputate its territory, forbid it to arm, and
deprive it of a share of its sovereignty. Now what matters most is that the
clauses of the peace treaty prevent war’s return: is it wise that the desire
for punishment, however legitimate, should influence the treatment of the
enemy and the clauses of the peace treaty? And we are considering, let us
recall, the optimistic hypothesis. It is easy to imagine the use that the
victorious Reich would have made of its right to punish the “criminal”
states (Poland, France, Great Britain).
If it is a question of punishing not the state or the nation but the
persons by whose agency the state has committed the "crime against the
peace,” a single formula would be quite satisfactory, the one that occurs in
ON INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS
115
several speeches of Sir Winston Churchill: One man, one man alone. If one
man alone has taken the decisions that have committed a people, if one
man alone possessed absolute power and acted in solitude, then this man
incarnated the criminal state and deserves to be punished for the nation’s
crime. But such a hypothesis is never completely fulfilled, the leader’s com¬
panions have shared in his decision, have conspired with him against peace
and for conquest. How far is the search for the guilty to be carried? To
what degree are the duties of obedience or national solidarity to be con¬
sidered as absolving excuses?
Further, even if this search for the criminal individuals, who must pay
for the state whose leaders or instruments they chose to be, were juridically
satisfactory, it would remain fraught with dangers. Would statesmen yield
before having exhausted every means of resistance, if they knew that in the
enemy’s eyes they are criminals and will be treated as such in case of
defeat? It is perhaps immoral, but it is most often wise, to spare the leaders
of an enemy state, for otherwise these men will sacrifice the lives and
wealth and possessions of their fellow citizens or their subjects in the vain
hope of saving themselves. If war as such is criminal, it will be inexpiable.
Further still: even in the case of the last war, for which the major re¬
sponsibility was manifestly Germany’s, it is far from the case that innocent
states and guilty states were all on one side or the other. Before 1939 the
international system was heterogeneous. A complex heterogeneity, more¬
over, since three regimes were in conflict, profoundly hostile to one another,
each of them inclined to put its two adversaries “in the same sack.” To the
Communists, fascism and parliamentary government were only two modes
of capitalism. To the Western powers, communism and fascism represented
two versions of totalitarianism. To the fascists, parliamentary government
and communism, expressions of democratic and rationalist thought, marked
two stages in degeneration, that of plutocracy and that of despotic leveling.
But under duress each of these regimes consented to acknowledge elements
of relationship with one of its adversaries. During the war Stalin dis¬
tinguished between the fascisms that destroyed workers’ organizations and
liberties and the regimes of bourgeois democracy which at least tolerated
unions and parties. But at the time of the Russo-German Pact, he hailed
the love of the German people for their Fiihrer and the “meeting of two
revolutions.” The Western democracies, at the time of the anti-fascist coali¬
tion or of the Great Alliance, believed they discovered a community of
aspiration with the Left, but when the Iron Curtain fell on the demarcation
line, they recalled that Red totalitarianism was worth no more than the
Brownshirt variety had been. As for the fascists, they were ready, depending
on circumstances, to ally themselves with either communism in the in¬
terests of the revolution, or with the bourgeois democracies against Soviet
barbarism and for the defense of civilization.
THEORY
Il6
This ternary heterogeneity, as it might be called, excluded the formation
of blocs depending on the internal regime, a circumstance resulting from
ideological dualism. It also gave the advantage to those states, tactically
free in their maneuvers, capable of allying themselves with one of their
enemies against the other. Now France and Great Britain could ally them¬
selves with the Soviet Union against fascism (though it required imminent
aggression for the Right to agree to such a step), but they could not ally
themselves with fascism, because of the unshakable opposition of the Left.
Finally, the Soviet Union had the most trumps, since it accepted any kind of
enemy as a provisional ally and was similarly accepted by any of them.
The Soviet Union and the Western democracies had one interest in com¬
mon: to prevent the Third Reich from outstripping one or another of the
hostile blocs. But forestalling war was to the interest of France and Eng¬
land, not necessarily of the Soviet Union. To turn the first German
aggression westward corresponded to Soviet interest, as it would have cor¬
responded to the Western interest that the Soviet Union should receive
the first attack. The Russo-German Pact did not extend beyond the frame¬
work of traditional Machiavellianism.
But once all the states were participating in this tragic game, the Soviet
aggression against Poland, then against Finland and the Baltic countries,
however incontestable on the juridical level, could be interpreted as a de¬
fensive reply, by anticipation, to the foreseeable Hitlerian aggression. When
the intentions of a neighboring and powerful state are obvious, must the
designated victim wait passively? The invasion of Germany by French
troops in March 1936 would perhaps have been condemned by world
opinion; it would have saved the peace. The classical jurists were familiar
with the impossibility of resorting to the criterion of “initiative” alone to
establish responsibility, and they regarded it as the major reason for legal¬
izing war. As for the Nuremberg judges, who included one Russian, they
obviously ignored the aggression of which the Soviet Union, according to
the letter of the law, was incontestably guilty with regard to Poland, Fin¬
land and the Baltic States. An inevitable discretion, but one that illustrates
all too well the formula of injustice: two weights, two measures.
In the prewar international system the desire of dissatisfied states to upset
the status quo was the primary datum. Among those states threatened by
this revolutionary desire, some were more conservative and others less. But
all being eager to prevent a German hegemony, each hoped to stop Hitler
with a minimum of expense to itself, and to derive a maximum of benefit from
the victory. Finally, the expenses were enormous for all, but the benefits were
also enormous for the one that had, perhaps out of fear of the coalition of
the capitalist nations, given Hitler the occasion to loose the holocaust.
In such a circumstance it is easier for the moralist to blame these ma¬
neuvers than for the politician to find a substitute for them.
ON INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS
II 7
5. Ambiguities of Recognition and Aggression
The juridical order created after the Second World War and of which
the United Nations is the expression is based on the same principles as
the Versailles Covenant of the League of Nations. This time the United
States has inspired this order and desires to maintain it, instead of sug¬
gesting its conception and thereafter withdrawing, as it had done after the
First World War.
This juridical order henceforth extends to almost all the world’s population
(Germany, by reason of its division, and Communist China being the two
notable exceptions), and thereby applies to realities historically and politically
heterogeneous. The heterogeneity, masked by the principle of equality of na¬
tions, is that of the political units themselves: Yemen, Liberia, Haiti are
proclaimed sovereign with the same qualification and the same prerogatives
as the Soviet Union, Great Britain and the United States. Some regard this
as decisive progress in relation to diplomatic circumstances early in the cen¬
tury, when Europeans considered their domination over so many non-Euro¬
peans quite natural. Fortunate or not, the development is incontestable: fifty
years ago, juridical equality was granted to few states outside the European
and American sphere; today it is granted to all, whatever their resources or
institutions. International law, which was first that of the Christian nations,
then that of the civilized nations, is henceforth applied to the nations of all
continents, provided they are peace-lovingP^
Even more than historical heterogeneity,^ political heterogeneity burdens
the juridical order. Communist states and democratic states are not only differ¬
ent, they are, as such, enemies. The Soviet leaders, according to their doctrine,
regard the capitalist states as committed to belligerent expansion and con¬
demned to death. America’s leaders, according to their interpretation of
Communist ideology, are convinced that the masters of the Kremlin aspire
to world domination. In other words, the states in each bloc do not present,
in the eyes of the other bloc, that peace-loving character which, according to
the Charter , 0 would qualify them for United Nations membership. The
liberal states, if they acted according to the logic of their convictions, would
not admit the totalitarian ones, which they regard as imperialist, into the
international juridical community, and the latter would adopt the same atti¬
tude with regard to them.
As a matter of fact, the decision was taken to ignore this political and
historical heterogeneity, at least at Lake Success or in New York. NATO
and the Warsaw Pact, whose spokesmen exchange Homeric insults and whose
member states multiply military preparations, express the real hostilities, im¬
plied by facts and ideas. In the United Nations the states, externally hostile,
EUCf. B. V. A. Roling: International Law in an Expanded World, Amsterdam, i960.
UlCf. below, Chap. XIII.
! i 3 Article 4.
ii8
THEORY
find themselves within the same assembly and, depending on the day, give
each other evidence of their good intentions or accuse each other of the worst
misdeeds.
As to the historical inequalities of nations, they have been taken into ac¬
count only with regard to the choice of five permanent members of the Se¬
curity Council (the United States, the Soviet Union, Great Britain, France,
China). In 1961 the Chinese seat remained occupied by the representatives
of Chiang Kai-shek—that is, of the so-called Nationalist regime which had
taken refuge in Formosa. In the Assembly, one vote is as good as another,^
although the Great Powers possess, in fact, a clientele.
The circumstance of juridical and historical heterogeneity on the one hand,
and the juridical formalism of equality of nations on the other, gives the no¬
tion of recognition a decisive importance. Since a state has the right to handle
internally everything pertaining to its sovereignty, since it even has the
rightE of appealing to foreign troops, everything depends on what I shall
call the governmental incarnation of the state. The same facts receive a con¬
trary juridical description depending on whether one government or the
other is recognized as legal.
The sending of American forces to Lebanon and of British forces to Jordan
(1958) was not regarded as contrary to international law and the United
Nations Charter because it occurred upon the request of the “legal govern¬
ments.” If the King of Iraq and Nuri Said had escaped the conspirator^
and appealed to English and American troops for help, would the latter’s
intervention have been illegal? Let us suppose that the Hungarian govern¬
ment, legal in the eyes of the United Nations, had not been that of Imre
Nag}' but that of the “Stalinists”; the intervention of the Russian divisions,
called in by the “legal government,” would then have been scarcely more con¬
trary to international juridical formalism than the landing of American troops
in Lebanon. Starting from the determination of the “subject of law,” the
consequences inexorably follow: in some cases one wonders if a certain de
facto state (the German Democratic Republic, North Korea) will be recog¬
nized as a “subject of law,” a legal state; in others, one wonders which group
of men or which party represents the state, whose existence no one denies
(the two blocs do not put the existence of a Hungarian state in doubt, but
did Kadar or Nagy preside over the legal government on November 3,
1956^.
Thus we see that the problem of recognition has been at the core of dip¬
lomatic discussions since 1945, whether Korea, China or Germany was in
HD The Soviet Union, of course, possesses three votes, the Ukraine and White Russia
being regarded as states.
MJWhich the jurists dispute but which has become a practice.
InlA further reason, for the latter, to put them to death immediately.
EHOn November 3, 1957, there was no longer any doubt that it was the Kadar gov¬
ernment: international law forgets the birth and death of governments.
ON international systems
”9
question. Jurists had elaborated “implicitly normative” theories of recognition,
held forth on the distinction between de facto and de jure recognition, ob¬
served the various practices of states. These practices and distinctions are
illuminated only by reference to policy.
Let us start from an uncontested proposition: according to custom, states
enjoy a certain liberty of recognizing or not recognizing any state which has
just been created (Guinea in 1958) or any government which has just as¬
sumed power. The United States has employed non-recognition in dealing
with the revolutionary governments of South America, and with “territorial
modifications imposed by force,” non-recognition being a diplomatic instru¬
ment. The American leaders hoped to prevent coups d'etat or conquests by
letting it be known in advance that they would not acknowledge the conse¬
quences. The United States took years to extend de jure recognition to the
Soviet Union (sixteen in fact: from 1917 to 1933). Although de jure recog¬
nition does not constitute an approval of the methods and principles of the
regime to which it is granted, the diplomats have added one concept, that of
de facto recognition, halfway between non-recognition and full and complete
recognition
The weapon of non-recognition has been ultimately ineffectual, against
both revolutions and conquests. The leaders of a revolution, like those of the
imperialist state, know that in the long run the power of reality is irresistible.
It is impossible to ignore the de facto authorities indefinitely, on the pretext
that their origins are disagreeable and their methods reprehensible. Yet recog¬
nition has not thereby become simple and automatic. On the contrary, one
might distinguish, sociologically if not juridically, two modes of de facto
recognition and two modes of de jure recognition.
I should call implicit de facto recognition the kind that consists in dealing
with a de facto authority, while denying its legal existence. Such is the case
with the relations of the Western states with the German Democratic Repub¬
lic (Deutsche Demokratische Republik, or D.D.R.). To reduce as much as
possible the element of recognition which the contracts contain, the Western
powers, in particular the Bonn leaders, have insisted that the economic agree¬
ments between the two Germanies be signed by functionaries of inferior rank.
There would be de facto recognition if agreements in good and due form,
on the governmental level, were concluded with the D.D.R.
As for de jure recognition, it has, depending on circumstances, two histor¬
ically different meanings. If the regimes of the states that recognize each
other are the same, or different but not opposed, the recognition is valid in
UlThe distinction is juridically dubious, since recognition, even de jure, could only
be the recognition of a fact, the fact that a state or a regime or a government exists.
The actual government, by a group of men, of an independent collectivity—such
must be the non-ideological meaning of recognition, but, in a heterogeneous system,
recognition always has political consequences and ideological implications. Hence gov¬
ernments use the modalities of recognition, or non-recognition, for their own purposes.
120
THEORY
all circumstances. The states could fight each other without either one at¬
tempting to overthrow the other’s regime and instigate or support rebels. On
the other hand, when two states whose regimes are directly contradictory
grant each other de jure recognition, neither of the two governments es¬
tablished at the beginning of the hostilities would survive defeat. Even in
peacetime, ideological hostility is expressed in many ways, neither of the states
being capable of completely separating national interests and ideological in¬
terests.
Over all the territories liberated by Eastern and Western armies, the dis¬
pute of recognition has assumed a harsh character. In Korea, only the Re¬
public of South Korea was recognized by the United Nations, North Korea
having stubbornly refused to apply the U.N. decisions relative to free elec¬
tions and unification. Further, the crossing of the 38th Parallel was the
action of the North Korean army; responsibility for the aggression (initiation
of hostilities) was therefore unequivocal. But, according to Soviet ideological
interpretation, the North Korean aggression was primarily a civil war, the
attempt of the true (Communist) Korea to free the Koreans established on
the other side of the demarcation line from the imperialist yoke. In appear¬
ance, the United Nations succeeded in mobilizing the neutral powers against
the aggressor, a feat the League of Nations had been unable to accomplish
against Italy. In reality, it was the American action that assured resistance to
the aggressor and not a United Nations decision, which was effected only by
the absence of the Soviet Union.^ Further, the victim suffered no less than
the aggressor, and the United Nations command, far from punishing North
Koreans and Chinese aggressors, dealt with them in the fashion of any
government that was eager to end, by a peace without victory, a secondary
conflict.
In Germany the Western powers refuse to extend de facto or de jure
recognition to the D.D.R., because in their eyes the Bonn Republic represents
all Germany. The Soviets, on the contrary, recognize the Federal Republic to
the same degree that they recognize the D.D.R.; they have everything to
gain from such a recognition, which serves them as an argument with regard
to the Western powers, who are urged to treat Pankow as they themselves
treat Bonn.
Stranger still is the non-recognition of Communist China by the United
States and most of the Western powers. The Peking regime exhibits the
characteristics of a legal government, at least as much as the regimes of
Eastern Europe. Washington may regard it as illegitimate, but in that case it
should regard the Soviet regime in Russia as illegitimate too. As for the
Chinese aggression in Korea or the treatment of a number of American citi¬
zens, these facts do not differ from those that might be invoked against the
Soviet Union. Non-recognition is merely the means of preserving the prestige
of legality for the Chiang Kai-shek government. Similarly, the United States
H^Because of this fact, the legality of the decision is in doubt.
ON INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS
121
defends Formosa, Quemoy and Matsu against the ventures of the Chinese
Communists as the result of an agreement with the legal government of
China.
Thus the Peking government is not “recognized” by a number of the
Western states, although it presents all the characteristics of de facto govern¬
ment Ceffective control of territory and population), necessary and sufficient,
according to most jurists, to justify recognition. Conversely, the FLN, estab¬
lished in Cairo or Tunis, was recognized by most governments of the Arab
nations, though it exercised no regular authority over any portion of the
Algerian territory. In a heterogeneous system, recognition is a means of diplo¬
matic or military action. It aims at morally reinforcing improvised or revolu¬
tionary organizations. The recognition of the FLN was a proclamation of
sympathy for the Nationalist Algerian camp, the affirmation that French policy
was condemned and the rebel action sanctified by the principle of self-
determination. Let us conclude the analysis: for the determination of the
subjects of law to be unequivocal, the principle of legitimacy and its inter¬
pretation must be unequivocal too, in which case, in what manner must self-
determination be applied? By what methods must governments he chosen?
But the very heterogeneity that prevents an unequivocal determination of the
subjects of law also forbids reaching a definition, unanimously accepted, of
aggression.
The reasons why attempts to define aggression have failed are many and
complex^ The attitudes of the various states on this subject have been, in
each circumstance, dictated by considerations of expedience. In 1945 the
Americans tried to introduce a definition (one which had been elaborated by
the disarmament conference of 1933) into the statute of the Nuremberg
tribunal, and the Russians stubbornly opposed it. Ten years later it was the
Russians who favored a definition of aggression in the United Nations and
the Americans who had meanwhile become hostile to it. A definition of ag¬
gression seems to me impossible and, further, useless, whatever the character
of the international system. By the term aggression, diplomats, jurists and
mere citizens designate, more or less vaguely, an illegitimate use, direct or
indirect, of force. Now relations among states have been and are such that
it is not possible to find the general and abstract criteria in the light of which
the distinction between legitimate and illegitimate use of force would be
automatic and obvious.
If all use of armed force, in every circumstance, is illegitimate, the threat
of such use is no less so. But how can a threat be disclosed that has no need of
being explicit in order to be effective? What rights should be granted to the
state that is, and regards itself as being, threatened? It is true that the
United Nations Charter forbids the threat as much as the use of force, but
E 3 A detailed study of the attempts to define aggression in the League of Nations and
the United Nations will be found in the work of M. Eugene Aroneanu, La definition
de Vagression, Paris, 1958.
122
THEORY
such a formula is pure hypocrisy: lacking a tribunal capable of deciding dif¬
ferences equitably, all states have relied and continue to rely on themselves
to obtain justice; none genuinely subscribes to the view that threats in the
service of a just cause are, as such, culpable.
Further, it would be an oversimplification to consider armed force and the
direct use of this force alone. If we seek to elaborate an international penal
code, we must define the delinquencies and the crimes that states are capable
of committing outside the extreme crime of “the use of armed force.” The
various means of constraint or of economic, psychological and political attack
must also be condemned. But what procedures of “economic pressure” are
culpable? Which propaganda is criminal, and which is tolerable?
In short, in a homogeneous system, it is impossible to define aggression
because the recourse to force (or to the threat of force) is intrinsically linked
to the relations among states desiring to be independent. In a heterogeneous
system, it is impossible to define aggression because the regimes in conflict
assail each other continuously and commit, with good conscience, the crime
of indirect or ideological aggression.
Futile attempts have been made to overcome the first obstacle by defining,
in general terms or by enumeration, the circumstances in which the recourse
to force would be either legitimate or illegitimate. But this has merely ex¬
tended or multiplied the difficulties. If the use of force is legal in the case of
legitimate defense, this latter concept requires definition. If we refer to the
sequence of events, if the aggressor is the one who initiates the hostility, we
are caught in the casuistry of attack and initiative. We do not always know
who started the hostilities. The initiator is not always the disturber of the
peace. The state in danger does not always have time to employ the proce¬
dures known as peaceful.
Further, must the state that does not receive justice (according to its con¬
ception of justice) endure injustice indefinitely? The enumeration of the
circumstances in which the recourse to force is not legitimate risks guarantee¬
ing the impunity of those who violate the law, encouraging international
anarchy and finally provoking the very thing that it has attempted to prevent.
In a heterogeneous system, only “armed aggression,” the crossing of fron¬
tiers by regular armies, is clearly identifiable. All forms of indirect aggression
are common practice. It is ironic but not surprising that the Soviet representa¬
tives serving on the U.N. committees to define aggression have proposed the
following formula: "Any state will be recognized as guilty of indirect ag¬
gression which:
a) Encourages subversive activities directed against another state
(acts of terrorism, sabotage, etc.);
b) Foments civil war in another state;
c) Favors an uprising in another state or political changes favor¬
able to the aggressor. ’HH
[HI Aroneanu, op. cit., p. 292.
ON INTERNATIONAL SYSTEMS
I2 3
Of course, in th° eyes of the Soviets, only the Atlantic bloc knows the
“criminal” secrets of subversive war.
In 1933 a committee known as the Politis Committee defined aggression
by enumeration of cases. Four of these five cases were readily predictable®:
“declaration of war against another state; invasion by armed forces, even with¬
out declaration of war, of the territory of another state; attack by land, naval
or air forces, even without declaration of war, of the territory, ships or air¬
ships of another state; naval blockade of the coasts or ports of another state.”
Providing that the side taking the initiative be regarded as the guilty one, all
these cases are simple. But the fifth case assumes, today, a strange relevance.
“Support given to armed groups which, formed on its territory, have invaded
the territory of another state; or the refusal, despite the demand of the state
invaded, to take, on its own territory, all the measures in its power to deprive
the said groups of all aid or protection.”
Let us consider only this last case: the organization or toleration of armed
groups contradicts, in effect, the ancient customs of intercourse among states,
but, supposing that a nation becomes guilty of such indirect aggression, what
should the corresponding reaction be? Protests are ineffective, military inter¬
vention risks returning us to the simpleton’s equation: respect for interna¬
tional law equals war by sanctions. It is not certain that the French army
would have pursued the groups of Algerian rebels into Tunisian and Moroc¬
can territory, even if the United Nations did not exist.
The Politis definition added an enumeration of the circumstances that did
not legitimize the military action of a foreign state: “The interior situation of
a state, for instance its political, economic or social structure, the alleged
defects of its administration, the disturbances resulting from strikes, revolu¬
tions, counterrevolutions or civil wars; the international conduct of a state,
for instance a violation or the danger of violation of the rights or material or
moral interests of a foreign state or its members, the rupture of diplomatic or
economic relations, measures of economic or financial boycott, disputes rel¬
ative to economic or financial commitments or other commitments to foreign
states, frontier incidents not referring to one of the cases of aggression indi¬
cated in the first article.” The prohibition against intervention in revolution
or counterrevolution applies directly to the Soviet action in Hungary, as the
prohibition against using force to defend material interests endangered by a
foreign state precisely describes the Franco-British action against Egypt. This
definition of aggression had been inserted in many pacts concluded by the
Soviet Union, in particular those with the Baltic nations and FinlandM The
latter were not saved thereby. The United Nations has finally abandoned
defining aggression and prefers to utilize the other concepts included in the
Charter: breaking the peace, the threat to peace or to international security,
attack on the territorial integrity or the political independence of states. It
124
THEORY
limits the use of the term aggression to a single case, that of the crossing of
a state’s frontiers by regular troops of another state without the former’s con¬
sent. Propaganda, agents of subversion, terrorist commandos pass across or
through frontiers without being formally condemned by the international
organizations or even by the interpreters of international law.
Juridical formalism has yielded to the realities of the cold war.
No juridical system has answered, even theoretically, two basic questions:
how can any modification of the status quo be prevented from occurring as
a result of a violation of law? Or again, to formulate the same question in
different words, in the name of what criteria can an arbitrator or a tribunal
dictate those peaceful changes without which any particular international
law, based on the will of states, must be conservative? The rights and duties
of states being, by hypothesis, precisely defined, how can the de facto organic
groups be defined that deserve to be regarded as states?
The League of Nations did not answer the first question. The United
Nations is seeking an answer to the second, but the historical and juridical
heterogeneity of the world system prohibits it from finding it.
chapter V
On Multipolar Systems and Bipolar Systems
Foreign policy, in and of itself, is power politics. Therefore the concept of
equilibrium—balance—applies to all international systems up to the Atomic
Age Chut perhaps not including it).
In the course of the preceding chapters we have distinguished forces—
the various means of pressure or constraint which states possess—and power
—the capacity of states, each taken as a unit, to influence the others. Thus
we deliberately use the expressions power politics and balance of forces. The
first means that states recognize neither arbitrator nor tribunal nor laws
superior to their will and, consequently, owe their existence and their se¬
curity only to themselves or their allies. If I prefer “balance of forces” to
“balance of power,” it is because forces are more measurable than power. But
if forces are balanced, powers too are balanced, approximately. No state im¬
poses its sovereign will on others unless it possesses resources so decisive
that its rivals admit in advance the futility of resistance.
I. The Policy of Equilibrium
It is in Hume’s brief essay entitled "On the Balance of Power” that the
abstract theory of equilibrium is set forth with the most convincing simplic¬
ity-
David Hume takes as his point of departure this question: is the idea of
equilibrium a modern one or is the formula alone of recent invention, the
idea itself being as old as the world? The second term of the alternative is
correct: “In all the politics of Greece, the anxiety with regard to the balance
of power is apparent, and is expressly pointed out to us, even by the ancient
historians. Thucydides represents the league which was formed against Ath¬
ens, and which produced the Peloponnesian War, as entirely owing to this
principle. And after the decline of Athens, when the Thebans and Lace¬
daemonians disputed for sovereignty, we find that the Athenians (as well as
many other republics) always threw themselves into the lighter scale, and
endeavored to preserve the balance.”
126
THEORY
The Persian Empire behaved in the same way: “The Persian monarch
was really, in his force, a petty prince, compared to the Grecian republics;
and, therefore, it behooved him, from views of safety more than from emula¬
tion, to interest himself in their quarrels, and to support the weaker side in
every contest.” Alexander’s successors followed the same principle: “They
showed great jealousy of the balance of power; a jealousy founded on true
politics and prudence, arid which preserved distinct for several ages the parti¬
tion made after the death of that famous conqueror.” The nations capable of
intervening in the war belong to the system: “As the Eastern princes con¬
sidered the Greeks and Macedonians as the only real military force with
whom they had any intercourse, they kept always a watchful eye over that
part of the world.”
If the ancients seem to have ignored the policy of equilibrium, the reason
is the astonishing history of the Roman Empire. It is a fact that Rome was
able to conquer her adversaries one after another, for they were unable to
conclude in time the alliances which would have saved them. Philip of
Macedon remained neutral until the time of Hannibal’s victories and then
imprudently concluded with the conqueror an alliance “upon terms still
more imprudent.” The Rhodean and Achaean republics, whose wisdom is
celebrated by the historians of antiquity, offered assistance to the Romans in
their wars against Philip and Antiochus. “Massinissa, Attalus, Prusias, in
gratifying their private passions, were all of them instalments of the Roman
greatness, and never seemed to have suspected that they were forging their
own chains, while they advanced the conquests of their ally.” The only
prince who, in the course of Roman history, seems to have understood the
principle of equilibrium is Hiero, King of Syracuse: “Nor ought such a force
ever to be thrown into one hand as to incapacitate the neighboring states
from defending their rights against it.” Such is the more simple formula of
equilibrium: a state should never possess such strength that neighboring
states would be incapable of defending their rights against it. The formula,
based as it is on “common sense and obvious reasoning,” is too simple to
have escaped the ancients.
By virtue of the same principle, Hume then analyzes the European system
and the rivalry of France and England. “A new power succeeded, more
formidable to the liberties of Europe, possessing all the advantages of the
former, and laboring under none of its defects, except a share of that spirit
of bigotry and persecution, with which the House of Austria was so long,
and still is, so much infatuated.” Against the French monarchy, which had
been victorious in four wars out of five but which had nonetheless not
greatly enlarged its dominion nor acquired a “total ascendancy over Europe,”
England was in the forefront. We cannot help being amused today by
Hume’s criticism of English policy. Like the Greeks, he says, “we seem to
have been more possessed with the ancient Greek spirit of jealous emulation
than actuated by the prudent views of modem politics.” England has with-
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS 127
out profit continued wars begun justifiably and, perhaps more, out of neces¬
sity but which might have been concluded sooner under the same conditions.
England’s hostility to France seems a certainty in any event, and the Allies
count on the English forces as on their own and are quite uncompromising
in their demands, England being obliged to assume the cost of hostilities.
Finally, “we are such true combatants that, when once engaged, we lose all
concern for ourselves and our posterity, and consider only how we may
best annoy the enemy.”
The excesses of belligerent ardor seem to Hume vexing because of the
economic sacrifices they involve, but he regards them as particularly dan¬
gerous because they risk some day leading England to the opposite extreme:
“rendering us totally careless and supine with regard to the fate of Europe.
The Athenians, from the most bustling, intriguing, war-like people of
Greece, finding their error in thrusting themselves into every quarrel, aban¬
don all attention to foreign affairs; and in no contest ever took part, except
by their flatteries and complaisance to the victor.”
David Hume favors the policy of equilibrium because he is opposed to
huge empires: “Enormous monarchies are probably destructive to human na¬
ture in their progress, in their continuance, and even in their downfall,
which never can be very distant from their establishment.” If the Roman
Empire is cited as an objection, Hume answers that though the Roman
Empire may have been of some advantage, this was because “mankind were
generally in a very disorderly, uncivilized condition before its establishment.”
The indefinite expansion of a monarchy—rod Hume means that of the Bour¬
bons—creates obstacles in and of itself—"thus human nature checks itself in
its airy elevation.” We would scarcely simplify Hume’s thought by offering
the antithesis of the •policy of equilibrium and that of universal monarchy.
Since universal monarchy seems no less disastrous to Hume than to Montes¬
quieu, the state inevitably losing its virtues with the extension of its territory,
the policy of equilibrium is rationally preferable in terms of historical ex¬
perience and moral values.
The Roman decadence began, Montesquieu said, when the immensity of
the Empire made the Republic impossible. Were the Bourbon monarchy to
be unduly extended, the nobility would refuse to serve in remote places,
in Hungary or in Lithuania, “forgot at court and sacrificed to the intrigue of
every minion or mistress who approaches the Prince.” The king would have
to call in mercenaries “and the melancholy fate of the Roman emperors,
from the same cause, is renewed over and over again, till the final dissolu¬
tion of the monarchy.”
The policy of equilibrium obeys a rule of common sense; it issues from
the prudence necessary to the states concerned to preserve their indepen¬
dence and not be at the mercy of another state possessing irresistible strength.
It seems blameworthy to those statesmen or doctrinaires who regard the
clandestine or overt use of force, sometimes leading to violence, as the mark
THEORY
128
and expression of human wickedness. Yet such censors should devise a
juridical or spiritual substitute for the equilibrium of autonomous wills. The
same policy of equilibrium will be considered moral, or at least historically
justified, by those who fear a universal monarchy and desire the survival
of independent states. It will be judged if not immoral, at least anarchic, by
those, on the contrary, who, in a given space, at a given time, prefer the
unity of an empire to the maintenance of multiple sovereignties. The un¬
prejudiced observer will decide, according to circumstances, in favor of
equilibrium or empire, since it is not likely that the optimum dimension of
the state territory (optimum for whom? for what?) will be the same at all
periods.
The policy of equilibrium, on the highest level of abstraction, is reduced
to maneuvering in order to prevent a state from accumulating forces superior
to those of its allied rivals. Every state, if it wishes to safeguard the equilib¬
rium, will take a position against the state or the coalition that seems
capable of achieving such a superiority. This general rule is valid for all
international systems. But if we seek to elaborate the rules of the policy of
equilibrium, we must construct models of systems, according to the configura¬
tion of the relation of forces.
The two most typical models are the ones I have called multipolaid] and
bipolar: either the chief actors, whose forces are not too unequal, are rela¬
tively numerous; or, on the contrary, two actors dominate their rivals to such
a degree that both become the center of a coalition and the secondary
actors are obliged to situate themselves in relation to the two "blocs,” thus
joining one or another, unless they have the opportunity to abstain. In¬
termediary models are possible, depending on the number of chief actors and
the degree of equality or inequality of forces among the chief actors.
2. The Policy of Multipolar Equilibrium
Let us posit an international system defined by the plurality of rival
states, whose resources, without being equal, do not create a disparity in
nature—taking, for instance, France, Germany, Russia, England, Austria,
Hungary, Italy in 1910. If these states wish to maintain the equilibrium,
they must apply certain rules which stem from the rejection of a universal
monarchy.
The enemy being, by definition, that state which ventures to dominate
the others, the victor in a war (the side which has gained the most ad¬
vantages) immediately becomes suspect to its former allies. In other words,
alliances and enmities are, in essence, temporary, since they are determined
by the relation of forces. By the same token, the state whose forces are
increasing must anticipate the dissidence of certain of its allies, who will
rejoin the other camp in order to maintain the balance. Anticipating such
[UAuthors generally attach the phrase balance of power to the systems I call multipolar.
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS
129
defense reactions, the state whose power is in the ascendant will be wise
to limit its ambitions, if it does not aspire to hegemony or empire. If it
does aspire to hegemony, it must be prepared, as disruptive force of the
system, to face the hostility of all the conservative states.
May we look beyond these generalizations, which are also commonplaces,
and enumerate the rules the actors must rationally observe in a multipolar
system (again, we are concerned with a hypothetical rationality, based on
the postulate that the actors desire to maintain the system}? An American
author, Morton A. KaplanpDhas formulated the six rules both necessary and
sufficient for the functioning of a schematic system which he calls the bal¬
ance of power and which, it seems to me, corresponds to the one that
concerns us.
These six rules are as follows: 1. each actor must act in such a way as
to increase his capabilities, but must prefer negotiation to combat; 2. each
must fight rather than miss an opportunity to increase his capabilities;
3. each must cease fighting rather than eliminate a “principal national
actor’ll] 4. each must act so as to oppose any coalition or individual actor
tending to assume a position of predominance in relation to the rest of
the system; 5. each must act so as to constrain the actors subscribing to a
supranational principle of organization; 6. each must permit the national
actors, whether beaten or constrained, to return to the system as acceptable
partners, or must bring a previously non-essential actor into the essential
category. All the essential actors must be dealt with as acceptable partners.
Of these six rules, we may immediately detach the fourth, which is the
simple expression of the principle of equilibrium, a principle valid for all
international systems and already defined in Hume’s essay. Not one of the
other rules, interpreted literally, is of obvious application, generally speaking.
The first—which enjoins all the actors to increase their capacities (re¬
sources, means, forces) to the maximum—is valid for any system defined by
the struggle of each against all. Since each state relies upon itself alone,
any increase in resources is welcome as such, provided it leaves all other
things equal. Now it is rare for a state to increase its resources without
modifying either the resources or the attitude of its allies or rivals. That
negotiation is preferable to combat may be considered a postulate of rational
policy, comparable to that of the least effort for a given economic yield (in
production or income). However, this postulate requires that the actors
disregard their pride or glory.
The rule of fighting rather than missing an opportunity of increasing
capabilities is neither rational nor reasonable. Of course, in the abstract, all
other things being equal, any actor on the international stage seeks maxi-
IZjSystem and Process in International Politics, New York, 1957, pp. 23 ff.
■"-The principal national actor, in such a system, is what in ordinary terms we call a
“Great Power” or a state possessing forces great enough to constitute one of the
essential elements of the system of equilibrium.
* 3 °
THEORY
mum capabilities. But if we attempt to determine in what circumstances it
is rational for a state to fight, we shall he reduced to virtually meaningless
formulas of the following type: the state must take the initiative in combat
if the advantages it anticipates from victory are to exceed the probable cost
of the struggle, the gap between advantage and cost widening with the
risk of non-victory or defeat. Whatever the specific formula achieved, the
possibility of increasing capabilities is not enough to justify recourse to
arms.
The classical authors had acknowledged only the threat of hegemony
brought about by the growth of a rival as a reasonable and legitimate
motive for taking the initiative in hostilities. It is not immoral, but it is
imprudent to contemplate passively the rise of a state toward a superiority
so great that its neighbors would be at its mercy.
Rules three and six tend to contradict each other or, at least, illustrate
the various outcomes possible. In a system of multipolar equilibrium, the
wise statesman hesitates to eliminate one of the principal actors. He does
not proceed to the extremes of victory if he fears that, by continuing the
combat, he will destroy a temporary enemy necessary to the system’s equilib¬
rium. But if the elimination of one of the principal actors involves, di¬
rectly or indirectly, the entrance on stage of an actor of equivalent stature,
he will consider whether the old actor or the new is the more favorable
to his own interests.
Rule five is equivalent to the following principle: any state which, in a
given system, follows a supranational ideology or acts according to a supra¬
national conception is, as such, an enemy. This principle is not strictly
implied by the ideal model of a multipolar equilibrium. Of course, so long
as this kind of equilibrium is expressed normally in a rivalry of states,
each exclusively concerned with its own interests, the state that recruits
partisans beyond its borders because it claims a universal doctrine, thereby
becomes a threat to the others. But we cannot draw the conclusion from
the inevitable hostility between national states and the state appealing to
a transnational idea that the former must make war on the latter: it all de¬
pends on the relation of forces and on the probability of reducing the
attractiveness of the transnational idea by arms.
Again more generally, all these rules presuppose implicitly that the safe¬
guarding of equilibrium and of the system is the sole object or at least the
predominant concern of states. Yet nothing of the kind is so. The only
state that, more or less consciously, has acted according to this hypothesis
is England, which, indeed, had no other interest than safeguarding the
system itself and weakening, in each period, the strongest state capable of
aspiring to hegemony. None of the continental states was or could have
been so disinterested in the modes of equilibrium, even if it did not aspire
to domination. Possession of strategic points or provinces, the configuration
of frontiers, distribution of resources, such were the stakes of the conflicts
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS 131
which the continental states desired to settle to their advantage. That they
were prepared, if necessary in order to achieve their goals, to eliminate
a principal actor was not an irrational step, as long as there remained
enough actors to reconstitute another system. The elimination of Germany
as a principal actor, as a result of division, was not irrational on the part
of French policy, which thereby reinforced its own position without dan¬
gerously reducing the number of chief actors.
The purely national policy of European states covers only a brief period
between the wars of religion and the wars of revolution. The termination
of the wars of religion was not due to the outlawing or the irremediable
defeat of states appealing to a transnational idea, but to the proclamation
of the primacy of the state over the individual; the state determining the
church to which individuals would have to belong, if not in which they
would have to believe, tolerating dissidents only on condition that the lat-
ters’ religious choice appeared to be a strictly private matter. The European
peace of the seventeenth century was obtained by a complex diplomacy
which re-established the equilibrium of states and prevented the disputes of
churches or the beliefs of the governed to put this equilibrium to the test.
The sovereigns had abandoned the strategy of “ideological war” to return
to that of “Holy Alliance”: any rebellion against an established power,
grievous in itself, was condemned even by those governing rival states.
The stability of the powers was given precedence over the weakening by
dissidence or rebellion of a state that was a potential enemy.
Perhaps the author whose theses we are discussing would subscribe to the
preceding remarks. The six rules he formulates would be those which per¬
fectly rational actors would follow in an ideal typical multipolar (balance-of-
power) system. Even granting that these rules are valid for an ideal type, I
cannot accept them. The conduct of the -pure diplomat cannot and must
not be held as determined by reference to equilibrium alone, which itself is
defined by the rejection of universal monarchy and by the plurality of
principal actors. The behavior of economic subjects is determined in a
typical ideal market because each member seeks to maximize his interests
or his profit. The behavior of diplomatic subjects, in a system of multipolar
equilibrium, has no unequivocal objective: all other things being equal,
each subject hopes for the maximum resources, but if the increase of
resources requires a battle or provokes the reversal of alliances, he will
hesitate to take risks. The maintenance of a given system has as its condition
the safeguarding of the principal actors, but each of the latter is not
rationally obliged to set the maintenance of the system above any of its own
interests. To suppose implicitly that states have as their objective the safe¬
guarding or functioning of the system is to return, by a devious route, to
the error of certain theoreticians of power politics: to confuse the calcula¬
tion of means or the context of the decision with the goal itself.
It is possible neither to predict diplomatic events from the analysis of a
132 -
THEORY
typical system nor to dictate a line of conduct to princes as a result of the
type of system. The model of multipolar equilibrium helps us to understand
the systems that have occurred in history, and the rules which we have
borrowed from the American author suggest the circumstances favorable
to the duration of such a system.
Strictly “national” states regard themselves as rivals, not mortal enemies;
the leaders do not regard themselves as personally threatened by those of the
neighboring states; each state is a possible ally for every other, today's
enemy is spared because he will he tomorrow’s partner and because he is
indispensable to the system’s equilibrium. Diplomacy, in such a system, is
realistic, sometimes even cynical, but it is moderate and reasonable. Hence,
when the ravages of another kind of diplomacy became tragically evident,
this disabused wisdom seemed retrospectively not only an ideal type but an
ideal.
The diplomacy called realist, which the system of multipolar equilibrium
implies, does not conform to the highest requirements of the philosophers.
The state which changes camp the day after victory awakens the bitterness
and resentment of its allies, who may have accepted greater sacrifices than
that state for the sake of their common victory. A pure diplomacy of
equilibrium ignores and must ignore feelings; it has no friends or enemies
as such, it does not regard the latter as worse than the former, it does not
condemn war as such. It acknowledges the egoism or, if one prefers, the
moral corruption (aspiration to power and glory) of states, but such calculat¬
ing corruption seems in the long run less unforeseeable, less formidable
than passions, perhaps idealist but certainly blind.
Until 1945 United States diplomacy was situated at the antipodes of
this traditional and prudent immorality. The United States had preserved
the memory of the two great wars of its history, that against the Indians,
that of the Secession. In neither case was the enemy an accepted state
with which, after hostilities were over, a peaceful coexistence would be
resumed. Diplomatic relations, alliances and conflicts did not seem insepara¬
ble from the normal life-process of states: war was a repellent necessity,
to which one was obliged to adapt, a duty of circumstances which had to
be performed as well and as fast as possible, but it was not an episode of
a sustained history. Thus American public opinion reflected little on the
past and the future when the war had begun. The enemy was guilty
and deserved punishment, was wicked and must be corrected. Afterward,
peace would prevail.
Obliged, in its turn, after 1945, to reverse alliances, America was tempted,
following General MacArthur’s example, to proclaim that it had assigned
roles and merits badly, China having somehow shifted to the ’wrong side
and Japan, simultaneously, to the right side of the barricade. If the enemy
is always the incarnation of evil and if reversals of alliances are sometimes
inevitable, we must conclude that good and evil change their incarnation.
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS I33
According to Machiavelli, virtii shifted in the course of history from one
people to another. According to a moralizing diplomacy, it is virtue, quite
different from Machiavelli’s virtii, which affects such migrations.
Hateful or admirable, baneful or precious, the diplomacy of equilibrium
does not result from a deliberate choice on the part of statesmen—it results
from circumstances.
The geographical scene, the organization of states and military technique
must prevent the concentration of power in one or two states. That there
are several states possessing comparable resources is the structural character¬
istic of the multipolar system. In Greece as in Europe, the geographical
scene was not hostile to the independence of cities and kingdoms. As long
as the political unit was the city-state, the multiplicity of centers of
autonomous decision was the necessary result. To quote Plume, “if we
consider, indeed, the small number of inhabitants in any one Republic
compared to the whole, the great difficulty of forming sieges in those times,
and the extraordinary bravery and discipline of every free man among the
noble people,” we shall conclude that equilibrium was relatively easy to
maintain and empire difficult to impose. In Europe since the end of the
diffused sovereignty of the Middle Ages, first Great Britain, then Russia
constituted insurmountable obstacles in the path of universal monarchy.
The principle of state legitimacy, whether dynastic or national, did not
justify unlimited ambitions. European armies, between the sixteenth and
twentieth centuries, were not equipped for vast conquests: Napoleon’s sol¬
diers advanced on foot from the frontier to Moscow. With distance, they
were weakened still more quickly than Alexander’s soldiers.
The concern for equilibrium inspires diplomacy in proportion as men—
both governing and governed—cling to the independence of their political
unit. The Greek citizens did not separate their own freedom from that of
their city-state. Together, they had defended the civilization of free men
against the Persian Empire, which they regarded as founded on the despotism
of a single man. Against each other, they defended the autonomy of city-
states. The first French monarchy ardently desired total independence, pas¬
sionately refused any submission to empire. Peoples have desired inde¬
pendence of which the national state was the expression. This desire for
state independence, for absolute sovereignty, checks the tendency to ideologi¬
cal diplomacy, maintaining a kind of inter-state homogeneity despite the
conflicts of faith or ideas. It helps to “internalize” the rules of equilibrium
that cease to appear as counsels of prudence, becoming moral or traditional
imperatives. Safeguarding equilibrium is acknowledged as a common duty
of statesmen. The European concert is transformed into an organ of arbitra¬
tion, of common deliberation, even of collective decision.
Yet changes in the relation of forces must not be too rapid. Whether
the people be passive or indifferent, it is better that reversals of alliances
not occur from one day to the next. Whatever the intelligence of statesmen,
THEORY
134
it is better that the shifts of resources not be such that yesterday’s calcula¬
tions are radically false today. The system functions better with known
actors and a more or less stabilized relation of forces. None of these condi¬
tions, taken in isolation, suffices to guarantee the survival of the multipolar
system. The desire for independence will ultimately be swept away by
violent transnational passions. The concern for the common system will not
resist extreme heterogeneity. All the actors are no longer acceptable partners
for each other if the peoples are separated by memories that they refuse to
forget or by the suffering of open wounds. (After 1871 France could not
have allied herself with Germany even if the calculation of equilibrium
had made such an alliance rational.)
Before 1914 the growth of the Reich and the irreducible opposition be¬
tween France and Germany had contributed to the transformation of the
system: alliances tended to become permanent, to crystallize in “blocs.” Be¬
tween the two wars the transnational ideologies of communism, then of
fascism, had made the system so heterogeneous that awareness of a common
interest in its maintenance had entirely disappeared: partisan hostilities, in¬
ternal to states, cut through and aggravated inter-state hostilities. The mili¬
tary revolution, a result of the internal-combustion engine, seemed to clear
the path for great conquests. At this point theoreticians began to dream
nostalgically of the diplomacy of Richelieu, of Mazarin, of Talleyrand.
The system of multipolar equilibrium, as it functioned at the end of the
nineteenth century, is a historical compromise between the state of nature
and the rule of law: the state of nature, because the enemy remains the
strongest insofar as he is the strongest, because each actor is the sole judge,
in the last analysis, of his behavior and retains the right of choosing be¬
tween peace and war. But this state of nature is no longer the struggle of
each against all, without rules and without limits. States recognize each
other’s right to existence; they desire, and know they desire, to preserve
equilibrium and even a certain solidarity in confronting the outside world.
The Greek city-states were not unaware of their profound kinship and at
the same time of the “foreignness” of the barbariansCOTo Asian eyes, rather
than being rivals, the European conquerors gave the impression of being
united in a single “aggressive” bloc.
This intermediary solution between the state of nature and the rule of
law (or again, between the jungle and universal monarchy) is, in essence,
0 Cf. Vattel, op. cit., Book III, Chap. 3, paragraph 47. “Europe comprises a political
system, a body in which everything is linked by the relations and the various interests
of the nations which inhabit this part of the world. It is no longer a jumble of
isolated parts each of which considered itself unaffected by the fate of the others, and
rarely bothered about what did not immediately concern it. The continual attention
of sovereigns to everything that happens, ministers in permanent residence and perpetual
invitations make modem Europe a kind of republic whose independent members, linked
by common interests, gather in order to maintain its order and freedom.”
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS
135
precarious. In theory it leaves the sovereigns free to attack if attack seems
indispensable to prevent the rise of a dreaded rival. Equilibrium is the im¬
perative of prudence rather than the common good of the system: yet if the
war to weaken the strong is waged frequently, the system becomes sterile,
costly and detested. The risk grows greater as it becomes more difficult to
distinguish between “weakening the strong” and “humiliating the proud.”
Was it out of a desire for security or the pride of dominance that the
Greek city-states fought each other so often? Was it concern for security or
the love of glory which inspired the diplomacy of Louis XIV? There was
a time when the diplomacy of cabinets, to which the realist theoreticians
show such indulgence today, was harshly judged because the historians
blamed the kings and their belligerent dealings for the wars described,
whether rightly or wrongly, as wars of prestige. The system of European
equilibrium has perhaps limited the violence of wars (at certain periods);
it has never reduced their frequency.
A precarious compromise, the system perpetually tends to overstep its
bounds, either toward a return to the jungle, or in the direction of a
“universal empire” or a “juridical order.” The double awareness of a common
civilization and of a permanent rivalry is, in essence, contradictory. If the
sense of rivalry prevails, war becomes inexpiable and civilized diplomacy is
eclipsed. If the sense of the community of culture prevails, the temptation
of state unification or of organized peace becomes irresistible. Why did the
Greeks, instead of exhausting their military force against each other, not
combine to bring down the Persian Empire? Why did the Europeans not
choose to rule Africa or Asia together instead of ruining themselves in
fratricidal combat?
Let us note: these questions, historically, were raised after the fact. Philip,
Alexander and their spokesmen have contrasted the city-states’ loss of
autonomy with the greatness which a united Greece was capable of achiev¬
ing. It was Valery, after 1918, who observed that the goal of European
policy seemed to be to entrust the government of the Old World to an
American committee. Indeed, Europeans have always reserved the major
part of their forces for the wars they waged against each other. If the French
sent great armies overseas, it was when they vainly disputed the last shreds
of their possessions with rising nationalist forces; it was when they were
losing, not building, their empire.
Further, it is understandable that this so-called folly be judged as such
only after the fact. States fear their rivals, peoples their neighbors, each
desiring to dominate those close by rather than aspiring to reign over dis¬
tant lands and alien populations. The immense empires of Spain and
England, whether attributed to the spirit of adventure or of lucre, to the
lust or gold or for power, have had as their condition the exceptional mili¬
tary superiority of the conquerors. When such a superiority is not a condi¬
tion, the wars are most frequently waged within the same sphere of civili-
THEORY
136
zation. The Chinese or the Japanese, like the Europeans, have in general
fought among themselves.
It is perhaps human but it is futile to cultivate the nostalgia for the
amoral and measured diplomacy of equilibrium. Such nostalgia is, in es¬
sence, retrospective. Those who regret the days when diplomats were in¬
different to ideas are nevertheless living in a heterogeneous system and an
age of ideological conflicts. Those who admire the subtle combination of
national egoism and respect for equilibrium are contemporaries of the in¬
expiable struggles between candidates for empire, between faiths both
temporal and spiritual, inseparable from the states in conflict. Those who
marvel at the subtle combinations permitted by the plurality of actors are now
observing a diplomatic field occupied by rigid blocs.
Men, including statesmen, are not free to determine the distribution of
forces, the neutral or ideological character of diplomacy. It is wiser to un¬
derstand the diversity of worlds than to dream of a world which no longer
exists because one does not love the world that does.
3. The Policy of Bipolar Equilibrium
I call bipolar the configuration of the relation of forces in which the
majority of political units are grouped around those two among them
whose strength outclasses that of the others. The distinction between the
multipolar and the bipolar configuration is evident to the observer because
of the consequences, some logical, others historical, which each of these
configurations involves.
Whatever the configuration, the most general law of equilibrium applies:
the goal of the chief actors is to avoid finding themselves at the mercy of a
rival. But since the two great powers call the tune, and since the lesser
powers, even by uniting, cannot outweigh one of the great powers, the
principle of equilibrium applies to relations among the coalitions, each
formed around one of the two influential powers. Each coalition has as its
supreme objective prevention of the other from acquiring means superior
to its own.
In such a system we distinguish three kinds of actors (and not only
“small” and "great”): the two leaders of the coalitions, the states obliged
to take part and lend allegiance to one or the other of the leaders, and
lastly the states which can and desire to remain outside the conflict. These
three kinds of actors behave according to different rules.
The leaders of the coalition must simultaneously be on guard to prevent
the growth of the other great power or coalition and to maintain the
cohesion of their own coalition. The two tasks are related to one another
in many ways. If an ally changes sides or shifts from commitment to
neutrality, the relation of forces is modified. On the most abstract level,
the means the leader uses to maintain the coherence of its own coalition
fall into two categories, some tending to protect, others tending to punish:
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS 137
the former assure advantages to allies, the latter hold the threat of sanctions
over dissidents or traitors. The rational use of these means depends on
many circumstances: to the state which fears the other coalition, the great
power gives the guarantee of assistance, that is, of security; to the state
which has nothing to fear, it offers financial advantages; it tries to terrify the
state which cannot be seduced or convinced.
Thucydides wondered to what degree Athens was responsible for the
dissolution of the alliance it led and which did not resist defeat. The
league, theoretically composed of city-states equal in rights, had become a
kind of empire, directed by a heavy-handed master who required the pay¬
ment of tribute. The Greek historian suggests that the strongest always
tends to abuse his strength. Even without invoking this motive of eternal
psychology, today’s historian can draw other interpretations from Thucyd¬
ides’ narrative. A league of "insular powers” does not spontaneously keep
its cohesion once the external danger is past. A league of equal city-states
should have been entirely peaceful and sought no other goal than the
security and freedom of its members. By taking the path of imperialism,
Athens condemned itself to brutality. The servitudes of power are in¬
escapable.
The political units which, by vocation or necessity, rally around one or
other of the two camps, also act as a consequence of two considerations:
to a degree, the interest of the coalition is their own interest, yet the in¬
terest of the coalition does not exactly coincide with their own interest.
Let us consider the alliances within the multipolar system: each of the
chief actors, temporarily associated, is alarmed by the growth of its chief
ally (or of its chief allies) even when the enemy (or the enemies) is not
(or is not yet) conquered. The benefits of a common victory are never
equitably distributed: the weight of a state is a function of the strength
it possesses at the time of negotiations more than of the merits it has
acquired during the hostilities (this “realistic” proposition scandalized France
when the British and Americans suggested it in 1918). The rivalry among
allies has not the same character in a bipolar system. The more distinct
this configuration is, the more the two great powers prevail over their
partners and the more the alliances tend to become permanent. As a member
of a permanent alliance, opposed to another equally permanent alliance,
the secondary state has a major interest in the security or in the victory
of the whole of which it is a parfS it resigns itself more easily to the
growth of its rival-partners. Yet Thucydides’ narrative shows over and over
that Athens was feared by her allies. The secondary states would feel quite
at one with their “bloc” (its success is my success) if the fate of each,
within the alliance, was not affected by the relative forces of the partners;
if the leader were purely a protector or an arbitrator: a borderline case, to
say the least.
Hkf it is a part voluntarily.
13
THEORY
The world being what it is, each political unit tries to influence the
policy of the alliance in the direction of its own interests or to reserve the
greatest possible amount of its forces for enterprises which directly concern
it. In 1959 what the French diplomats understood by the common policy
of the Atlantic bloc was Anglo-American support of the pacification of
Algeria, a task to which France was dedicating the majority of its army,
gradually reducing its contribution to the NATO shield. The difficulties
of a diplomacy or a strategy of coalition, though somewhat attenuated within
permanent coalitions, cemented by a common ideology or an external threat,
still remain fundamentally the same: the various ways of maneuvering,
of fighting, of conquering do not benefit the partners equally. Even if
the latter were in agreement as to the estimate of risks and opportunities—
which is never the case, given the uncertainty of these estimates—they
would have rational motives for controversy, for the possible diplomatic or
strategic methods largely involve, even for sincere allies, an unequal dis¬
tribution of immediate sacrifices and eventual gains.
As for the non-engaged, they consist primarily of those political units
external to the system which most often have no reason to side with one
coalition or the other and which may even have advantages to gain from a
generalized warfare weakening both groups of belligerents. The state ex¬
ternal to the system is, in both cases, induced by calculation to intervene:
either if it expects the victory of one of the two camps to afford it ad¬
vantages superior to the cost of the aid necessary to insure that victory; or
if it fears the victory of one of the two camps because that victory seems
likely if it were to remain passive. This latter case illuminates a possible
motive of American intervention in 1917 (which does not imply that this
intervention had no other causes). Perhaps the Persian intervention at the
end of the Peloponnesian War can be classified under the same heading.
As to the choice of states situated within the system—taking sides or
remaining neutral—it chiefly depends, assuming each desire neutrality, on
the security to be derived from isolation. The small state’s geographical
situation and actual resources are the two decisive factors: it is no accident
that in 1949, when the Atlantic Pact was signed, Switzerland and Sweden,
which did not join it, had the two strongest armies on the Continent west
of the Iron Curtain. On the other hand, as Thibaudet writes, commenting
on Thucydides, a maritime power cannot allow the neutrality of a single
island.
The multipolar and bipolar configurations are as radically opposed as
they are pure types. At one extreme, each principal actor is the enemy
and the possible partner of all the rest. At the other, there are only two
principal actors, enemies by position if not by ideology. In the first case
alliances are temporary, in the second they are lasting; in the first case
the allies do not recognize any leader, in the second all the political
units, save the two leaders, are subject to the will of the latter. In the
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS 139
first case several units remain outside the alliance, in the second all units
are willy-nilly obliged to lend their allegiance to one or the other of the
leaders, to aggregate themselves into one or the other of the blocs.
Intermediate conditions are obviously conceivable and even more often
real than the pure types. Even within a homogeneous multipolar system, an
actor can rarely ally himself with or oppose just any actor; the stakes (the fate
of a province, the contour of a frontier) and popular passions may forbid a
reconciliation which a rational calculation would not exclude. Even in a
system with many chief actors, one or two of the latter are more im¬
portant than the rest. If generalized warfare breaks out between two coali¬
tions, each is more influenced by one of the actors than by the other. In
other words, if generalized warfare breaks out, a multipolar configuration
tends of itself to approach a bipolar configuration. This is why Thibaudet
and Toynbee immediately compared the First World War to the Pelopon¬
nesian War, although the pre-1914 European system was still multipolar:
the comparison involved the generalization of a conflict, gradually embrac¬
ing all the units in the system and confronting a league directed by the
insular power with a league grouped around the continental power, Athens
and England, Sparta and Germany. Since then, commentators have alluded
to Thucydides to emphasize the bipolar configuration, because the world
after 1945 presents such a configuration. But obviously the Greek system
differs by nature from the present system, just as the superiority of Athens
and Sparta over the other cities was not of the same genre as the superiority
of the two giants today.
Thus it is not a question of formulating laws according to which a
bipolar system would function or develop. The geometry of diplomatic rela¬
tions is comparable to the battle plans drawn up by the German strategists
(a double flank encirclement: the battle of Cannes; the collapse of one
flank: the battle of Leuthen, etc.). The diplomatic configurations, like the
battle plans, are few in number, because the modes of distribution of
forces within a system or the movements of armies involve only a few
typical models. The theory of models, however, permits neither the stra¬
tegist to know in advance the maneuver he should perform, nor the his¬
torian to foresee what a given system, whether multipolar or bipolar, will
become.
At best we may note several structural characteristics of a bipolar system.
Such a system may not, as such, be more unstable or more belligerent than
a multipolar system, but it is more seriously threatened by a generalized
and inexorable war. Indeed, if all the political units belong to one camp
or the other, any kind of local conflict concerns the whole of the system.
The balance between the two camps is affected by the behavior of many
small units. Lacking a "third man,” whether arbitrator or contributor, the
two great powers are perpetually in conflict, directly or through intermedi¬
aries. In order to reach an understanding, they would have to trace a
140
THEORY
demarcation line, distribute zones of influence, forbid dissidence: the client
of one would not have the right to shift to the camp of the other, and
each would be obliged to desist from inciting the other’s allies to dissidence.
More or less precise rules of this nature seem to have existed in Greece
during the period which preceded the Peloponnesian War. It was difficult
for the two ruling city-states to respect these rules, still more difficult to
impose respect for them upon their respective allies.
In such a system, indeed, it is the fate of the satellites which is both
the occasion and the stake of the conflicts between the great powers. Yet,
depending on the rigidity or the flexibility of the coalitions, responsibility
for the conflicts rests principally upon the satellites or principally upon
the leaders. In the Greece Thucydides describes, the supremacy of Athens
at sea and of Sparta on land was not overwhelming. The fleets of Corcyra
or of Corinth were enough to modify the relation of forces. The great
powers did not exert a sovereign command upon their allies, and the latter
could, in their own interests, involve their leaders in a struggle to the
death.
Lastly, this system which, by the absence of the "third man,” makes a
generalized war more likely, also makes it almost inevitable that a gen¬
eralized war becomes ideological. To avoid fighting, the great powers must
prohibit shifts of allegiance. Once they have begun fighting, how could
they forego provoking dissidence? The two great powers rarely have the
same institutions, particularly when the respective bases of their military
forces are not the same. Within the units, factions are formed, some favor¬
ing peace, others war, some championing one of the leaders, others another.
The preferences for one kind of institution or another govern such as¬
sumptions of position, at least in part. All the units are increasingly divided
between advocates of one or the other coalition, each coalition exploiting
these internal quarrels in order to weaken the enemy units.
The peace of a system having a bipolar configuration requires the stabili¬
zation of state clienteles by agreement of state leaders, hence the ban on
recruiting partisan clients within states. This ban is dropped once the
death-struggle is launched. But peace is warlike or war is cold when this
ban does not exist before the death-struggle is launched.
4. The Bipolar System of the Greek City-States
The formal analysis we have just conducted does not afford us a means of
forecasting but a kind of outline. Given a bipolar configuration, the
historian or the sociologist must traverse these stages if he wishes to gain an
understanding of events: 1. Which of the coalitions are in conflict? What
degree of rigidity does each exhibit? What are the instruments of power
wielded by each of the leader-states? What is the degree of superiority of
each of the leader-states over its partners, whether allies or satellites? 2. If
the system has provoked a death-struggle, what were the occasions or causes
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS I4I
of the explosion? 3. How does the conflict occur, before or during the
death-struggle, between the two coalitions, between the leading states, be¬
tween them and their respective allies? In other words, we must understand
the nature and structure of each of the coalitions, the occasions and basic
reasons for their opposition, and finally the style and modes of their combat.
The first book of The Peloponnesian War provides an admirable applica¬
tion of these principles. From it we shall borrow an illustration of these
requirements of analysis: “In the face of this great danger, the command of
the confederate Hellenes was assumed by the Lacedaemonians in virtue of
their superior power; and the Athenians having made up their minds to
abandon their city, broke up their homes, threw themselves into their ships,
and became a naval people. This coalition, after repulsing the barbarian,
soon afterward split into two sections, which included the Hellenes who
had revolted from the king, as well as those who had aided him in the
war. At the head of one stood Athens, at the head of the other Lacedaemon,
one the first naval, the other the first military power in Hellas. For a short
time the league held together, till the Lacedaemonians and Athenians quar¬
reled, and made war upon each other with their allies, a duel into which
all the Hellenes sooner or later were drawn, though some might at first
remain neutral. . . . The policy of Lacedaemon was not to exact tribute
from her allies, but merely to secure their subservience to her interests by
establishing oligarchies among them; Athens, on the contrary, had by de¬
grees deprived hers of their ships, and imposed instead contributions in
money on all except Chios and Lesbos.’® Two city-states dominate the
others, each with a typical element of military force; all the other city-
states group around them. The domination of Athens is financial (the
allies pay tribute) and maritime (the ships of the allies are “integrated”
into the Athenian fleet). The Spartan alliance was founded on the
oligarchic character of the regime of the city-states which took her side
and also, as Thucydides often says, on the concern of the city-states to
preserve their liberties, which the power of Athens endangered.
The case of Corcyra furnishes an example of how the leading states do
not respect the treaty which they have concluded in order to avoid war, an
example whose significance is apparent as soon as we employ modem con¬
cepts. Corcyra and Corinth (the first the colony of the second) began a
dispute concerning Epidaurus, claimed by each as a colony. Corcyra was
an “uncommitted” city-state, a fact on which both sides, in their contra¬
dictory arguments, agree. Why did Corcyra keep out of the pact? Accord¬
ing to the Corinthians, because “their geographical situation makes them
independent of others” (I, 37); according to Corcyrans seeking the aid of
Athens, because Corcyra once believed "in the wise precaution of refusing
to involve ourselves in alliances with other powers, lest we should also
0 Book I, 18. Crawley translation.
142,
THEORY
involve ourselves in rislcs of their choosing dangers of a foreign alliance
according to the will of our neighbor” (I, 32) only to discover, at the
eleventh hour, that this isolation was “folly and weakness.” The extension
and imbrication of alliances made it increasingly difficult for political units
of any importance not to ally themselves with one or tire other of the
great powers.
Is it consonant with the treaty linking Athens and Sparta in the interest
of peace that an uncommitted unit should join one of the two camps? Is
the shift from neutrality to alliance contradictory to the pact or not? Ac¬
cording to all the orators, the pact forbids defections, the unit that be¬
longs to a coalition must not leave it. The Corinthian advocates say as
much to the Athenians: “Do not lay down the principle that defection is
to be patronized” (I, 40). If one camp receives the defectors of the other,
the adverse camp will do the same. “If you make it your policy to receive
and assist all offenders, you will find that just as many of your dependencies
will come over to us, and the principle that you establish will press less
heavily on us than on yourselves” (I, 40). The supreme principle is “that
every power has a right to punish her own allies” (I, 43)).
The case of Corcyra, seeking the assistance of Athens, was difficult.
Formally Corcyra, having been uncommitted, did not fall under the in¬
fluence of the ban on receiving defectors. The Corinthians admitted as
much: according to the provisions of the treaty “it shall be competent
for any state, whose name was not down on the list, to join whichever
side it pleases” (I, 40). But the spirit of the treaty excludes, the Corin¬
thians say, those allegiances which in themselves constitute an aggression
with regard to the other camp. “But this agreement is not meant for those
whose object in joining is the injury of other powers, but for those whose
need of support does not arise from the fact of defection, and whose
adhesion will not bring to the power that is mad enough to receive them
war instead of peace” (I, 40). In modern terms, the treaty involves two
ambiguities: its function was to avoid a rupture of the equilibrium of
forces, yet the allegiance of certain uncommitted parties, which is not
explicitly forbidden, risks provoking this rupture. On the other hand, the
uncommitted parties, which retain the right to choose their allegiance,
cannot all call upon the treaty as their authority. If Corcyra, which
turns against Corinth (whose colony she has been) became the ally of
Athens, this commitment would be, in fact and in spirit, an aggression
against Corinth and therefore against Sparta. The Athenians are thus aware
of the scope of their action when they conclude a simple defensive al¬
liance with Corcyra, involving reciprocal aid in case of attack against
Corcyra, Athens or their allies. An offensive alliance would have involved
the risk of Athenian participation in an attack against Corinth, hence war
with Sparta.
What motive determines the behavior of the Athenians? According to
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS
143
Thucydides, a calculation of forces in a period when each side anticipates
the imminent war. "If any of you imagine that war is far off, he is griev¬
ously mistaken, and is blind to the fact that Lacedaemon regards you with
jealousy and desires war” (I, 33). That is how the Corcyran ambassadors
express themselves before the assembly of Athens. And Thucydides him¬
self: “For it began now to be felt that the coming of the Peloponnesian
War was only a question of time, and no one was willing to see the naval
power of such magnitude as Corcyra sacrificed to Corinth; though if they
could let them weaken each other by mutual conflict, it would be no
bad preparation for the struggle which Athens might one day have to
wage with Corinth and the other naval powers” (I, 44). There are three
navies which count in Greece, that of Athens, of Corcyra and of Corinth.
If Athens, out of fear of breaking the trace, lets Corcyra and Corinth
unite, would she not lose face by publicizing her fear at the same time
as she would sacrifice a considerable military advantage? When the su¬
premacy of the leading states over their partners is not overwhelming, they
are led by their allies more than they lead them. They cannot, in effect,
abandon their allies without weakening themselves dangerously. Athens
did not possess such superiority that she could scorn the Corcyran con¬
tribution.
The conflict of Potidaea, which Thucydides presents as the second im¬
mediate cause of the great war, was formally of the same type. Potidaea
was a colony of Corinth and an ally of Athens. The Athenians decided
it was necessary and legitimate to punish a defecting ally. They clashed
with the Corinthians, who were desirous to defend their colony. The
Lacedaemonians, in violation of the pact, had detached from Athens a
tribute-paying city-state “and were openly fighting against her on the side
of the Potidaeans” (I, 66). The interlinking of relations among cities—
relations between metropolis and colony, between hegemonic city and al¬
lies—often made the determination of the just and the unjust uncertain.
But according to Thucydides, these ambiguities of “international law”
were not the real cause of the conflict. The historian says as much him¬
self, in a famous formula: “The real cause I consider to be the one which
was formally most kept out of sight. The growth of the power of Athens
and the fear this inspired in Lacedaemon made war inevitable” Cl, 24).
The Corinthians, speaking at the Congress of Sparta and her allies, de¬
nounced the bad conduct—contrary to justice and to treaties—of the Athe¬
nians. But the essential accusation is that Athens was on the point of
assuming “the role of tyrant in relation to all without distinction, that she
commanded some and dreamed of commanding others” (I, 74). After the
vote of the Lacedaemonians deciding that the truce had been broken and
that they would have to wage war, Thucydides repeats that the Spartans
had been less convinced by their allies; rather “they feared the growth
144
THEORY
of the power of the Athenians, seeing most of Hellas already subject to
them" (I, 88).
Considerations of equilibrium and considerations of equity (justice, con¬
ventions) are mingled, at every moment, in the course of the narrative and
in the arguments of the first book, which is devoted to the study of what
we should call the diplomatic circumstances and the origins of the war. But
the historian does not hesitate to regard the first as decisive, and to put in
the actors’ mouths admissions whose frankness is inconceivable in our day
and age, which ideology and the role of the people condemn to hypocrisy.
The Athenian delegates declared before the Spartan assembly: "It follows
that it was not a very wonderful action, or contrary to the common prac¬
tice of mankind, if we did accept an empire that was offered to us, and
refused to give it up under pressure of three of the strongest motives, fear,
honor, and interest. And it was not we who set the example, for it has
always been the law that the weaker should be subject to the stronger.
Besides, we believed ourselves to be worthy of our position, and so you
have thought us up to now, when the calculations of interest have made
you take up the cry of justice—a consideration which no one had ever yet
brought forward to hinder his ambition when he had a chance of gaining
anything by might” (I, 76).
The obsession of equilibrium, the fear the expansion of the Athenian
Empire inspired in the Spartans, the resentment of the allies against the
Athenian hegemony do not have as their chief cause the material disad¬
vantages of the rule of a single power. Of course, the allies are angered by
paying tribute or furnishing ships, Sparta fears for her very existence
should Athens become irresistible. But Hume has understood Thucydides
precisely when he describes, among the city-states, a conflict of amour-
propre rather than a concern for security —jealous emulation rather than
cautious politics. The hegemonic city seeks the honor of ruling as much or
more than the commercial or financial benefits of domination. The city-
states rebel against subjection, which is as unworthy of a free state as sub¬
jection to a tyrant (that is, to an absolute and arbitrary master) is unworthy
of a free man. Thus Athens, democratic and insular, appears to the Corin¬
thians and the other allies of Sparta as the major danger to the liberties of
the Greek city-states. Thucydides, a citizen of Athens, does not condemn
his fatherland for aspiring to empire, since such is the course of human
affairs, but he does not deny that the Spartan camp has been that of
traditional liberties.
Pericles’ oration counseling war gives us another proof that the meaning
of the conflict was the protection of autonomy. The supreme argument is
“no concession to the Peloponnesians.” Yielding to an ultimatum is already
accepting servitude: “For all claims from an equal, urged upon a neighbor
as commands, before any attempt at legal settlement, be they great or be
they small, have only one meaning, and that is slavery” (I, 140). The
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS 145
pretext is of no account. Let it not be imagined that “to die for Megara”
would be to die for a small thing: essentials are at stake, safeguarding the
autonomy which constitutes freedom.
When Pericles makes this oration, he considers that war is inevitable,
which is also what the leaders of the other coalition believe. In the
course of this history which Thucydides’ narrative presents embroidered
throughout by the decisions of actors, men nonetheless have, and com¬
municate to the reader, the sense of fate. Archidamos, King of Sparta, has
no more illusions than Pericles as to the duration of the war once it breaks
out: both are wise, clear-sighted men, both are resolved or resigned to the
struggle, both know that neither of the two camps will win easily. Each is
superior on one element, Athens at sea, Sparta on land. Maritime superiority
does not suffice to reduce Sparta to subjection any more than the superiority
of the hoplites will bring Athens to its knees. Thus the Corinthian am¬
bassador and Pericles proclaim, in turn: we shall win because we are the
stronger, the historian himself presenting the arguments of each side in
such a way that the extension of a hyperbolic war appears fatal in advance
and the issue, uncertain at the start, seems to be attributed either to the
role of chance, which limits but does not succeed in eliminating human
intelligence, or to the faults of the vanquished.
Certain comparisons come to the reader’s mind almost of themselves. Of
course, the comparison between the Peloponnesian War and certain wars of
contemporary history has been sketched by several authors, particularly
Thibaudet and Toynbee. Such a comparison is legitimate only provided
that it is limited in its significance and its scope. Thibaudet was describing
the American Civil War and the European wars since Charles V. The
first comparison seems without foundation. The War of Secession had as
its stake the very existence of the state, several federated states claiming
the right to leave the federation. That this war became “total” and was
waged until absolute victory in terms of a strategic erosion still does not
justify the historical analogy with a general war which concerns a whole
international system, even involving, step by step, marginal or external
political units. Of all the European wars, only that of 1914-18 or perhaps
the two world wars taken together formally present analogous characteristics.
A comparison, we must repeat, that is entirely formal. In Greece, the
dominance of a sea power was most feared, because it seemed most capable
of exploiting and oppressing, and perhaps, too, because it was wielded by
Athens, which outstripped Sparta in her superiority to her allies. Thibaudet
observes that in Greece it was the city-state favorable to the freedom of
persons which wdth good reason appeared to be a threat to the freedom of
other states. In 1914 a Continental state was at the same time the closest
to hegemony and the most authoritarian (Tsarist Russia aside).
In modem Europe as in ancient Greece, it is the hyperbolic amplification
of a general war which constitutes, in the eyes of historians inclined to
THEOEY
146
comparisons, the major fact, the one which requires the most explanation
and involves the most consequences. Ultimately, in fact, the system of
multipolar equilibrium, that of the Greeks or that of the Europeans, is con¬
demned if it provokes excessive and exhausting conflicts. Yet the formation
of two coalitions, each around one of the leader-states, has preceded the
explosion of the Great War and has marked a transition between the phase
of state freedom and imperial unification.
The Peloponnesian War, like the First World War, ended in the victory
of the camp which sought to safeguard the freedom of city-states. Sparta's
partial hegemony was brief, like that of Thebes which followed. Having
rejected the only hegemony which might have been lasting, the Greek
city-states were conquered by Macedonia, then by Rome. Having rejected
the hegemony of Germany, the European states were subject on one side
to the joint domination of Soviet Russia and the Communist doctrine
(or practice), on the other to American protection. Perhaps, to quote the
Athenian ambassadors, this latter provokes more bitterness in that it dis¬
simulates itself under the principle of equality. “They are so habituated to
associate with us as equals, that any defeat whatever that clashes with their
notions of justice, whether it proceeds from a legal judgment or from the
power which our empire gives us, makes them forget to be grateful for
being allowed to retain most of their possessions, and more vexed at a part
being taken, than if we had from the first cast law aside and openly
gratified our covetousness. If we had done so, not even they would have
disputed that the weaker must give way to the stronger” (I, 77).
The victory of the camp of state freedom is not enough to save a system
of equilibrium disintegrated by the violence, the duration and the cost of
generalized warfare.
We have not even attempted to establish the list of rules of conduct to be
deduced from the bipolar configuration of the relation of forcesP The rea¬
sons such rules are of little significance or arbitrary are the same in either
a bipolar or a multipolar configuration. The maintenance of the configuration
is not the primary or supreme objective of the actors. It is therefore not
legitimate or, if one prefers, not instructive to consider as rules of rational
conduct the precepts which must be respected in order to preserve the
system. The only universal and formal rule is that of equilibrium in the
vague sense Hume gave it: each actor (I should add each principal actor)
tries not to be at the mercy of the others. It increases its resources or its
degree of mobilization; it maneuvers in the diplomatic field, forms or breaks
0 Morton A. Kaplan distinguishes the rigid bipolar system from the loose bipolar sys¬
tems, but in both cases he introduces into his model certain elements appropriate to the
present system (e.g., the international actors). The comparison would be long and, for
our purposes, of no use.
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS I 47
alliances in order to avoid that subjection contrary to its idea of itself
and perhaps fatal to its security. This desire “not to be at the mercy of
others” will be expressed in varying behavior, depending on whether there
is a plurality of chief actors of more or less equal capacities or “two giants”
overwhelming their rivals. The combination of the desire “not to be at the
mercy of others” and of a typical configuration permits us to sketch
models of systems. But the models, characterized by only two traits—a
desire for equilibrium and the configuration of the relation of forces—
remain indeterminate in too many respects for us to be able to discover
the laws of their functioning or development.
Is it possible, starting from the preceding analyses, to list the variables
which sociological or historical study of a given international system must
consider? The concept of a variable seems to me of questionable use, since
these data are essentially qualitative and do not even comprise the whole of
the distinction of more and less. But if we replace the term variable by a
neutral term, it seems to me possible to derive from the preceding chapters
a list of chief elements of an international system, or, if one prefers, a list
of questions which the study of international systems should answer.
Two elements control the systems: the configuration of the relation of
forces, the homogeneity or the heterogeneity of the system. But each of these
two elements is subdivided in its turn. The actors are situated in a geo¬
graphical-historical space whose limits are more or less clearly defined. On
the frontiers, other actors are half-integrated, half-alien to the system. The
forces peculiar to each actor depend on his resources and on the degree
of mobilization: this latter in its turn depends on the economic, military,
political regime. The internal regimes which influence the relation of forces
determine the nature and stakes of the conflicts. The same political unit
sometimes changes objectives when it changes regimes. The dialogue of
political units is a function of the dialogue of classes or men in power:
at one extreme, the solidarity of kings against peoples, as was said in the
last century (or the solidarity of Communist parties, in Eastern Europe,
against the counterrevolution), at the other, the solidarity of the govern¬
ments of a state (or of a side) with the rebels or the revolutionaries within
the rival or enemy state (or side). Between the two is sandwiched the
diplomacy of non-intervention, each state inhibiting itself, whatever its
ideological sympathies or its national interest, from intervening in favor of
either the established power or of the revolution in case of civil war,
whether open or latent.
Homogeneity and heterogeneity involve modes and countless nuances.
The system is more or less homogeneous or heterogeneous: homogeneous
in a certain zone, heterogeneous in another; homogeneous in peacetime,
heterogeneous in wartime; homogeneous with partial respect to the diplo¬
matic rule of non-interference, heterogeneous with the diplomatic use of
the techniques of revolutionary action. Heterogeneity can be that of social
THEORY
148
structures or that of political regimes, that of ideas more than that of realities
or, conversely, that of realities more than that of ideas. In any case, we do
not understand the nature of the rivalry and of the dialogue of political
units except by reference to the established power in each of them, to the
conception of legitimacy, to the external ambitions, and. to the strategy and
tactics of the ruling classes.
The configuration of the relation of forces leads, by the intermediary of
the degree of mobilization, to the internal regime; the homogeneity or
heterogeneity of the systems leads, by the intermediary of the techniques of
action, to the relation of forces. The two terms—relation of forces and homo¬
geneity of the system—are not two rigorously circumscribed variables, but
two complementary aspects of any historical constellation. The analysis of
these two aspects illuminates the system’s mode of functioning on the so¬
ciological level and the course of international relations on the historical
level: calculation of forces and dialectic of regimes or ideas are both indis¬
pensable to the interpretation of diplomatic-strategic behavior in any period;
neither the goals nor the means, neither the lawful nor the illicit are ade¬
quately determined by the calculation of forces alone or by the dialectic of
ideas alone. Once we recognize that in the middle of the fifth century b.c.
the system of the Greek city-states was bipolar and that the global system in
the middle of the twentieth century a.d. is also bipolar, the task of the so¬
ciologist and the historian begins: to specify the nature, the structure, the
functioning of the two systems.
The distinction of change in the system and change of the system is en¬
tirely relative. The diplomatic groupings may be called systems because an
event, at any point within the space considered, has repercussions which ex¬
tend to the whole grouping. But these systems do not maintain themselves
by a self-regulating mechanism, for the simple reason that none of the
chief actors subordinates his ambitions to the objective of maintaining the
system. Athens desired, or was led to desire, hegemony; she did not have as
her goal the crystallization of the bipolar structure or the equilibrium of her
own league and the Lacedaemonian league.
The same phenomenon may be considered as a change in the system or a
change of the system depending on the number of characteristics utilized to
define a historical system. The French Revolution inaugurated, certainly, a
new system, since it introduced fundamental heterogeneity. Does the acces¬
sion of Napoleon III mark a change of the system? The unification of Ger¬
many in 1871 opens another phase of European history. Does it radically alter
the European system? Such questions seem to me largely a matter of words.
It is simplest to distinguish type and case, according to the habits of our old
logic. When the configuration of the relation of forces becomes essentially
different or when homogeneity yields to heterogeneity, there is a change in
type. When heterogeneity or bipolarity are accentuated or attenuated, we
speak of either a change in the system or a change of kind. The models or
ON MULTIPOLAR SYSTEMS AND BIPOLAR SYSTEMS
I49
types of international relations serve and must serve only as a preparation for
concrete study.
Thucydides has drawn the stylized model of two powers, one based on
naval force and the other on territorial force, one with men “addicted to in¬
novation, whose designs are characterized by swiftness alike in conception
and execution,” the other with men who "have a genius for keeping what
they have got, accompanied by a total want of invention” 0 , 70), one
open, the other closed to foreigners. How many times, in recent years, has
de Tocqueville’s famous parallel been quoted as to the two peoples destined,
by a mysterious decree of Providence, each to dominate one half of the world,
the one by the plow and the other by the sword! The comparison of the
two types of societies, of the two regimes, of the two ideologies, of the two
conceptions of the international world is classical too because it is indis¬
pensable to historical and sociological understanding. The system depends
on what the two poles, concretely, are, not only on the fact that they are two.
A system which covers the planet differs, by nature, from a system of
Greek city-states or European states. The Soviet Union and the United
States do not run the same risk of being swept into war in spite of them¬
selves by the disputes of their allies or their satellites as Sparta or Athens.
The means of destruction which the two protagonists possess change perhaps
the essence of the diplomatic-strategic competition. On every level, differ¬
ences of quantity provoke qualitative revolutions.
chapter VI
Dialectics of Peace and War
War is to be found throughout all history and all civilizations. With axes
or cannon, arrows or bullets, chemical explosives or atomic chain reactions,
remote or immediate, in isolation or en masse, by accident or according to
rigorous method, men have killed each other, using the instruments which
custom and the communities’ knowledge afforded them.
Thus we might regard a "formal typology” of wars and peace as illusory,
only a sociological typology*] retaining the concrete modes of phenomena
being valid. Yet, if the following analyses help illuminate the logic of dip¬
lomatic and strategic behavior, the formal typology they reveal may be of
some use.
i. Types of Peace and Types of War
I have taken war as my point of departure because strategic-diplomatic
behavior is related to the eventuality of armed conflict, because the latter is,
so to speak, the denouement of operations on trust. This time we shall take
peace as our point of departure because peace is rationally the goal to which
societies tend.
This proposition does not contradict the principle of the unity of foreign
policy, of the continuous relations among nations. The diplomat does not
forget the possibility and the requirements of arbitration by arms during the
period when he refuses to resort to violent means. Rivalry between political
communities does not begin with the breaking of treaties, nor does it end
with the signing of a truce. But whatever the goal of foreign policy—pos¬
session of territory, domination over men, triumph of an idea—this goal is not
war itself. Some men love battle for its own sake; certain peoples engage in
war the way others engage in sport. But at the level of the so-called higher
civilizations, when states are legally organized, war can no longer be any-
0We shall find one in IChapter XIlJ in [Part II | of this book.
DIALECTICS OF PEACE AND WAR
I 5 I
thing but a means if consciously desired, or a calamity if provoked for a
cause unknown to the actors.
Peace has hitherto appeared to be the more or less lasting suspension of
violent modes of rivalry between political units. Peace is said to prevail
when the relations between nations do not involve the military forms of
struggle. But since these peaceful relations occur within the shadow of past
battles and in the fear or the expectation of future ones, the principle
of peace, in the sense Montesquieu gives this term in his theory of govem-
mentsp] is not different in nature from that of wars: peace is based on
power, that is, on the relation between the capacities of acting upon each
other possessed by the political units. Since the relations of power, in peace¬
time, without being the exact reflections of the actual or potential relation of
forces, are a more or less distorted expression of it, the various types of peace
can be related to the types of relation of forces. I distinguish three types of
peace— equilibrium, hegemony, empire: in a given historical space, the forces
of the political units are in balance, or else they are dominated by those of
one among them, or else they are outclassed by those of one among them
to the point where all the units, save one, lose their autonomy and tend to
disappear as centers of political decisions. The imperial state, in the end,
reserves to itself the monopoly of legitimate violence.
One might object that imperial peace thereby ceases to be, by definition,
a "situation of external policy.” Imperial peace would not be distinguished
from civil peace: it would be the internal order of an empire. This objection
might stand were the typology purely abstract, without relation to the data of
history. Yet if there are cases in which imperial peace, once established,
becomes indistinguishable from peace among nations, reducing imperial
peace as such to civil peace would lead us to misunderstand the diversity of
the engagements.
The peace within the German Empire after 1871, despite shreds of sov¬
ereignty retained by Bavaria, for instance, differed less and less, as the
years passed, from the internal peace of the French Republic. On the other
hand, the Greek city-states, conquered by Philip and led by Alexander to
the conquest of Asia, had not lost all political-administrative autonomy; they
were not deprived of all the attributes which we regard as constituting
sovereignty; they possessed immediately, in case of revolt, an embryo of
armed forces. The Jewish war would remind us, if necessary, of the pre¬
cariousness of the Roman peace; the conquered peoples were not entirely
disarmed, the ancient institutions and sovereigns, henceforth protected by
Rome, were overlapped by the imperial order but not eliminated. In other
words, imperial peace becomes civil peace insofar as the memory of previously
independent political units are effaced, insofar as individuals within a paci-
[Urhat is, the sentiment or, as we should say today, the emotion or impulse necessary
to maintain a type of government—virtue, honor, fear.
152.
THEORY
fied zone feel themselves less united to the traditional or local community
and more to the conquering state.
The empire which Bismarck forged with iron and fire became a national
state: the Roman Empire remained a pacified zone to the end. The kings of
France created the French nation: for a time France caused imperial peace
to prevail throughout North Africa.
Between peace by equilibrium and peace by empire is sandwiched the
■peace by hegemony. The absence of war does not result from the approxi¬
mate equality of forces prevailing among political units and forbidding any
one of them or any coalition to impose its will; it results, on the contrary,
from the incontestable superiority of one of the units. This superiority is such
that the unsatisfied states despair of modifying the status quo, and yet the
hegemonic state does not try to absorb the units reduced to impotence. It
does not abuse hegemony, it respects the external forms of state indepen¬
dence, it does not aspire to empire.
In a system of units jealous of their independence, hegemony is a pre¬
carious mode of equilibrium. The German Reich, after 1870, possessed the
kind of hegemony that Bismarck hoped to make acceptable to the other
European states by means of moderation, thus appeasing their fears or re¬
sentments. The Chancellor’s successors were less fortunate; they could not
prevent the formation of alliances re-establishing equilibrium. Perhaps Bis¬
marck’s Germany does not deserve to be called hegemonic, since its hegemony
was limited to the Continent and the latter did not constitute a closed sys¬
tem. Yet, if we take into account Great Britain and her maritime extensions,
the Reich was not frankly hegemonic. It had a preponderance on land as
France had before it during the first part of the reign of Louis XIV, or
Spain in the sixteenth century. England had always prevented such a pre¬
ponderance from turning into an empire or even an uncontested hegemony.
The German preponderance would have become hegemony if the Reich,
having beaten France and Russia, could have signed a peace of victory or
compromise with Great Britain. The Kaiser’s Reich would have been con¬
tent with a hegemonic peace—Hitler’s would have dictated an imperial peace.
In North America the hegemonic peace enforced by the United States is
not a partial and fugitive aspect of the system of equilibrium: it is the lasting
result of the disproportion, indicated on the map and accentuated by history,
between the forces of the Republic of the United States and those of Mexico
or Canada. During the last century the United States had to fight a great
war not to enlarge the space of its sovereignty, but to maintain the federation.
The acquisition of Louisiana, Florida, California and Texas required only
dollars or very minor military operations. It was the Southern states’ claim to
the right of secession which caused the shedding of oceans of blood. Once
the federation was consolidated and the western and southern lands were
conquered and occupied, once the Indians and the other Europeans were
dominated or expelled, the United States was too powerful for a system of
DIALECTICS OF PEACE AND WAR
1 53
equilibrium to be constituted on the American continent, too indifferent to
the glory of ruling, not needing land to threaten the independence of the
neighboring states to the north and south. This combination of hegemony
and the good-neighbor policy is called the pax Americana. The hegemony of
the United States has also contributed to the peace which has prevailed in
South America since the Organization of American States (created at the
instigation of the United States) forbade open war between states. (Never¬
theless, internal disputes, the conflicts of regimes and the repercussions of
world diplomacy are generating a kind of cold war there.)
Neither the ancient world nor Asia nor modern Europe has known a last¬
ing phase between equilibrium and empire. The Greco-Latin civilization of
the Mediterranean, after long periods of disturbance, evolved toward impe¬
rial peace. In Asia the three great civilizationP-l alternated between peace by
equilibrium and imperial peace. In Japan, peace by equilibrium was retro¬
spectively considered as a feudal dispersion of sovereignty because the Toku-
gawa imperial peace, thanks to the homogeneity of culture and institutions,
turned into civil peace. The imperial unity achieved in China over two thou¬
sand years ago—as a result of the final victory of one state over its rival-
only succeeded through alternate phases of decomposition and restoration,
of civil wars, and a peace that was both civil and imperial. In its foreign
relations, the empire hesitated between the defensive, behind its great walls,
and inclination toward impulses of expansion. Conquered by the Mongols,
then by the Manchus, it never entered (before the nineteenth century) into
a permanent system of international relations among equals. As for India,
before the British domination it had never known as a whole the equivalent
of the peace of the shoguns or of the peace of the Middle Empire, nor
had it developed a system of equilibrium comparable to that of the Greek
city-states or of the European states.
Formally, a historical space is either unified by a force or by a single sov¬
ereignty, or fragmented into autonomous centers of decision and action. In
the first case we shall call it a universal empire, in the second, warring
states. The system of equilibrium with a multipolar configuration tends to
stabilize relations among units which acknowledge each other and to limit
the conflicts that cause one unit to oppose another. As a matter of fact,
the conflicts have always, at one period or another, extended and intensified
until the partner-rivals within a civilization appear to be warring states, re¬
sponsible for the common ruin, to the observer who has studied the centuries
that have elapsed between the time of the actors and the observer, the future
of the former and the latter’s past.
The ternary classification of the forms of peace provides at the same time
the most formal and the most general classification of wars: “perfect” wars,
according to the political notion of war, are inter-state. They bring into
OOThe word taken in the sense of Spengler’s “cultures” or Toynbee’s “societies.”
154
THEORY
conflict political units which recognize each other’s existence and legitimacy.
We shall call super-state or imperial the wars that have as their object, origin
or consequence the elimination of certain belligerents and the formation of
a unit on a higher level. We shall call infra-state or infra-imperial the wars
that have as their stake the maintenance or the decomposition of a political
unit, whether national or imperial.
Inter-state wars become imperial when one of the actors in an international
system, whether voluntarily or not, is led to establish his hegemony or em¬
pire over his rival, in case of victory. Inter-state wars tend to be amplified into
hyperbolic war when one of the actors ventures to acquire an overwhelming
superiority of forces: such was the case in the Peloponnesian War or in the
First World War. The violence of the conflict can be imputed neither
to the technique of combat nor to the passions of the belligerents, but to the
geometry of the relation of forces. It is the magnitude of the stake—freedom
of the Greek city-states or of the European states—that inflames military
ardor. Great wars often mark the shift from one configuration to another,
from one system to another, and this shift itself has many causes.
In a general way, we cannot attribute to wars of a determined category
this or that concrete characteristic. Infra-state or infra-imperial wars such as
the war of the Jews against Rome, of the Chouans against the French Rev¬
olution, wars of secession such as the war of Algerian liberation, which
bring into conflict an organized power and those populations which refuse
to obey it, are often among the most cruel; they are, in certain respects,
civil wars, especially if the established power wins. Similarly, war becomes
imperial when one of the belligerents brandishes a transnational principle,
and the inter-state conflict is charged with partisan passions. The enemy
is then simultaneously alien and adversary (or heretic or traitor).
It would be just as dangerous to insist on these abstract notions. Men are
not always interested in safeguarding the political unit to which they belong
or the historical idea their state incarnates. There are units which outlive
themselves, and ideas devoid of meaning. Even if these categories determined
the violence of the hostility, the former alone determines neither the dura¬
tion of the combat nor the conduct of the combatants.
2. Stakes of War and Principles of Peace
These two formal typologies each require further analysis. If the three
kinds of peace—peace by equilibrium, by hegemony, and by empire—have
power as their principle JUthe question will be asked: is there no other princi¬
ple of peace except power? If wars are not concretely defined by their inter-,
supra- and infra-state character, it will be asked: what other qualifications
should be applied to them in order to define them?
0This word, may I remind the reader, is used here in the sense Montesquieu gives it.
DIALECTICS OF PEACE AND WAR
155
Let us answer tills last question first. Many classifications of wars are
possible and have been proposed. Perhaps none of them can be accepted
without question; perhaps many classifications have some validity. It is not
evident that the different kinds of wars can be organized into a harmonious
scheme. It seems to me, however, that the preceding typology, justified by
the relation it establishes between the types of peace and the structure of the
international system, can be coupled to two other typologies, one based
on the nature of the political units and the historical ideas which the bellig¬
erents incarnate, the other on the nature of the weapons and the military
machinery. The first of these two typologies implies a reference to ends, the
second a reference to means.
It is customary to speak of feudal wars, dynastic wars, national wars,
colonial wars. All these expressions suggest that the mode of internal organi¬
zation of collectivities imposes its quality, gives its style to the belligerent be¬
havior of the political units. In reality, the mode of organization helps de¬
termine, if it does not exclusively determine, the occasions and stakes of the
conflicts, the judgments of statesmen on legitimate and illegitimate action,
their conception of diplomacy and of war. The principle of legitimacyto
return to an expression used above, answers two questions at once: who com¬
mands within the state? to what unit should a specific territory or population
belong? Wars resemble the principle of legitimacy prevailing over the space
and in the time within which they are waged.
The principle of legitimacy creates the occasion or the cause of the conflict.
The relations of vassal to suzerain are intermingled in such a way that con¬
tradictions appear. The desire for power leads to the failure of certain vassals
to fulfill their obligations. The limits of legitimate action are difficult to trace
when so many inferior powers retain their own military means or claim some
freedom of decision. As long as land or men belong to ruling families, the
stake of a war is a province which two sovereigns dispute by means of juridi¬
cal arguments or guns, or a throne which two princes claim. The day the
collective consciousness recognizes that men have the right to choose their
political unit, wars become national, either because two states claim the same
province or because populations divided among traditional units seek to con¬
stitute a single state. Finally, if public opinion were to admit tomorrow that
the national era has passed and that economic or military requirements of the
great ensembles should prevail over the preferences of the governed, wars
would become imperial as they have never yet been: the Roman conquerors
in the Mediterranean, the Europeans in Asia and Africa did not deny the
national idea; they were unaware of it or refused its advantages to populations
or to classes of men they regarded as inferior and unworthy, either tempo-
0Of course, the word principle is used here in its ordinary sense, and not in that of
Montesquieu.
THEORY
156
rarily or permanently, of the dignity of citizenship. This time, the conquerors
would deny the idea in the name of material necessities.
Neither Nazis nor Communists invoked such necessities. The true jus¬
tification of the Third Reich’s undertaking, as the doctrinaires of Nazism
conceived it, was the racial superiority of the German people. The true jus¬
tification of world Sovietization, according to the doctrinaires of Marxism-
Leninism, is the superiority or the inevitable victory of the regime which they
call socialist. In our time, and perhaps in other periods as well, conquerors
feel the need of justifying themselves, morally or historically, in their own
eyes.
The principles of legitimacy provoke three kinds of conflicts: those which
result from the plurality of possible interpretations, those which derive from
the contradiction between the existing status and the new principle, and
those which result from the actual application of the principle and from the
modifications that appear in the relation of forces.
The claims of the King of England to the throne of France belong to the
first category, as do the incompatible claims of Germany and France to
Alsace, an imperial territory in the Middle Ages, of Germanic dialect and
culture, conquered by Louis XIV, and whose population, in 1871, wanted to
remain French. In 1914 the territorial status of Europe was a compromise be¬
tween the national idea and the heritage of dynastic rights. The partition of
Poland, the multinational empires of Austria-FIungary and Turkey were the
work of past centuries. They did not conform to the ideas of the age. Yet
every modification of territorial status risked upsetting the equilibrium. The
guardians of European order belonged to the past; perhaps they were working
for peace. The champions of the national idea were accounted bellicose in
the immediate present, even if they were peace-loving in the long run.
We need not even bring up the countless cases in which a state, absolute
monarchy or democratic republic seeks to “round out” its territory, to explain
the frequency of inter-state conflicts. The tendency to justification, the desire
for recognition, both create more occasions for quarrels than are submitted to
arbitration. Even if the permanent instability of the material conditions (eco¬
nomic, political, demographic) did not compel an incessant and precarious
adjustment of equilibrium, the evolution of historical ideas would burden
the statesman with the heavy task of reconciling the changing imperatives
of justice with the constant necessity of equilibrium. It is even easier to un¬
derstand, in the light of this analysis, why the classical jurists should have
distinguished legal wars from just wars, left it to moralists to determine what
justice was, and urged princes not to outlaw their enemies.
Yet up to now we have enumerated only the historical ideas which were,
as such, ideas of statehood—in other words, which could serve as a basis for
the political organization of collectivities. Certain ideas are national, religious
or ideological. In certain periods, conflicts of ideas and rivalry for power are
inextricably mingled: sometimes the desire for national or state power pre-
DIALECTICS OF PEACE AND WAR
157
vails over religious or ideological faith, sometimes the latter gains ascendancy
over the former. The so-called realistic statesman, even if he is a dignitary of
the Church, is the man who employs the passions of crowds with a view to
the exclusive interest of the political unit which he serves, an interest identi¬
fied, as far as he is concerned, with the weakening of rival units. But the
moralist or the historian should not reproach those who, at whatever point in
the scale, set the triumph or at least the safety of their Church, or their truth,
above the reinforcement of a state that may be hostile to the supreme values.
The principle of legitimacy is often at the origin of conflicts (which does
not mean that it is their true cause); it is sometimes consecrated by the result
of the combat: the assassination of an Austrian archduke by Serbian nation¬
alists set fire to the powder; national states emerged from the explosion. But
Europe, after 1918, even had it not been lacerated by as many national quar¬
rels as Europe before the war, was also less stable. The War of 1939, provoked
by a desire for empire, ended in two worlds, each more or less in conformity
with the idea of one of the factions of the victorious alliance.
The historical idea is linked to the military force. Down through the ages,
political organization and military organization have had a reciprocal rela¬
tionship. In ancient civilization all citizens—but not the half-castes or the
slaves—were combatants. Thus the Greek city-states possessed a military force
of which number—great numbers and not small, as legend has it—was often
the foundation. An empire measured its forces by the number of its nobles
who enjoyed the right of bearing arms, and not by that of its subjects. Greece,
and not the Persian Empire, was, as H. Delbriick has shown® an almost
inexhaustible reservoir of soldiers.
Military force also depended on the available equipment and on the more
or less effective use of this equipment. Impact weapons and projectiles de¬
termined the distance between the combatants. The influence of gunpowder
on the volume of resources necessary to the armies, and hence on the di¬
mensions of the political units, is a commonplace in historical accounts. Con¬
scription and industry, universal military service and the monstrous increase
in the degree of mobilization are at the origin of the hyperbolic character
assumed by the First World War: a democratic war, since “civilians in uni¬
form” faced each other; a partially ideological war, since these citizens believed
they were “defending their souls’ll; a war of matdriel, waged until the nations
in conflict were exhausted, since the armies did not win victories of annihila¬
tion and since both the physical and human materiel mobilizable on either
side was enormous.
The double dependence of the military machine on social and political
organization, and on the techniques of destruction, does not permit us, in this
Efeee below, Chap. VIII.
□The two expressions are taken from the speech of Paul Valery when Marshal
Petain was received in the Academie Franfaise.
THEORY
I 5 8
abstract analysis, to discern pure types than can he characterized by a single
word. Each military system is an organization of arms varying with a social
hierarchy, or again, by reversing the formula, the deployment of a certain
society, taking into account the effectiveness of the weapons and their various
combinations. If the men in combat have always been, to a degree, practical
—in Auguste Comte’s sense of the word positif —that is, if they sought to
achieve goals and modify their behavior in relation to experience and rational¬
ity—they were never, before modern times, exclusively rational, that is, capa¬
ble of ignoring morality and custom in order to conceive of warfare in
terms of pure effectiveness. Further, this rationality, oriented toward an
exclusive victory over the enemy as toward a single object, would have been
partial and, in certain cases, unreasonable with regard to the privileged class:
the structure of the military system is not without influence on the structure
of society. Is that mling class rational which gives weapons to the discon¬
tented classes at the risk of weakening its own power? Throughout history it
is rare to find a ruling class which, in the manner of the Meiji reformers,
took the initiative of a political and social revolution in order to establish the
military machine indispensable to their country’s independence and strength.
More often, the privileged are incapable of overturning the order from which
they benefit and which has become incompatible with the requirements of
the system of combat: then appears an Ataturk who liquidates the Ottoman
Empire and founds a new state.
Only in our times does military technique, following the example of in¬
dustrial technique, free itself of all shackles and advance indifferent to the
human consequences of its progress. Once production or at least the capacity
for production becomes (or seems to have become) a goal in itself, how could
it be otherwise with destruction or capacity for destruction? Industry and war
are related, inseparable. The growth of one, which generous hearts acclaim,
furnishes resources to the other, which is cursed by men of good will. Lan¬
guage itself reminds us of this indissoluble alliance, which is symbolized by
the resemblance of automobiles and tanks, long files of workmen and columns
of soldiers, armored divisions and families fleeing cities: the same word,
power , designates the capacity to impose one’s will on one’s kind and to domi¬
nate nature.
Of course, a difference exists, although it is often misunderstood. Man’s
utilization of water and air, the transformation of coal into heat, of heat into
energy, the eventual domestication of the phenomena of fusion, spontaneously
produced in the sun—all the countless, foreseeable and rigorous methods for
the exploitation of natural resources belong to the order of technology.
Whether it is a question of substituting energy from coal, oil or the atom, for
labor, of manufacturing objects for which the cosmos offered elements but
not models (transformers, automobiles, refrigerators, etc.) or of improving
and multiplying the plants or animals by which humanity is fed, the behavior
remains essentially technological, in other words, it leads back to the planned
DIALECTICS OF PEACE AND WAR
159
combination of means with a view to ends. The vagueness of our knowledge
and the risks involved in applying to concrete reality laws established in the
laboratory create degrees of uncertainty, enforce margins of security; they do
not modify the essence of technological behavior, of human power over na¬
ture.
Power over men is also characterized by rationality, once the workers, ap¬
parently subject to the power of their fellow men, actually obey the impera¬
tives of technology. The authority of the technologists is not so much per¬
sonal authority as an awareness of the discipline which a humanized nature
imposes upon all. On the other hand, diplomatic-strategic action tends to
constrain or convince another center of autonomous decisions, in other words
a consciousness whose response to external challenge involves an essential
unpredictability: any consciousness may prefer death to submission.
The combined progress of the techniques of production and destruction
introduces a 'principle of peace, different from power, which usage has al¬
ready baptized. Peace by tenor is that peace which reigns (or would reign)
between political units each of which has (or would have) the capacity to
deal mortal blows to the other. In this sense, peace by terror could be also de¬
scribed as peace by impotence. When traditional peace prevailed among rival
political units, the power of each was defined by the capacity to impose its
will upon the other by the use or the threat of force. In the ideal peace by
terror, there would be no further inequality between rivals, since each would
possess thermonuclear bombs which, dropped on the other’s cities, would
claim millions of victims. Can we still speak of a fairly powerful nation, or
of equilibrium or disequilibrium, once the side which has the fewest thermo¬
nuclear bombs and the least-perfected launching vehicles still possesses the
capacity to inflict upon its enemy losses out of all proportion to the advantages
of any victory?
Peace by terror differs fundamentally from any sort of peace by power
(equilibrium, hegemony, empire). The balance of forces is still approximate,
equivocal, continually threatened either by a secondary unit changing camp
or by the unequal development of the leading states. The calculation of forces
involves risks: it is only when under fire that the virtues of armies and peoples
are revealed. The course of hostilities in relation to diplomatic and strategic
combinations adds further uncertainties. It is conceivable that terror could
lead to technical certainty. The destruction which the weakest state would
have the means of inflicting upon its enemy, without being precisely mea¬
surable in advance, would be in any case sufficient for war to be senseless,
just as the resistance of a bridge, though not precisely measurable, is in any
case sufficient to sustain the maximum weight which it will some day have
to bear.
The perfection of this peace by terror has not yet been achieved, even be¬
tween the United States and the Soviet Union. Perhaps it will never be
i6o
THEORY
achieved® In effect, it requires the certain knowledge that none of the bel¬
ligerents can, in a surprise attack, eliminate the enemy’s means of reprisal or
reduce them to such a point that the eventual reprisal no longer inflicts upon
the aggressor “unacceptable” losses. It has not been proved that this is actually
the case. Today or tomorrow, one side or the other may perfect its means of
passive defense (shelters for the population) and active defense (rockets
against bombardment planes or against ballistic missiles) as well as its means
of aggression (number and position of ballistic missiles) to the point where
the leaders are tempted by the possibility of a Pearl Harbor on a thermonu¬
clear scale—in other words, of a massive attack on all the enemy’s means of
reprisal and on several of its cities. Would not, therefore, the victim of the
aggression have to capitulate, since retaliation would not noticeably weaken
the aggressor, and would involve its own total destruction? Whatever the im¬
probability of such a hypothesis, peace by terror will only be perfected when
the advantage possessed today by the one who strikes first is suppressed or
reduced to the minimum.
Aside from the vulnerability of the means of reprisal, the uncertainty con¬
cerns also the “amount of destruction endurable” or the “threshold of satu¬
ration.” Initiating war would be absolutely senseless if the aggressor were
assured of being also totally destroyed or knew that the number of thermonu¬
clear bombs necessary to eliminate the enemy’s means of reprisal was such
that its own population or humanity as a whole would be gravely threatened
by radioactive fallout. Despite varying opinions among experts, we have not
yet reached this point. Here, the question rises: at what point of destruction
does war cease to be a justifiable political instrument? By the end of the
Thirty Years’ War the German population had been diminished by half. In
1941 the first battles cost the Soviet Union tens of millions of inhabitants
and more than a third of its industry, which had fallen into German hands.
The Soviet Union nonetheless survived and ultimately triumphed.
Of course, losing by occupation and losing by extermination, losing in a
few minutes and losing in several years are not equivalent phenomena. Let
us be content, provisionally, with noting the original factor which thermonu¬
clear weapons introduce into military calculations: they make possible de¬
struction of such magnitude that the cost of combat would in all rationality
seem to be superior to the advantage of victory. In this sense, the effect of
weapons of massive destruction could be to jeopardize Clausewitz’s formula
“war is the continuation of policy by other means.”
Between peace by power and peace by impotence exists a third term, at
least on the conceptual level: peace by satisfaction. Valery once said that
there can be no true peace except in a world where all the states are satisfied
with the status quo. But this status always reflects the relations existing at the
end of the preceding trial by force. The status which satisfies some provokes
0Cf. a detailed analysis below, Chap. XIV.
DIALECTICS OF PEACE AND WAR
161
claims from others, and this is why there are only truceP of a more or less
precarious nature.
What are the conditions, in the abstract, of a peace by satisfaction? Per¬
haps the theory of objectives will permit us to answer such a question. The
political units should first seek neither territory external to that under their
sovereignty, nor alien populations. This first condition is neither absurd nor
even unrealizable. Let us suppose that men are conscious of their nationality
—that is, of the political-cultural community to which they wish to belong;
why should the leaders seek to integrate by constraint human groups which
feel alien, or forbid them to join the nationality of their choice?
Let us suppose the national idea were universally admitted, and honestly
applied. Is this enough? Certainly not: it is necessary for political units not to
seek to extend themselves, either to increase their material or human resources,
to disseminate their institutions, or to enjoy the most vain and intoxicating
of victories, the pride of ruling. The satisfaction derived from the respect of
one principle of legitimacy must be supplemented by the suspension of
rivalry for land and men, force and idea, and even for pride.
None of these hypotheses is contradictory or even, as such, unrealizable.
But we must proceed with care: nothing is done so long as something remains
to be done. Satisfaction will be lasting and assured only on condition that it
is general. If one of the actors nourishes ambitions or is suspected of nourish¬
ing them, how could the others keep from returning to the infernal cycle of
competition? Not to take precautions if he—my neighbor, the evil one, that
is—is plotting my death, would be unreasonable and even culpable. But what
precaution will replace the superiority of strength, the use of this superiority,
while there is still time, the accumulation of resources to guarantee this su¬
periority?
In other words, peace by consent presupposes that confidence is general; it
therefore requires a revolution in the procedure of international relations, a
revolution which would bring to an end the era of suspicion and inaugurate
that of security. But this revolution, unless there is a conversion of souls, must
affect institutions. In other words, universal peace by universal consent and
mutual confidence does not seem to me effectively possible if the political
units do not find a substitute for security by force. Universal empire would
furnish this substitute, since it would suppress the autonomy of centers of
decisions. The rule of law, in the Kantian sense, would also furnish it, insofar
as the states would commit themselves to obeying the decisions of an
arbitrator, a tribunal or an assembly and have no doubt that this commitment
would be honored by all. But how would this doubt be dissipated if the
community was not in the position to constrain the criminal?
The universal state and the rule of law are not like concepts; the one ap¬
pears at the end of power politics, the other at the end of the evolution of
0Paul Valery: Regards sur le monde actuel.
THEORY
162
international law. But both ultimately imply the suppression of what has
been the essence of international politics: the rivalry of states which put their
pride and their duty in taking the law into their own hands.
Hence there has never been an international system including the whole
of the planet. The partial systems have known only peace by power. If, in
certain areas, at certain periods in time, we divine the premises of a peace by
satisfaction, the relations of power, over a larger area and on a higher level,
do not permit us to state that the principle of peace has been satisfaction.
Since 1945 we have seen the beginnings of a peace by terror (between the
Soviet Union and the United States) and a peace by satisfaction (in West¬
ern Europe). But the international system tends to become worldwide and,
thereby, the traditional types assume new appearances and are juxtaposed or
combined in a system of singular complexity.
3. Warlike Peace
Peace, whose types we have distinguished in the course of the preceding
pages, was defined strictly by the absence of war and not by a positive fac¬
ulty: virtus (to return to Spinoza’s expression). Even peace by consent does
not seem to us distinct from the world of egoism. Does the notion, current
today, of a cold war call into question the distinction between war and peace?
I do not think so. We have said that Clausewitz’s formula—war is the con¬
tinuation of policy by other means—has been replaced by its opposite: policy
is the continuation of war by other means. But these two formulas are, for¬
mally, equivalent. They both express the continuity of competition and the
use of alternately violent and non-violent means toward ends which do not
differ in essence. At most we may add that the margin of semi-violent means,
regarded as legitimate in peacetime, has a tendency to broaden, and that
Montesquieu’s precept, “nations ought in time of peace to do one another all
the good they can, and in time of war as little injury as possible,” is further
from practice now than it has ever been. But it has probably never been very
close.
The situation known as a cold war nonetheless offers certain original fea¬
tures, some of which derive from the peace hy terror, others from the double
heterogeneity, both historical and ideological, of a system extended to the
limits of the entire globe. These original features may be summarized, I
believe, by the three words deterrence, persuasion, subversion, which desig¬
nate the three modes of cold-war diplomatic-military strategy.
Peace by terror involves the use of a so-called deterrence strategy. Each of
the two super powers, possessing more or less equivalent means of destruction,
makes a play to the other by threatening to resort to the supreme argument
of weapons of mass destruction. Does peace by terror imply the permanent,
definitive character of cold war (barring a general and controlled disarma¬
ment)? This is not certain. But the present phase of the peace by terror has
special characteristics.
DIALECTICS OF PEACE AND WAR 163
First of all, it constitutes the initial phase of peace by terror. Humanity has
not yet grown accustomed to the new universe, which it is hesitantly ex¬
ploring, incapable of foregoing the threat of thermonuclear war, eager not
to put this threat into practice, uncertain of the ultimate compatibility be¬
tween the strategic use of the threat and not carrying it out.
At the time when the United States possessed an atomic monopoly, the
Soviet Union had an irresistible superiority of conventional weapons. The
inequality of risks taken by the European and American partners in the At¬
lantic Alliance created a climate of reciprocal suspicion: the desire for peace
on the part of the state that has the least to lose in case of war never seems
resolute enough for the allies who have nothing to hope for in case of con¬
flict, even in case of victory. It was not the Soviet Union’s production of
atomic and thermonuclear bombs but the development of strategic bombers
and above all of ballistic missiles which put an end to these suspicions and
convinced all the Western powers that they were in the same boat.
At this moment there appeared another cause for apprehension: was the
peace by terror really secured? At what point was the advantage of either
the United States or the Soviet Union in the race for arms, bombs and de¬
livery systems, passive defense for the population and active defense against
missiles, likely to compromise the peace by terror? Or again, to substitute
another probably better expression, in what measure is the balance of terror
as stable or unstable as the balance of forces? If the balance of terror were
perfect—giving this word the same meaning as above—the notion of the
balance of forces would have lost all meaning. But theoreticians and states¬
men are not in agreement on this point. Rightly or wrongly, the arms race
keeps alive the secret anxiety that the balance of terror is as precarious as the
old balance of power.
At the same time, humanity is questioning itself as to the prospects: is it
desirable or deplorable that the number of members of the atomic club should
increase? There is no lack of argument for both alternatives: could those
states not possessing atomic weapons be protected tomorrow by an ally? Will
the United States assume the excessive risk of the destruction of its cities in
order to save West Berlin today and Western Europe tomorrow? Or rather,
will the Russians believe that the United States will assume this risk? But
on the other hand, is it not terrifying to imagine that within ten or fifteen
years states like Egypt or China will possess weapons whose explosive power
can be counted in thousands (twenty thousand for the Hiroshima bomb) and
millions of tons of TNT (for the thermonuclear bomb)!® In short, men
have always waged the wars for which they were preparing. The advice si vis
pacem para helium justified preparations: it has never, however faithfully
EDA single thermonuclear bomb has an explosive power superior to that of all the bombs
dropped on Germany between 1939 and 1945.
THEORY
164
taken, prevented war. Can one use diplomatically the threat of a war which
one wants to avoid at almost any cost?
Peace by terror is accompanied by ideological rivalry, characteristic of all
heterogeneous systems. In the systems which include North America, Europe
and northern Asia, the two chief actors are in conflict neither for territory
nor for men. The United States and the Soviet Union both occupy an un¬
derpopulated space. They have reserves of arable soil and have no reason to
fear the growth of their populations. Now, in any bipolar system, the leaders,
incapable of ruling together, are doomed to competition, any progress of the
one seeming a danger to the other. Today’s great powers cannot rule together
because of the incompatibility of their institutions and their principles of
legitimacy .0 Therefore they have the entire planet for their theater and all
nations and contested frontiers as the stake of a dispute which they are un¬
willing to decide upon by the sword and which they cannot settle by negotia¬
tion.
Not all heterogeneous systems have provoked the equivalent of the present
modes of cold war. The origin of the novelty is a combination of industry
and conscription, of technology and democracy. During the First World War
the belligerents discovered that civilians “in uniform” did not agree, as readily
as professional soldiers, to die without knowing for what or for whom. Propa¬
ganda, organization of enthusiasm behind the lines as well as at the front,
involved, of necessity, an element of ideology, a political and moral justifica¬
tion of the cause to which so many lives and so much wealth was sacrificed.
The logic of the justification cut across military necessities. If the Allied cause
was just, that of the Central Powers was not. If the conviction that their
cause was just sustained the courage of the combatants and constituted an
element of strength, it was useful to spread doubt, on the other side of the line
of fire, as to the nature of the cause which both soldiers and civilians were
defending, or believed they were defending. Thus, inexorably, each side
passed from organizing enthusiasm at home to organizing defeatism among
the enemy.
Technological means (radio, television) and the establishment of revolu¬
tionary parties are enough to make this war of propaganda, newspapers, tracts
and sound waves permanent. Allied spokesmen had tried to separate the Ger¬
man people from its regime (and to a certain extent had succeeded): “You
are not fighting for yourselves,” they insisted by every available means. “You
are fighting for your masters, the despots who have deceived you and are
leading you to the abyss. We do not make war against the German people but
against imperial despotism.” Whatever judgment is made about the Versailles
EIlThe question often asked, do the United States and the Soviet Union ultimately
seek security (or power), or on the contrary the diffusion of their ideas, is senseless.
Whether statesmen believe they seek one or the other, they cannot fail to seek one
and the other, since one involves the other.
DIALECTICS OF PEACE AND WAR
165
Treaty, it must have appeared, in the eyes of the conquered, as a sinister
mockery of the hopes which the propaganda of the democracies had awakened
during the war. It was no different from 1939 to 1945; each side attempted
to persuade the enemy masses that they were fighting for and because of a
minority of exploiters, capitalists, plutocrats, Nazis, Jews or Communists, not
for the fatherland and for a regime that was ultimately just. In the end, all
these kinds of propaganda neutralized each other or were neutralized by the
faults of statesmen and strategists. Every people followed its leaders to the
end: the German armies of occupation revived the various traditional patrio¬
tisms; in Russia, the brutality of the occupants forged the unity of the Soviet
regime and the population; the Anglo-American insistence on unconditional
surrender deprived the adversaries of National Socialism of what would have
been their best argument, the chance of escaping absolute defeat.
With Europe divided into a Sovietized zone and a zone of pluralist de¬
mocracy, with the custom, inherited from the war, of foreign-language broad¬
casts, the organizing of defeatism abroad, if not of enthusiasm at home, has
become a permanent and normal aspect of international relations. Invectives
against foreign regimes do not achieve the same violence as during the hos¬
tilities. Western broadcasts to the countries of Eastern Europe tend to assume
an informative character rather than an openly combative one. But informa¬
tion seeks to be a weapon as soon as it addresses the governed over the heads
of the leaders and breaks the monopoly which the state claims to exercise.
The minimum result aimed at by the psychological weapon in cold war is to
prevent the totalitarian regimes from being alone with their peoples: the
third man—the stranger, the enemy, the foreigner, the democracies, world
opinion—is always present. He does not suppress, hut he limits the modem
form of the royal prerogative, the right of official lies, of excluding speech
and interpretation from the outside.
It is difficult to measure exactly the effectiveness of the strategy of per¬
suasion, but experience suggests that it disturbs neither the Soviet regimes
nor the pluralist regimes or, to use the concepts I prefer, the regimes of
monopolistic parties and the pluralist-constitutional regimes, provided the
former are based on a national party which has effectively accomplished the
Revolution, and that the latter reveal a determination and give the people
the feeling that they are governed. It is not the Western strategy of persua¬
sion which provoked the Polish and Hungarian revolts of 1956, any more
than the Soviet strategy of persuasion was responsible for the collapse of the
Fourth Republic.
Things happen quite differently the day persuasion is transformed into
subversion—in other words, when action to overturn an established power
and substitute for it another is added to the language defining what is ex¬
tolled and what is not (the regime of the future or the regime of the other).
We use the expression technique of subversion rather than subversive war
because this latter notion seems equivocal. It tends to identify a juridically
THEORY
166
defined species of conflict and a means of combat. There is an obvious link
between the conflicts in which, at the outset, a single one of the belligerents
is internationally recognized and the methods of subversion: that is to say,
the revolutionary party which has no or only a few organized troops is obliged
to resort to the methods of subversion. But these two notions are nonetheless
conceptually separable and sometimes actually separated.
Legally, the wars which French authors have acquired the habit of calling
subversive or revolutionary belong to the genre of conflicts which we have
called infra-state or infra-imperial. They can be classified with the civil wars
since, initially, only one side is recognized by the international community.
But civil wars are not all subversive; the War of Secession in America, al¬
though juridically a civil war, was fought by two powers organized from the
outset. An undertaking against an established power, like that of General
Franco, does not always resort to means which, in the eyes of French theore¬
ticians, are the very essence of subversive war, that is, the conversion and
recruiting of the people. Subversion is the weapon used by a national or
revolutionary party to strike down the recognized authority in possession of
the military and administrative machinery.
If revolutionary parties all belong to the same juridical category, if they
almost all resort to the weapon of subversion, it is still proper to outline sev¬
eral cases, depending on the relations between the established power and
the revolutionary party. In China the stake was the regime of an existing,
undisputed state. Chiang Kai-shek and Mao Tse-tung both sought to gain
leadership over eternal China. Which men, in the name of which ideas,
would take over the Middle Empire and adapt it to the requirements of the
industrial age, these were the questions which the civil war was to decide.
In Indonesia, in Indo-China, in Tunisia, in Morocco, in Algeria, the stake
was the independence of a population subject to foreign domination or of a
state which had transferred its sovereignty to the advantage of a protecting
state. The Algerian War was bom from a revolt. The FLN nationalists were
rebels and the French government stated that it was dealing with an internal
affair. But historically, sociologically, since 1945, all wars called subversive
by French authors, from Indonesia and Indo-China to Algeria, have belonged
to a category which is not defined by the concept of civil wars: these wars of
imperial disintegration, which are defined as subversive in the eyes of the
theoreticians of the ex-imperial state, are called wars of liberation in the
language of the nationalists. We shall understand nothing of the nature of
these conflicts if we insist on the analysis of only the technique of subversion
and forget two essential facts: the sympathy of a great part of public opinion
for the anti-colonialist cause, and the community of race, language and re¬
ligion between the revolutionaries and the masses, and not between the
masses and the established power.
Abstractly, the goal of subversion is to withdraw a population from the
administrative and moral authority of an established power and to integrate
DIALECTICS OF PEACE AND WAR
167
it -within other -political and military frameworks, sometimes in and hy con¬
flict. From all evidence, success or failure chiefly depends on the spontaneous
relations between the active minority leading the combat and the mass of the
population.
To Western eyes, what matters most is the relation between the active
minority and communism (local party or Soviet bloc). When this minority
is composed of Communists or directed by them, as was the case in Indo-
China, national liberation brings with it a regime which adheres to the Soviet
bloc. When the minority includes a Communist faction, Western strategy
hesitates between the fear of a Communist advance and the desire to favor
“national liberation” (the moderate nationalists will resist the Communists).
When the minority is anti-Communist, Western strategists (except for
those who belong to the ex-imperial power) tend to favor the nationalist
cause, either by ideological sympathy or by calculation. Still the spokesmen
for the ex-imperial power may contend that the national revolution will turn
to the advantage of the Communists, despite the intentions or convictions of
the nationalists.
Whatever the merits or defects of the two possible Western strategies in
colonial territories, one yielding to and the other resisting the nationalist
claims, events in the territory are chiefly controlled by the relation between
the revolutionaries and the masses, not by the relation between the revolu¬
tionaries and the blocs in conflict on the world scene. The outcome of these
wars assumes its historical significance within the framework of global diplo¬
macy; the causes of the victories and defeats are chiefly local.
4. Dialectics of Antagonism
Deterrence, persuasion, subversion—these three concepts designate modes
of action, i.e., behavior oriented to the conduct of other men, neutrals or
objects. Analyses of these three means of action, even on the most abstract
level, are incomplete insofar as they neglect the dialectical essence of politics,
namely the law of antagonism. Each of these procedures is employed by at
least two actors: it is the dialogue of the actors which establishes the mean¬
ing of the action.
The strategy of deterrence seemed unilateral as long as the Soviet Union
did not have the means of inflicting upon the United States the blows which
the latter would be capable of striking against her. This asymmetry was
more apparent than real, as long as Europe was without protection. Even the
appearance of asymmetry has vanished, thereby producing a doubt as to the
value of deterrence once the latter becomes reciprocal. To what degree is the
threat of killing plausible if the other’s death is to be followed by our own?
Is threat of mutual suicide of any use in diplomacy?
In Part III we shall study in detail the problems of diplomacy in the Atomic
Age. Let us confine ourselves here to enumerating the three possibilities
which, in the abstract, the reciprocal capacity for destruction affords. If war
i68
THEORY
signified mutual suicide, either the great powers would not fight any longer,
or they would fight without resorting to weapons too destructive to be used
rationally, or else they would fight by means of satellites, interposed allies or
neutrals. Peace, non-atomic war, with or without participation of the mem¬
bers of the atomic club, these are the three hypotheses. A limited, non-atomic
war between the great powers of the system has not yet occurred, as if the
leaders mistrusted each other, fearing that once again the intoxication of bat¬
tle and the desire for victory at any cost might drown out the voice of reason
and the simple instinct of self-preservation.
The reciprocity of deterrence tends, it seems to me, to neutralize a strategy
which must be unilateral in order to be completely convincing. The more
inhuman the threat, the rarer the circumstances in which it will be taken
seriously. When unilateral, the strategy of deterrence holds a death-threat
over the enemy. When bilateral, it holds an almost similar threat over all the
actors. Reciprocity diminishes the frequency of use and increases the improb¬
abilities of executing the thermonuclear threat.
Asymmetry, in the case of persuasion, derives from the difference between
the regimes in conflict. A constitutional-pluralist regime tolerates, in fact, the
existence of parties which are in sympathy with another nation and another
regime. If it has the right, as a result of its principles, not to tolerate con¬
spiracy, the initial stage of rebellion, it has difficulty distinguishing in practice
between persuasion and subversion, propaganda and conspiracy. Also the
Western democracies do not forbid the “foreign nationalists” to speak and
organize, whereas, in the regimes to which the latter give their adherence, no
one is entitled to plead the cause of the West.
Yet it would be a mistake to exaggerate the consequences of this “inequal¬
ity of opportunity.” The West is present in the Soviet Union, despite the
radio "jamming.” When the Soviet leaders repeat the formula which Stalin
launched at the outset of the last Five-Year Plan—overtake the United States
—they thereby recognize the American lead in production, productivity and
standard of living. Economists, philosophers, propagandists read the Western
authors and the dialogue with them continues. Sometimes the excesses of
official propaganda ultimately provoke curious reactions. Some men, on the
other side of the Iron Curtain, arrive at an excessive idea of the West’s stan¬
dard of living from not believing the caricatured image of capitalism spread
by the official spokesmen. A regime based on the state monopoly of political
interpretation is perhaps, in the long run, more vulnerable than a (normally
functioning) regime which admits dialogue, both interior and exteriorP®
Reciprocity is still more important in the case of subversion, because re¬
prisal resembles challenge, repression resembles subversion, from which re¬
sults a striking symmetry of action and reaction, of revolutionaries and con¬
servatives. The former wish to dissolve the existing community, uprooting
EDSee helow, Chap. XVII, Sec. 3.
dialectics of peace and war
169
individuals and integrating them into another community. The clandestine
organization is the nucleus of this community: when it has managed to gain
control of administration and justice, the substitution of the rebel community
for the previous community is accomplished. What can be the objective of
repression, if not to destroy the clandestine organization, nucleus of the future
community, and to restore, both materially and morally, the people to the
pre-existing community? This objective is not unreasonable, declare the the¬
oreticians of repression, whatever the sentiments of the people, since only a
minority is capable of the energy, courage, and sacrifices which clandestine
action requires and since, without the hard core of activists, the masses in¬
cline to passivity.
The strategy of persuasion—that is, the methods as a whole which are
intended to modify or consolidate the sentiments, opinions or convictions of
men—is an element of the strategy of subversion and of repression. The FLN
nationalists wanted to make the Algerian Moslem believe that he never was
or would be French, that he could have no other country but Algeria. The
French officers of “psychological action’’ wanted to make him believe that if
he had never been entirely French, he would be so henceforth, that the
Algerian nation proclaimed by the FLN was a deception and would be a
disaster for him. The dialogue, addressed to the Moslems, between the ad¬
herents of Algerian independence and the partisans of French Algeria, was
transformed into a dialectic of subversion and repression the day the revolu¬
tionaries used violence in order to break up the existing community and to
demonstrate thereby a schism between Moslems and French. At that moment,
terror, a decisive element of the strategy of deterrence, became one of the
major weapons of subversion.
The word terror has been employed, in our era, in at least four contexts:
by the Germans to designate the bombing of cities, by those seeking to con¬
serve an established power (German occupation officials in France or French
authorities in Algeria) to stigmatize the action of the resistants or nationalists,
by all authors to characterize one of the aspects of totalitarian regimes, and
lastly by usage to designate the relation of dual impotence between the two
great powers armed with thermonuclear bombs. These different uses of the
same word reveal certain profound characteristics of our period and the re¬
lationship of today’s three strategies.
The bombardment of cities, the “raids of terror” as the German communi¬
ques called them, had material objectives. They obliged the enemy to devote
important resources to active or passive defense, clearing the ruins, maintain¬
ing public services. Directly and indirectly, they reduced production. But
the morale of the populations was a further objective; in naming them “raids
of terror” the German government denied them a military function, assigning
as their sole objective the weakening of the collective desire to resist. Whether
true or false, this interpretation constituted a rejoinder to the intention of
Allied strategy. The latter may have had as its major objective the morale of
170
THEORY
the population, but it did not admit the fact. By doing so, it would have
reduced the effectiveness of its method: the Germans were meant to believe
that the destruction of their cities corresponded to a wartime necessity. The
German government, on the contrary, had every reason to denounce the raids
of terror, so that the enemy would appear odious and so that the civilians,
immediate target of the bombs, would have the desire and the pride to con¬
duct themselves like soldiers at the front.
An action of violence is labeled “terrorist” when its psychological effects
are out of proportion to its purely physical result. In this sense, the so-called
indiscriminate acts of revolutionaries are terrorist, as were the Anglo-Ameri¬
can zone bombings. The lack of discrimination helps spread fear, for if no
one in particular is a target, no one can be safe. As a matter of fact, the bomb¬
ings were effective in a different way when their object was to destroy means
of communication or synthetic petroleum factories. Even on the psychological
level, non-discrimination was probably an error. The destruction of the fac¬
tories would have shaken the confidence of the population, whereas the
accumulating ruins, apparently without military motive, tended to exasperate
rather than to discourage. Perhaps the urban terrorism would have the same
effect contrary to revolutionary expectation, were it inflicted on a homoge¬
neous population. Among a mixed population, like that of Algeria, the ex¬
asperation of one of the communities provokes the schism which the rebels
demand and which the conservative forces wish to prevent. Indeed, the
schism between those of French stock and the Algerian Moslems confirms
the FLN thesis and denies that of the established power.
In case of “indiscriminate” terrorism, the reaction of those of French stock
is to regard all Moslems as suspect, if not to take revenge on any of them who
happen to be caught. If terrorism is not selective, the repressive reprisal is not
likely to be selective either. As suspects, all the Moslems felt excluded from
the existing community. Between them and the French, all confidence van¬
ished. There is no community without confidence: if men do not know' what
they can expect from each other, they no longer live in society. All are afraid,
and each is alone.
The inevitable errors of repression heighten this disintegration. When too
many innocents are punished, abstention ceases to seem a protection. The
activists have no further difficulty recruiting combatants, once the risks of
legally culpable action do not seem so different from the risks of legally
innocent passivity.
Hence we understand the transition from the terror created by the dialectics
of subversion and repression to the terror erected into a system of government.
Let us recall Mr. Khrushchev’s speech and its description of the Stalinist
universe. Why was none of the members of the Politiburo able to stand
against the despot and bring to an end the crimes committed "under the
reign of the cult of personality”? Mr. Khrushchev gave as an essential reason
the fact that the people would not have understood, but he clearly suggests an-
dialectics of peace and war
171
other reason: the highest state officials dared not trust each other. Never has
Montesquieu’s theory of fear, the principle of despotism, received more strik¬
ing confirmation or illustration. When one man commands, without law and
without rules, fear reduces all men to a common impotence.
The President of the Council of Soviet Ministers also criticized Stalin for
having refused to make any distinction between the forms of guilt and for
having re-established the practice of collective punishment. The opposition
was wrong, Mr. Khrushchev said, yet they were not all traitors or Gestapo
agents. Through considering every deviationist as an enemy, honest militants
are confused with deviationists. Here, too, the outcome was the typical phe¬
nomenon of revolutionary periods, the generalization of suspicion. It is not an
accident that the key concept of every phase of terror is that of suspicion.
Countless are those, guilty or innocent, who feel a vague threat weighing
upon them. How could there not be thousands or millions of suspects, since
the established power is a new one and knows itself to be surrounded by
enemies?
Among the suspects, some groups bring themselves to the attention of the
authorities. They justify suspicion by their very being, aside from any action
they might take. The ci-devants were suspect in the eyes of the Jacobins.
Non-Russian citizens had become suspect in the period of the Stalinist mad¬
ness, and Mr. Khrushchev has described deportation of whole populations,
the Ukrainians having escaped such a fate only because of their number.
There is no longer any degree in crime since the deviationist does not differ
from the traitor, but collective inequalities exist, certain groups being more
suspect than others.
Up to a certain point, subversion and repression are both likely to enter the
diabolical cycle of strictly political terror. In every war the defeatists are
accused of preparing the defeat which they announce, and sometimes they
actually contribute to it. How can the established power help but be weak¬
ened by those citizens who question its action or its legitimacy? The French¬
man who cast doubt on Algeria frangaise objectively gave assistance to the
Algerian nationalists. With disregard to his intentions, he was called a traitor,
since in fact he was aiding the enemy. Similarly, the Moslem who refused to
obey the FLN abetted the French cause. He was a traitor to his Algerian
fatherland just as for the Ultras the liberal Frenchman was a traitor to
France.
Comparing conservatives and revolutionaries, it is the latter who often ex¬
tend political terror furthest in the so-called subversive war. Whether it is a
question of maintaining the clandestine nucleus or of winning enthusiasm,
persuasion is not enough. The discouraged must be punished by death, for
discouragement is on the watch for combatants who have only rifles with
which to face planes and tanks; impulses to negotiate and refusal to obey
must be punished severely, for the legitimacy of the political organization,
in exile or in hiding, has only uncertain foundations. “Collaborators” must be
1 72
THEORY
eliminated, since they tend to refute, by their example, the claims for which
so many men are struggling and dying. When the dialectic of subversion and
repression is prolonged, the conservative state gradually restrains liberties and
the revolutionaries multiply acts of violence in order to forge their own com¬
munity as much as to dissolve the mixed community upon which they have
declared war.
The so-called technique of re-education or brainwashing has developed out
of the combined strategy of persuasion and subversion. The effort, charac¬
teristic of subversion, to break up an existing community and integrate the
uprooted individuals into another, is no longer exerted clandestinely, but in
broad daylight, in camps where the captured soldiers are assembled. Here,
too, the results were asymmetrical: a few American soldiers were converted,
thousands of Chinese soldiers (who however, had previously served in the
Nationalist armies) refused repatriation. The technique is not foolproof. In
Indo-China the captured French soldiers and officers also suffered the ordeals
of re-education: the goal was not to induce them to become members of the
Vietnamese community, but to interpret their combat and the entire universe
in terms of the ideology of their enemies. By imputing to France the sin of im¬
perialism and to the Viet-minh the glory of the struggle for freedom, these
Frenchmen would have disavowed their fatherland and admitted that their
jailers were right. The effects of this re-education have rarely lasted more than
a few weeks, yielding, after liberation, to the influence of the national milieu.
The inspiration of these practices is as old as the attempts at conversion,
whether the inquisitors want to save souls, or the conquerors or revolution¬
aries seek to obtain, from the subjugated or from the ci-devants, the homage
of a self-styled renunciation. The confessions of the Moscow trials were no
more than a grotesque and monstrous semblance of conversion. The majority
of ci-devant Chinese intellectuals probably do not believe in the version of
their own past which they themselves edited, using the concepts of the vic¬
torious party. But belief and skepticism are not always distinguished in the
soul of militants or prisoners, re-educators or converts. In a sense, Lenin’s
companions, on the threshold of death, continued to believe that “the party
was the proletariat” and that Stalin, who was its leader, did not separate him¬
self from the proletarian cause. Ideological thought proceeds by chain identi¬
fication. It rationalizes, though it is often irrational. Nothing is easier than to
subscribe to rationalizations, reasonable in themselves, although absurd in
relation to reality.
Subversion and repression both result in the technique of re-education,
since both tend to dissolve a community and forge another one from it. The
communities, whether destroyed or broken up, in the case of a civil war, are
ideological, and, in the case of a war of liberation, national. Thus the op¬
portunities of either kind of re-education are determined in advance not by
the quality of its means but by the nature of the men. A Moroccan nation¬
alist could never, whatever the length of his stay in a camp and the subtlety
DIALECTICS OF PEACE AND WAR
173
of the psychotechnicians, be won over to the cause of French greatness. The
Algerians, genuinely won over by the nationalist cause, are also no longer
recoverable. Ideas are more malleable than souls: nationality is inscribed in
souls, not in ideas.
The cold war is located at the meeting point of two historical series, one
leading to the development of thermonuclear bombs and ballistic missiles, to
the incessant increase of ever more destructive weapons and even swifter car¬
rying vehicles, the other accentuating the psychological element of the con¬
flict at the cost of physical violence. The conjunction of these two series is
in itself intelligible: the more the instruments of force exceed the human
scale, the less usable they are. Technological excess brings war back to its
essence as a trial of wills, either because threat is substituted for action, or
because the reciprocal impotence of the great powers forbids direct conflicts
and thereby enlarges the spaces in which clandestine or scattered violence
flourishes, without too much risk to humanity.
If peace by terror, the triumph of inventive genius applied to the science
of destruction, coincides with the age of subversion, historical conjunctions
are to some degree the cause. The Second World War precipitated the de¬
cline of Europe by undermining the prestige and the force of those who, at
the beginning of the century, believed themselves the masters of the universe.
It is the Western powers themselves who have returned to the practices which
the establishment of regular armies and the international law of war had been
intended to suppress or limit: the mobilization of those who have been called
soldiers without uniform. From 1914 to 1918, obligatory military service had
universalized the duty to bear arms, except for those whose work was con¬
sidered more useful to the community than their sacrifice. From 1939 to
1945, universality of participation assumed another form, passive under bomb¬
ing, active in the resistance. Civilians were themselves mobilized to oppose
the occupying powers. Civilian resistance, whether effective or not on the
military level, bore witness to the stake of the war: to paraphrase Valery’s re¬
mark quoted above—man, without being in uniform, was defending his soul.
The victory of either side signified, or seemed to signify, a conversion of souls
by force.
Peace by terror holds a worldwide and monstrous threat over the mass of
humanity. Subversion imposes upon each individual the obligation to choose
his fate, his party, his nation. The thermonuclear threat reduces men to a
kind of collective passivity. The psychological weapon, manipulated by revo¬
lutionaries or conservatives, aims at all men because it aims at each of them.
Taylor &. Francis
Taylor &. Francis Group
http://taylorandfrands.com
PART TWO
SOCIOLOGY
Determinants and Constants
Taylor &. Francis
Taylor &. Francis Group
http://taylorandfrands.com
Introduction
The distinction between theory and sociology is, in the social disciplines,
as easy to make in the abstract as it is difficult to respect in practice. Even in
the economic sciences, whose theory has been rigorously and systematically
constructed, the frontiers are often vague. What data, what causes belong to
pure theory? Which data, which causes should be regarded as external to the
economic system as such (exogenous)? The answer to these questions varies
with the period, even within one and the same period, according to the
economists. In any case, theory must be elaborated in terms of its own con¬
cepts and of logic for the problems of sociology to become apparent.
The first part of this book has permitted us to grasp the concepts with the
help of which we can interpret the logic of the conduct of international
relations. In the first three chapters we have analyzed in turn the intercon¬
nections of diplomacy and strategy, the factors on which the power of po¬
litical units depends, and lastly the objectives that statesmen seek to achieve.
In the last three chapters we have analyzed not the conduct of international
relations considered in isolation, with their means and their ends, hut in¬
ternational systems. The analysis of these systems has involved two stages.
First the determination of the characteristics proper to any system (homo¬
geneous or heterogeneous, inter-relation of forces and juridical regulation),
then the description of the two ideal types of systems (multipolar and bipo¬
lar). The analysis of systems leads to the dialectic of peace and war—that is,
to the enumeration of types of peace and types of war, including intermediary
forms, currently named cold war, or warlike peace, or revolutionary war.
Theory, thus conceived, renders the study of international relations, as they
develop, three kinds of service: i. it indicates to the sociologist and the his¬
torian the chief elements which a description of the circumstances should
include (limits and nature of the diplomatic system; ends and means of
actors, etc.); 2. if the sociologist or historian wants to go beyond description
to understand the conduct of international relations of a political unit or of
INTRODUCTION
178
its leaders, he can utilize theory as a criterion of rationality, comparing the
action which, according to theory, would have been logical, with that which
has actually occurred; 3. the sociologist or the historian can. and should seek
out the causes, internal or external to diplomatic relations, which determine
the formation, the transformation or the disappearance of international sys¬
tems (just as the sociologist of economics seeks the economic or non-economic
causes which determine the birth or death of the regime: feudal, capitalist
or socialist).
We have intentionally, in the preceding paragraph, bracketed the sociolo¬
gist and the historian together. Now the former’s task, it seems to me, comes
between that of the theoretician and that of the historian. The historian in¬
terprets, recounts the events of international affairs; he follows the develop¬
ment of a political unit, of a diplomatic system, of a civilization considered as
a singular, unique whole. The sociologist seeks propositions of a certain
generality, relative either to the action which a certain cause produces upon
power or upon the objectives of political units, upon the nature of systems,
upon the types of peace and war, or to regular series or patterns of develop¬
ment which characterize the situation without the actors necessarily being
aware of it.
Thus theory naturally suggests the enumeration of effect-phenomena, the
determined factors, for which the sociologist is tempted to seek cause-phe¬
nomena, the determinants. These determined factors, following the order of
the chapters in the preceding part, are: 1. the factors of power (or again,
what is the actual weight, in each period, of the factors of power? How do
they combine?); 2. the choice, hy any one state or at any one period, of cer¬
tain objectives, rather than certain others; 3. the circumstances necessary or
favorable to the constitution of one system (homogeneous or heterogeneous,
multipolar or bipolar) rather than another; 4. the actual character of the vari¬
ous hinds of peace and war; 5. the frequency of war; 6. the order, if there is
one, by which war and peace succeed each other; the pattern, if there is one,
according to which the fortune—peaceful or warlike—of sovereign units, of
civilizaticms, of humanity itself fluctuates. These determined factors belong,
as we see, to two species: either they are the data by which we understand
the logic in the conduct of international affairs, or else they are total processes
created by men and perceptible only to the spectator situated at some distance
from the event.
To a certain degree, the historian’s task is the study of determined factors
in the first category, and even of their causes. He alone carries analysis down
to the singular case, understood and explained in all its details. But the so¬
ciologist is in a position to arrive at facts or relations of some generality, if he
succeeds in dividing the material according to determinants and not effect-
phenomena. The enumeration of these determinants must be systematic if
this sociological essay is to be of any use.
The political units whose peaceful-warlike relations we are analyzing are
INTRODUCTION
179
human collectivities, organized on a territorial basis. Men, living in society
within a delimited space—such are the political units, whose sovereignty is
identified with collective ownership of a fragment of the globe. A funda¬
mental distinction between the two kinds of causes is suggested by this
formulation: the material or physical causes on the one side, the moral or
social causes on the other, to use Montesquieu's vocabulary.
The causes in the first category, which we have just called physical or
material, are subdivided into three, indicated by the three following ques¬
tions: what space do these men occupy? how many men occupy this space?
what resources are to be found there? Space, population, resources or, if one
prefers, the names of the disciplines which treat these determinants, geog¬
raphy, demography, economy— such would be the titles of the first three
chapters.
We may also subdivide the study of the social determinants into three chap¬
ters. Not that the latter belong to three species as distinct as the three kinds
of physical determinants, but, in the case of the social causes, we are seeking
regular relations and above all typical series (if they exist). We are therefore
entitled to apportion our inquiry in relation to the historical unities whose
development would appear, after the fact, as subject to a general law. Now,
I see three such historical unities of paramount importance in the six thou¬
sand years of our history: the nation, the civilization, humanity.
In the first of these three chapters we study the influence which the regime
proper to each of the political units exerts upon the conduct of diplomacy or
strategy. At the same time, we inquire whether the nation is a major deter¬
minant, either by its constancy or by its necessary evolution. In the second we
inquire whether the history of each civilization offers a regular and foresee¬
able series of typical phases, each characterized by a way of conducting inter¬
national relations, by a determined frequency or style of wars. Finally, in the
third chapter, we raise the same question apropos of all humanity. Have
nations and civilizations, has humanity itself had until today—will it have
tomorrow—an inevitable destiny in peace or in war?
The same distinction can also be presented in the following manner. First,
we take the foreign policy of a particular political unit. With the idea in
mind of describing the causes, of a social nature, which determine this policy,
we first encounter the community organized according to a particular mode,
and we must assign appropriate significance to nation and regime. But nation
and regime are situated within a larger social milieu which we call a civiliza¬
tion : the Germany of the Third Reich was an integral part of Europe of the
twentieth century, itself a temporal period of Western civilization. But this
civilization in its turn had dealings with other civilizations. To what degree
do these other civilizations differ from the West with regard to the practice of
peace and of war? What share must we attribute to the nature of society and
to the nature of man? Thus, the questions formulated early in the last three
chapters follow each other logically.
l8o INTRODUCTION
It does not seem to me that any of the problems which the sociologist must
ask himself can escape this plan. The first three chapters relate to a spatial
consideration, the last three to a temporal one. Space, number, and resources
define the causes or the material means of a policy. Nations, with their re¬
gimes, civilizations, human and social nature constitute the more or less
permanent determinants. In the first three chapters the method is analytical,
aiming at isolating the action of three causes in which various sociological
schools have sought an ultimate explanation. In the last three chapters the
method is often synthetic, since it aims at defining institutions created with
the participation but without the clear knowledge of the actors.
Whether it is a question of material or social causes, of spatial or of tem¬
poral consideration, our inquiry is oriented toward the present. It is to il¬
luminate the distinctive features of our own period that, in each chapter, we
interrogate the past.
chapter VII
On Space
Every international order, down to our own day, has teen essentially
territorial. It represents an agreement among sovereignties, the compartmen-
talization of space. Thus, international law implies a permanent paradox
which in certain circumstances appears shocking: it recognizes political units
as subjects of law, as almost the sole subjects of law and, thereby, has to
ignore individualsJH
The paradox which provoked Pascal’s irony is, actually, the least of it:
“Truth on one side of the Pyrenees, error on the other.” International law,
insofar as it seeks to be in the service of stability, enjoins the cis-PyTeneans
to regard as truth what it is the duty of the trans-Pyreneans to reject as
error. The logic of these contradictory obligations is symbolized by the law
which put an end to the conflict of Catholics and Protestants in Germany:
cujus regio, hujus religio. Each man must adhere to the religion of his prince.
States recognize each other’s rights by denying those of persons.
Even today, too, the United Nations ignores in practice the protests of
individuals against the oppression of national powers. However improvised
they may be, states, from the day of the proclamation of their independence,
act as masters within their own frontierslH They possess a fragment of the
earth’s crust, with the men and objects thereon. The sea has not been divided
up and remains the property of all or of none, but air, in turn, has been made
subject—to a height not yet specified—to the authority of states.
The crossing of the line that separates the territories of political units is,
par excellence, a casus helli, proof of aggression. In wartime, space is open
to the movements of soldiers. Strategy is movement; it is influenced by means
of transport or communication. The utilization of the terrain is essential to
0The International Court of the Rights of Man, foreseen in the framework of Europe,
would theoretically end this paradox.
IUn the week that followed the proclamation of independence of the former Belgian
Congo, the government of the new state denounced as “aggression” the intervention of
Belgian troops trying to protect individuals.
182
SOCIOLOGY
tactics; the occupation of territory has been, down through the centuries,
the objective of armies in conflict. The annexation of territories, whether near
or remote, has traditionally been regarded as the legitimate ambition of
princes and the consecration of victory.
Thus, the two typical conditions of international relations, peace and war,
seem both to require a geographical consideration, an analysis in terms of
space, of treaties which put an end to the conflicts and combats which have
precipitated the collapse of the previously established order. The geographical
study of foreign policy is an integral part of what we ordinarily call human
geography or political geography: the study of the relations between the en¬
vironment and human collectivities, the adaptation of the collectivities to
the environment, the transformation of the latter by man’s hands, tools and
mind. But for reasons which we shall indicate, the geographical study of
international relations has followed a course peculiar to itself and now con¬
stitutes a semi-autonomous discipline.
It is not our intention, in the present chapter, to review the facts ac¬
cumulated by the geopoliticians or the theories which they have proposed
or established, but to specify, by critical or epistemological reflection, the
nature and limits of geopolitics.
I. On the Geographical Milieu
Space may be considered in turn as environment, theater and stake of
international relations.
The last of these three concepts is immediately intelligible. Since a state
is regarded as the owner of a certain space, any fragment of the latter can
be the stake of conflicts between individuals or groups. An Islamic state
which has won back its independence, like Tunisia or Morocco, does not will¬
ingly leave to French settlers (there by favor of the protectorate) the own¬
ership of the lands they are exploiting. The Moslems fled Palestine (in the
hope of returning) at the beginning of the war which the Israelis call a war
of liberation. One population has replaced another on a given surface. The
event illustrates, if illustration is necessary, the fact that the earth has not
ceased in the twentieth century to be a stake of disputes among collectivities.
On the other hand, the distinction between environment and theater, not
common in the literature, requires some explanation. Human geography de¬
picts the societies in a given territory, in a given climate; it attempts to
understand and explain the action which the characteristics of the setting
have exerted over the life style and social organization at the same time as the
modifications wrought in the former by the societies which have established
themselves there. The environment which geography studies and defines is
both natural and historical. It is concretely defined, involving all the features
which specialists in fauna, flora, terrain and climate are in a position to discern
and which the scholar considers instructive.
Considered as theater, space is no longer concrete but, so to speak, abstract;
ON SPACE
183
it is simplified, stylized, schematized by the observer’s attention. The battle¬
field, which the strategist must comprehend at a single glance, is no longer
the climatic or geological setting whose singularities the geographer has never
exhausted, but the framework of a specific activity. The terrain on which a
soccer game is played can and must be characterized exclusively by the
qualities (dimensions, hardness, bareness, wetness, etc.) which influence the
behavior of the players. Similarly, the globe, as a theater of international
relations, is only defined by the qualities which the actors in international
relations must take into account. It is insofar as planetary space can be con¬
ceived as the schematic frame of international politics that geopolitics offers
an original and fascinating insight into diplomatic history. Because the frame¬
work never entirely determines the playing of the game, the geopolitical
perspective, always a partial one, is easily corrupted into a justificatory
ideology.
Let us first consider space as a concrete environment. What is the nature
of the information which geographical study affords us concerning the life
of human collectivities in general, about international relations in particular?
One proposition, quite a commonplace one, comes to mind at once. The virtue
of geographical study is, first and foremost, to dissipate the illusions or
legends of a determinism of climate or relief. The deeper and more precise
the study, the fewer regular relations of causality it discovers.
Let us remember the boldness of Montesquieu’s formulas:
“These fertile provinces are always of a level surface, where the inhabi¬
tants are unable to dispute against a stronger power; they are then obliged to
submit; and when they have once submitted, the spirit of liberty cannot re¬
turn; the wealth of the country is a pledge of their fidelity. But in moun¬
tainous districts, as they have but little, they may preserve what they have.
The liberty they enjoy, or, in other words, the government they are under,
is the only blessing worthy of their defense. It reigns, therefore, more in
mountainous and rugged countries than in those that nature seems to have
favored 0
"We have already observed that great heat enervates the strength and
courage of men, and that in cold climates they have a certain vigor of body
and mind, which renders them patient and intrepid, and qualifies them for
arduous enterprises. . . . We ought not, then, to be astonished that the
cowardice of people in hot climates has almost always rendered them slaves;
and that the bravery of those in cold climates has enabled them to maintain
their liberties. This is an effect which springs from a natural causeP
“The barrenness of the Attic soil established there a democracy; and the
fertility of that of Lacedaemonia an aristocratic constitution.®
1 L’Esprit des his, XVIII, 2 ,
a Ud., xvn, 2.
01 bid., XVIII, 1 .
SOCIOLOGY
184
Today, no one believes that the courage or cowardice of peoples is a func¬
tion of the climate, that the political destiny of Sparta and Athens was
established in advance upon the soil occupied by each of the two city-
states, that notions of good or poor soil, of fertility or sterility suffice to define
a territory, that all mountains belong to one and the same category, even all
plains. At the risk of being accused of a futile pedantry, let us specify the
reasons, both of meaning and of method, which make Montesquieu’s proposi¬
tions unacceptable.
The relations suggested between climate and way of life implicitly suppose
a heredity of acquired characteristics. Biologists have made it impossible for
us to believe in such a heredity. That climate is favorable or unfavorable to
activity in general, or even to a specific activity, is not impossible for us to
admit; but the influence which the climate exerts over the mode of expression
of hereditary dispositions is never such that whole groups—peoples or races—
is forever marked by virtues or vices, whether glorious or detestable. Climate
does not make men cowardly or courageous.
The term employed by Montesquieu as causal is never defined with a
sufficient rigor for us to be able to attribute to it a constant effect. The
further our knowledge advances, the more such crude notions disintegrate.
There are too many different kinds of heat and cold, of dryness or humidity,
of plains or mountains, for a single type of social organization (or even a
single type of habitation) to accompany of necessity a general type of climate
or terrain.
Even if we avoid the error of making too vague a definition of the supposed
cause, we cannot assume a true geographical determinism. However precisely
defined the natural situation, we cannot thereby conclude that it will forbid
men to live there differently from the way they do now. If the situation is
singular, unique, how can we show that the reaction of men could not have
been other than it has been in the past? Regularity constitutes the only proof
of the necessity of the concomitance. Further, the impossibility of proof
confirms the direct observation of the margin of initiative which nature leaves
to man. Even when the constraint of nature is most burdensome, for example
in the case of the Eskimos, we are disposed to admire the intelligence with
which these archaic societies have adapted themselves to difficult circum¬
stances—that is to say, have survived. But we do not conclude that this mode
of adaptation was the only one possible.
Furthermore, non-determination by the natural environment has nothing
in common with indeterminism. A geographical determinism (or any other
theory which affirms the determination of human societies, or of some aspect
of human societies, by one cause of a given kind) assumes a philosophy of
the object, not the general principle of determinism. This latter principle does
not imply at all that, in a given climate or on a given terrain, all societies
present certain characteristics. It suffices that the way of life and the modes of
organization be a function of history at the same time as of geography, that
ON SPACE
l8 5
they be affected by many causes, not by the action of the natural environment
alone, for geography itself to contribute to the refutation of what was once
called geographical determinism.
These remarks suggest the following formula: it is always possible to
understand the relationship between a man or a collectivity and the geograph¬
ical environment. It is rarely (or never) possible to explain it if the explana¬
tion requires that the relation established be necessary. Understanding is, so
to speak, guaranteed a priori: whether or not the reaction to the environment
has been more or less intelligent, it remains understandable, since it has not
involved the death of the group. If it had involved the death of the group, it
would also have remained understandable: the interpreter would attempt to
discover the beliefs, obligations or prohibitions which prevented these human
beings from taking the measures indispensable to their safety.
Does this mean that the geographical environment, whether physical or
historical, is never the cause of social phenomena? Such a deduction would be
false. Natural phenomena have been, during the prehistoric phase, the cause
—sometimes almost a direct cause—of human events. The migrations of our
ancestors were influenced if not determined by modifications of climate.
Perhaps, as Toynbee observes)®] quoting the descriptions of Gordon Childe,
geography launched the first challenge taken up by men in creating a civiliza¬
tion:
“While northern Europe was covered in ice as far as the Harz, and the
Alps and the Pyrenees were capped with glaciers, the Arctic high pressure
deflected southward the Atlantic rainstorms. The cyclones that today traverse
Central Europe then passed over the Mediterranean Basin and the Northern
Sahara and continued, undrained by Lebanon, across Mesopotamia and
Arabia to Persia and India. The parched Sahara enjoyed a regular rainfall,
and farther east the showers were not only more bountiful than today but
were distributed over the whole year. . . . We should expect in North
Africa, Arabia, Persia and the Indus Valley parklands and savannahs, such
as flourish today north of the Mediterranean. . . . While the mammoth,
the woolly rhinoceros and the reindeer were browsing in France and
Southern England, North Africa was supporting a fauna that is found today
on the Zambesi in Rhodesia. . . .
"The pleasant grasslands of North Africa and Southern Asia were natu¬
rally as thickly populated by man as the frozen steppes of Europe, and it is
reasonable to suspect that in this favorable and indeed stimulating environ¬
ment, man would make greater progress than in the ice-bound north.tD
But after the close of the Ice Age, the Afro-Asian area began to experience
a profound physical change in the direction of aridity; and simultaneously,
two or three civilizations arose in an area which had previously, like all the
0 Cf. Toynbee, A Study of History, Vol. I.
HiV. Gordon Childe, New Light on the Most Ancient East, New York, 1934, Chap. II.
SOCIOLOGY
186
rest of the inhabited world, been occupied solely by primitive societies of the
paleolithic order. Our archeologists encourage us to look upon the drying-up
of Afro-Asia as a challenge. Our response was the genesis of these civilizations.
“Now we are on the brink of the great revolution, and soon we shall en¬
counter men who are masters of their own food supply through possession of
domesticated animals and the cultivation of cereals. It seems inevitable to
connect that revolution with the crisis produced by the melting of the north¬
ern glaciers and the consequent contraction of the Arctic high pressure over
Europe and diversion of the Atlantic rainstorms from the South Medi¬
terranean Zone to their present course across Central Europe.
“This event would certainly tax the ingenuity of the inhabitants of the
former grassland zone to the utmost.
“Faced with the gradual desiccation consequent upon the re-shift north¬
ward of the Atlantic cyclone belt as the European glaciers contracted, three
alternatives were open to the hunting populations affected. They might move
northward or southward with their prey, following the climatic belt to which
they were accustomed; they might remain at home eking out a miserable
existence on such game as could withstand the drought; or they might-
still without leaving their homeland—emancipate themselves from depen¬
dence on the whims of their environment by domesticating animals and tak¬
ing to agriculture.’!]
Have climatic phenomena, for five or six thousand years—that is, during
the so-called historical phase of civilizations—been the immediate cause of
events, greatness and decline of peoples, migrations provoked by drought and
resulting in vast conquests? This is the opinion of several authorsJH who be¬
lieve in the climatic oscillations and in the periods of drought in Central
Asia. The Spanish historian Olagiie is also convinced that the diminution of
rainfall has been one of the direct and principal causes of the Spanish deca-
dence[i£] Other authors deny the fact with the same assurance:
“The desertification of Spain, strictly linked to human intervention,” writes
M. Roger HeimJlII “probably originates in the seasonal shifting of sheep pas¬
turage, which Ferdinand and Isabella considerably intensified to increase their
personal fortune from profits derived from the European wool market, at
the same time that the direct destruction of the forest lands was increased
by the repeated cutting of large trees for the invincible Armada. Thus, for
five thousand years, no appreciable climatic change, no great natural fluctua¬
tions on the surface of the globe, and particularly in the Mediterranean
basin, but instead inadequacy of agricultural methods, deforestation, political
instability, causing the abandonment of techniques necessary to farming in a
Hhbid., Chap. III.
HOFor example, Ellworth Huntington in The Pulse of Asia, 1907.
EUlgnacis Olagiie, Histoire d'Espagne, Paris, 1957.
EH Director of tlie Museum national d’fiistoire naturelle, in Le Figaro litteraire, No¬
vember 21, 1959.
ON SPACE 187
dry country, all of which, today, are continually aggravated in their con¬
sequences by the demographic factor."
The uncertainty is related to the primary or secondary character of climatic
change. For some interpreters, climatic oscillation is a primary factor, having
nothing to do with man, and is the origin of important events. For others, it
results from human error or negligence. Exhaustion of lands and deforesta¬
tion create the geographical environment in which the civilization, incapable
of correcting its own faults, will ultimately perish.
Whichever interpretation we choose—we have no qualifications for decid¬
ing the controversy—such examples help us to distinguish and to specify
the modes of environmental causality. We speak of the historical causality^
of a natural phenomenon when the latter, without being imputable to human
action, brutally modifies the life of a collectivity: the destruction of Lisbon
by an earthquake and of Pompeii by an eruption of Mount Vesuvius belong
to this category. The same is true if drought, not imputable to men, has
gradually ruined Spain. But this latter example has quite another bearing be¬
cause it reminds us of the invisible and permanent influence of environment
on human societies.
Mankind is a species which, at least during its historical period, has in¬
cessantly transformed its conditions of existence. The environment is dif¬
ferent, even when it has not changed, if the collectivities acquire other tools
to develop it. The physical data change in relation to scientific knowledge
and technological instruments. In this sense the geographical environment,
taken concretely, prepared by nature and altered by labor, shares in historical
instability.
But, in each period, this environment, as produced by the conjunction of
nature and humanity at a certain point in its evolution, influences the destiny
of collectivities. It is alternately inducement and limit, favorable or hostile to
the efforts of societies, lenient or merciless to their weaknesses.
Let us suppose that the river civilizationspl those of the Nile, the Tigris
and Euphrates, and the Yellow River, owed their rise in part to the chal¬
lenge presented by the necessity of utilizing the spate periods, of regulating
the course of the waters, of insuring the irrigation of cultivable lands. The
civilizations of hydraulic engineering, as a result of these requirements for
collective survival, present specific characteristics, the very ones which define
“the Asiatic mode of production,” one of the regimes Marx discusses in his
introduction to the Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy. But
such civilizations are more vulnerable than those which prosper under tem¬
perate climates and which allow individuals and small groups to survive on
their own. The history of France would be less continuous if the political
EUln both the formal sense, as a unique sequence, and the material sense, as an event
relating to the development of human societies.
EUcf. Karl A. Wittfogel’s very important book, Oriental Despotism, New Haven, 1957.
i88
SOCIOLOGY
upheavals, not infrequent during the last thousand years, had involved, along
with the disorganization of the administration, the wrecking of the appara¬
tus indispensable for agricultural production. When the civilization survives
only by annually renewing its victory over a rebellious nature, men accept a
stricter discipline and even then the total surrender to a state is sometimes
not enough to preserve them from a catastrophe.
The environment, as historically constituted by the conjunction of physical
resources and technical means, is far more effective at inducing a determined
organization to act than at punishing errors or negligence, and fixes the limit
that the number of collectivities cannot exceed. Even today, despite the
growing independence which our species is in the process of acquiring in
relation to the physical environment, the distribution of the human masses
appears not strictly determined, but only influenced, by climatic conditions.
The various regions of the globe have not been equally propitious to the
development of civilizations. Whatever the state of techniques of production,
the number of men capable of living on a given surface remains dependent
on physical data, soil, relief, climate. Neither isolable nor specifically deter¬
minant, the action of the geographical environment is exerted continually,
without our being able to measure its limits. Is it possible to construct, deep
in the heart of Africa, societies of the industrial type? Perhaps we are all
inclined to underestimate the weight with which nature still weighs, even
in our age, upon human societies.
The preceding analysis, valid for political geography as a whole, applies
a fortiori to environmental explanations of international relations. The 'posi¬
tion (die Lage) is, in effect, essentially historical, since it depends on cir¬
cumstances which obey the law of change (techniques of movement, trans¬
portation, combat, effective circulation of men and merchandise, relation of
forces between political units in the same zone, etc.). Once the Islamic
conquests closed the Mediterranean to commercial traffic, Marseilles no longer
had the same status. The situation of a nation on the physical map is, itself,
immutable. But it is at most one cause among others; it suggests certain
actions, it offers a framework of possibilities. Perhaps it is subtly present in
all centuries, in all aspects of the national destiny. But it is expressed in a
position which changes with the rise and ruin of states, in institutions which
mark, in each period, the ideas, the dreams, the tools and the weapons of
men.
We are sometimes tempted—and even an A. Cournot has not resisted this
temptation—to read the destiny of the European nations on the map after
the fact. History, in the long run, has effaced the traces of accidents and
favored the fulfillment of the law promulgated by geography. Spain, France
and Great Britain have definitively assumed the dimensions that corresponded
to the natural order. As a matter of fact, Spain has not always been separated
from the current of European civilization by the Pyrenees; for a time her
armies played the leading role in Europe. Dynastic unions united lands that
ON SPACE
189
geography had separated, hut geography has not given the provinces of Spain
the homogeneity presented hy the provinces of France. Was French unity
“predetermined” as some today imagine? Such a proposition should be at the
least modified by reservations. The frontiers of the pre carre were and re¬
main contested. The spread of a single language, the creation of a national
community among Flemings, Bretons, Provencals and Beamais might perhaps
have been facilitated by geography: how easy it would be to find the “under¬
lying causes,” had this unification not been achieved!
It would be paradoxical to deny that the configuration of Switzerland or
France, or the island situation of Great Britain, have constantly influenced
the diplomacy of these nations down through the centuries. Switzerland owes
to its geographical situation a defensive power incommensurate with the
number of its inhabitants or the resources of its economy. But it required
historical circumstances to create first the confederation, then the Helvetian
federation, and then that the latter should adopt the policy of neutrality
indispensable to the maintenance of its unity as long as the great neighboring
nations were fighting. Still the history of the Swiss cantons—their capacity
to stand up to aggressors, to maintain their independence, to constitute a
neutral state and to make that neutrality respected—probably owes more to
geography than that of any other nation of the Old World.
Similarly, it is easy to speculate on the parallelism between the double
vocation—continental and maritime—of France and the hesitation of her
diplomacy. With a northern frontier open to invasions and quite close to the
capital, France was inevitably obsessed by the concern for an always pre¬
carious security. Situated at the western extremity of the small cape of Asia,
she could not ignore the call of the sea and the lure of remote expeditions.
She divided her forces between a diplomacy of continental hegemony (or
of security) and a diplomacy of an overseas empire. She did not succeed com¬
pletely in either direction.
It is apropos of England that analysis usefully indicates the limits of a
geographical interpretation, in itself convincing and apparently irresistible.
It is obvious that England’s fortune is inconceivable without her island situa¬
tion. The security from aggression which neither Venice nor Holland had
enjoyed to the same degree, the importance of her resources of food, the wheat
fields of the south, and subsequently her coal reserves gave English diplomacy
a freedom of action unknown to the continental states. To a degree, England
owed her defensive power to nature. She could keep apart from the
European conflicts, take sides with the momentarily weaker party, decide the
issue by the intervention, at the opportune moment, of an expeditionary force,
and reserve the bulk of her forces for the demands of naval supremacy and
imperial expansion.
This textbook stereotype is not untrue, though it simplifies and schematizes.
England has taken advantage of its insular position in order to conduct a
policy which would have been forbidden to a state otherwise situated. This
190
SOCIOLOGY
policy was not, all the same, determined by the situation. The latter left men
a marginal autonomy: it offered them a choice among several decisions. The
choice was not accidental and it is not unintelligible, but it was not imposed
by the natural environment.
Abstractly, a collectivity ruling the whole of an island may be tempted
either by withdrawal (breaking off relations with the world) or by an active
diplomacy. The latter, in its turn, may be oriented in three directions: con¬
tinental conquest, overseas expeditions, voluntary neutrality. Each of these
four policies has been adopted, at various times, by one or another of the
two island states, Great Britain and Japan.
When Japan achieved her unity in the seventeenth century, she did not
take advantage of it by undertaking conquest elsewhere. On the contrary,
during the Tokugawa era, the shoguns’ only ambition was to perfect, so to
speak, their island isolation. The ideal of a stable society and a refined civiliza¬
tion encouraged them to withdraw their flourishing empire from barbarian
contact, from exchanges with the West.
After the Meiji reform, Japan reversed her attitude, but did not cease to
vacillate between the two paths accessible to the expansion of an island
state: continental or maritime conquest. Lacking the resolution or the capac¬
ity to choose, Japan ultimately found herself in a war with China, which
the Japanese armies vainly attempted to occupy, and with the United States
and Great Britain, maritime powers, protecting the islands (Philippines, In¬
donesia). England, historically speaking, conducted her enterprises more ra¬
tionally. The phase of continental ventures ended with the Hundred Years’
War. Once the union of the two kingdoms of England and Scotland was
achieved, Great Britain acted, in most cases, as if she understood the logic of
European equilibrium, and turned her ambition toward the seas, the fleet,
commerce and the Empire.
Since 1945 Japan and Great Britain, drawn closer to the continents by
technical progress and outclassed by land powers, have both been integrated
into the United States system of alliance. Both island states count on Amer¬
ican protection, on the support of the dominant naval power in order to insure
their security. Great Britain makes this choice virtually without hesitation,
by reason of the close relationship of English and American civilizations.
Japanese public opinion, on the other hand, is far from being unanimous,
so artificial does the rupture of exchanges with China appear. Reduced to
secondary rank, could Japan not be neutral without being isolated as in the
times of the shoguns, without becoming a satellite of the continental states?
Even in England the question has been raised, at least in the indirect form
of opposition to the American bases and thermonuclear armament.
The island situation leads to a schematic analysis of diplomatic possibili¬
ties; it does not, of itself, establish causal relations. An island state is not
constrained to be a naval power. It was in the sixteenth century that the
English truly became a nation of sailors. The Japanese have never become
ON SPACE
I 9 I
such a nation. They have remained to the end a land people, reluctant to
emigrate, reluctant to entrust their fortunes to the uncertainty of the waves.
The island situation is a challenge, not a constraint.
2. The Mackinder Patterns
In the preceding pages we have gradually shifted from the first term to
the second, from environment to theater. Space, we have said, is regarded
as a theater, and no longer as an environment, when the observer takes into
account only certain characteristics, namely those that are supposed to influ¬
ence a specific behavior. For instance, the geopolitician sees the geographical
environment as “the terrain of diplomatic and military interplay.” The en¬
vironment is simplified into an abstract framework, the populations trans¬
formed into actors, making entrances and exits on the world stage.
How much concrete reality does the geopolitician retain in the designs
of the stage and of diplomatic-strategic actors? The conduct of foreign affairs
appears instrumental to the geopolitician, the use of certain means toward
certain ends. Resources—men, tools, weapons—are mobilized by states with
a view to security or expansion. Yet lines of expansion, like threats to se¬
curity, are indicated in advance on the world map if, at least, the geographer
can fix his attention on the natural data on which the prosperity and power
of nations depend. Geopolitics combines a geographical schematization of
diplomatic-strategic relations with a geographic-economic analysis of resources,
■with an interpretation of diplomatic attitudes as a result of the way of life
and of the environment ( sedentary, nomadic, agricultural, seafaring'). These
too-general formulas will be clarified and illuminated by an example. In our
century the Englishman Mackinder has probably contributed more than any¬
one else to the popularity of geopolitics. Fie originated several of the ideas
which the German school adopted in the service of imperialism. The brief,
compact books of Sir Halford Mackinder facilitate epistemological analysis,
which is our true object.
In 1904 appeared the essay called “The Geographical Pivot of FIistory .’0
Here Mackinder first explained the central theme of his thought. In 1905
another article, “Manpower as a Measure of National and Imperial Strength”
(in the National Review), accentuated the decisive influence of productivity
(or output of human labor). The principal book which gathers together the
essentials of Mackinder’s thought appeared in 1919: Democratic Ideals and
Reality. A quarter of a century later, in 1943, Foreign Affairs published an
article which assumed the character of a testament, "The Round World and
the Winning of Peace.” The same geographical designs were employed to
[lilPublished in the Geographical Journal in 1907; the communication to the Royal
Geographical Society of London, which served as the basis of the article, dates from
1904-
192
SOCIOLOGY
deal with the problems which would come up at the end of the Second
World War, after having been vainly utilized at the end of the First.
Probably the best method of summarizing our author is to start with what
I have called the schematisme geographique, in other words, to summarize
the two concepts of World Island and Heartland. Ocean covers nine twelfths
of the globe. A continent, or the total of the three continents Asia, Europe
and Africa, covers two twelfths. The rest, the last twelfth, is represented
by smaller islands, North and South America and Australia. In this planetary
diagram the Americas occupy, in relation to the World Island, a position
comparable to that of the British Isles in relation to Europe.
The second concept, that of the Heartland or of the pivot-region, has not
always been defined in the same termsP! The uncertainty as to the exact
delimitation of this enormous zone does not extend to the concept itself.
The Heartland covers both the northern part and the interior of the Eurasian
land mass. It extends from the Arctic Coast to the deserts of Central Asia.
It has as its western frontier the isthmus between the Baltic and the Black
seas, perhaps between the Baltic and the Adriatic.
The Heartland is characterized by three characteristics of physical geog¬
raphy which have a political bearing and which are combined without coin¬
ciding. It constitutes the largest flat area on the surface of the globe: the
plain of Asia, the steppes of European Russia which extend across Germany
and the Low Countries through the Ile-de-France and Paris, heart of the
West. Several of the world’s greatest rivers flow through it either to the
Arctic Sea or to inland seas (the Caspian, the Aral). Lastly, it is a grassland
favorable to the mobility of populations and warriors, whether on camels or
horses. The Heartland, at least in its eastern section, has been closed to the
intervention of naval power. It opened a way to the incursions of horsemen
riding westward.
On the basis of this reading of the simplified map, Mackinder’s three
famous propositions can be understood. Anyone controlling Eastern Europe
controls the Heartland. Anyone controlling the Heartland controls the World
Island. Anyone controlling the World Island controls the world. These are
the three propositions, in a vulgarized form, which have enjoyed most suc¬
cess. Through the German geopoliticians, Hitler learned and was perhaps
inspired by them. A theory which claimed to be scientific was transformed
into an ideology justifying conquests.
The theory itself is constructed, on the basis of geographical design, by
the simultaneous consideration of a constant element (the land-sea, conti¬
nental-seafaring opposition) and of three variable elements (the technique
of movement on land and on sea, the population and resources utilizable in
the rivalry of nations, and the extension of the diplomatic field). Writing at
the beginning of this century, when England’s fortunes seemed extraordinary
H 3 I use here the terms of the article published in Foreign Affairs.
ON SPACE
193
and invulnerable, Mackinder looked back and ahead, toward past centuries
in order to discover the necessary conditions for the victory of the island
state, toward the future to discover whether the circumstances to which
England owed most of her greatness were destined to disappear.
There is every reason to regard as fundamental, throughout history, the
opposition of land and sea, of continental power and seafaring power. The
two elements seem to symbolize two ways of life for men, incite in them two
typical attitudes. The land belongs to someone, to the landlord, individual
or collective; the sea belongs to all because it belongs to no one. The empire
of continental powers is inspired by the spirit of possession; the empire of
maritime powers is inspired by the spirit of commerce. It is not always
benevolent (let us recall the domination of Athens, as Thucydides describes
it); it is rarely closed.
If land and water represent the two elements in conflict on the global
stage, it is because international relations are, in Clausewitz’s formula, ex¬
change and communication. Wars create relations between individuals and
collectivities, but in a manner different from those of commerce. Nomads, of
both land and water, horsemen and sailors, are the builders of the two types of
empire, the professionals of the two kinds of combat. Movement and maneu¬
ver have not played the same role on land and at sea. The desire to reduce
the hazards of battle to the minimum, the strategist’s effort to muster his
forces on a battlefield and to offer the enemy a continuous front have no
equivalent on the ocean. Before the technical discoveries which multiplied
the means of communication, to venture upon a maritime career was to
accept the uncertainty of fate, to rely on improvisation, on the mastery of the
unforeseeable, through the individual’s initiative. On the eve of the battle of
Salamis the Athenians took the whole city into their vessels; in 1940 the
French denied that France could be elsewhere than on the soil of la fatrie:
a double decision symbolic of the state which chose water and the state
which will never separate itself from land.
Mackinder is aware of this dualism, but it is the destiny of his country
which fosters and orients his inquiry. From one point of view of diplomacy
and strategy the insular position exists only after political unification of the
island. On the international level a power becomes insular the day when it
no longer has any land neighbor. The British Isles are unified, the Continent
is divided: such has been the contrast which was chiefly the cause of the
United Kingdom’s imperial greatness. Yet this contrast is perhaps not an
eternal one: not that the unity of the United Kingdom is threatened, but the
unity of the Continent is no longer inconceivable.
From his study of the past Mackinder drew two ideas, still valid in
twentieth-century circumstances. The first, the most obvious but perhaps
the most misunderstood, is that the pitiless law of numbers also functions in
the struggle between maritime power and continental power. A maritime
power will not survive, despite the qualities of its fleet and its sailors, if it
194
SOCIOLOGY
is confronted by a rival possessing material and human resources which are
superior to its own. The second lesson, still clearer, is that a maritime power
can be conquered on land as well as at sea. When the continental power has
seized all the bases, there is no longer any room for the maritime power. The
sea becomes a closed sea, subject to a land empire, which no longer needs
to maintain a navy: e.g., the Mediterranean under the Roman Empire. The
British Empire risks destmction, Mackinder concludes, if a continental state
accumulates overwhelming resources or if the network of British bases es¬
tablished on islands and peninsulas around the Eurasian land mass is de¬
stroyed or occupied from the land.
For centuries Great Britain has profited by circumstances: Europe was
divided, the security of the British Isles guaranteed; the latter possessed re¬
sources, in raw materials and in men, on the scale of the resources of the
rival states; the other continents were without military force. The English
geographer perceives at the beginning of the century that the two variables
are shifting in a direction unfavorable to the maritime power.
Between the sixteenth and the nineteenth centuries, maritime mobility
was superior to land mobility. Yet Mackinder is struck by two almost con¬
temporary events, the Boer War and the Manchurian War. Russia’s capacity
to conduct a large-scale war ten thousand kilometers from her bases, at the
end of a single railroad, seems to him more striking than England’s capacity to
supply the South African Expeditionary Corps by sea. The internal-combus¬
tion engine was soon added to the contribution of the railroad. Spengler's
formula, that the steam horse will reopen the era of great invasions, closed
since the days of the Asian cavalcades, might have been utilized by Mackinder
who, in two chapter^!! on the seafaring prospect and the land prospect,
reviews the empires of past centuries: empires of horsemen, Scythians,
Parthians, Huns, Arabs, Mongols, Turks, Cossacks, coming from plateaus,
steppes or deserts, and empires of seafaring peoples, from Crete and Athens
down to Venice and England.
Now, at the very moment when land mobility prodigiously increases, the
Heartland is gaining possession of the material and human resources nec¬
essary to world empire. Eastern Europe is the hinge zone where this Heart¬
land touches its marginal regions, open on the ocean, where Slavs and Ger¬
mans meet and mingle. In 1905 and in 1919, Mackinder feared that the
Germans, conquering the Slavs, would be in a position to unify the Heart¬
land into a single sovereign territory and thereby outclass the forces of the
United Kingdom. He foresaw the economy of great space which would
serve as a base to the land power, certain to prevail, by sheer weight of
numbers, over the maritime power. It is in relation to this historical cir-
EUln Democratic Ideals and Reality.
ON SPACE
195
cumstance that the three positions reviewed above are explained and assume
their partial truth: anyone controlling Eastern Europe controls the Heart¬
land, hence the World Island, hence the universe.
From this analysis the author had drawn consequences, particularly in
1919, which he offered to the attention of those who were writing the peace
treaty. As an adviser to kings, Mackinder reread in i960 seems to have
suffered the worst disgrace: he was heeded by statesmen and mocked by
events. Since in 1919 the freedom of peoples and the greatness of England
were threatened by an eventual unification of the Heartland, it is essential to
prevent this unification—that is, the German domination of the Slavs (in
1945, the Slavic domination of the Germans). To this end, the geographer,
combining the British tradition with his impersonal (and professional) equa¬
tion, proposed constituting a belt of independent states between the two great
powers, one of which could not subject the other without breaking up global
equilibrium. So it was: the small independent states first gave the two great
powers the occasion to unite in order to divide the zone of separation, and
subsequently become the battlefield on which the Russian and German armies
met, and finally fell to the land power which, for the first time, occupied
the Heartland with a large garrison and an advanced technolog)'.
Is the history of the last forty years of a nature to disqualify the geog¬
rapher? One historian, belonging to a traditional school, Jacques Bainville,
had more accurately anticipated the consequences of the Versailles Treaty.
The independent states between (Soviet) Russia and (so-called eternal) Ger¬
many seemed to him, from their origin, incapable of lasting because they
were incapable of uniting. Poland, Rumania, Hungary, Czechoslovakia, all so-
called national states with, in fact, powerful minorities of dubious loyalty,
would never offer a common front to German revisionism and to Slavic
revisionism, which were in the last analysis opposed, but if need be prepared,
to go part of the way together.
The geographer’s answer, it seems to me, might be a double one. No
territorial treaty, he might say, is maintained if the conquering states, who
have imposed it upon the states now conquered, dissociate themselves from
it or weaken it by their disagreement. The Versailles Treaty, it is true, was
precarious, the two great continental powers being hostile to it. But the
Western nations had been given the means to act if Germany attempted to
destroy the established order: Germany was disarmed, the left bank of the
Rhine, first occupied by French troops, was subsequently to remain without
defense. The authors of the treaty were less responsible for the catastrophes
than the statesmen who had to apply it. Germany had been beaten by a
coalition which included the maritime states. Great Britain and the United
States. American isolationism and English hesitation left to France alone a
task which exceeded her forces: if the Versailles Treaty collapsed, it was not
because it was intrinsically worse than any other with regard to morality or
SOCIOLOGY
196
politics; it was because the states which should have been its guardians
deserted their task.
The other answer might be formulated as a question: What should have
been done? Destroy the German unity, as one school of French nationalism
proposed? None believed in the restoration of les Allemagnes. Save the dual
monarchy? It no longer resisted when the peace conference convened: the
diplomats took cognizance of its utter disintegration. Perhaps a peace,
whether separate or general, concluded two years earlier might have given a
new lease of life to the anachronistic unity of Central Europe under the
Habsburg dynasty. By 1918 it was too late.
In truth, the geopolitical outlook, Mackinder’s like the rest, allowed the
problem to be expressed, but dictated no solution. To prevent Germany or
Russia from achieving the unity of the Heartland from Eastern Europe,
such was the first requirement of global equilibrium, the condition of the
freedom of peoples. How forestall this unity which German imperialism
risked creating either by its victory or defeat? The belt of small states,
separating the two great powers, was a method that was not absurd, though
it has failed. The failure, even in retrospect, does not definitively condemn
the idea, because the British and Americans had, since 1920, forgotten the
most obvious lesson of the hostilities: no European order could survive with¬
out the active participation of the British and Americans united with the
continental democracies.
This is the lesson, in any case, that Mackinder, writing in 1943, drew
from the catastrophe. The war was not yet over: the British geographei
could not clearly point to today’s ally as tomorrow’s enemy. But he obviously
saw the danger of the unification of the Heartland by Slavs ultimately
victorious over the Germans. The Heartland garrison is henceforth numerous.
Russia has twenty times the area, four times the population of France. But
her open frontier is only four times that of France. This time it w'ould nc
longer be Mongols or the horsemen of central Asia, but tanks and cannons
that would stream westward. The motorized conquerors no longer lack any
of the instruments of Western technology. Whether the danger comes from
the Germans or the Russians, it comes from the Heartland; it can no longei
be warded off by alliances among the peoples who inhabit the marginal
zones of the Eurasian land mass and the peoples of the islands, British 01
Americans. The geographer sees forming before his eyes, on the map, the
Atlantic Alliance with a bridgehead in France, an air base outside Europe
(the British Isles, comparable to Malta in the Mediterranean), an arsena
and reserves across the Atlantic.
But perhaps the prospect is different from this point on. The objective ol
the maritime powers is no longer to keep Germans or Slavs from controlling
the Heartland by a single domination: the Russian army, established in Ber
lin, is determined to remain there. The Continental empire covering the
Heartland is achieved. Does Mackinder’s third proposition, anyone controlling
ON SPACE
197
the Heartland controls the universe, authorize us to foresee the outcome of
the present conflict? We cannot answer such a question without specifying
the mode of geopolitical judgments.
3. From Geographical Design to Ideologies
Mackinder himself does not hesitate to speak of geographical causation in
universal history. But in fact, there is no trace of geographical causality,
in the strict sense of the word, in his general outlook on universal history.
Of course, he starts from geographical facts, that is, the unequal dis¬
tribution of land and water on the surface of the planet, the allotment of
mineral wealth and agricultural resources across the various regions of the
globe, the unequal density of population on the various continents, depend¬
ing on the climate, the relief, and the fertility of the soil. In temperate
climates population is concentrated and civilization extended. Only thirty
million-^men lj ve on the twelve million square kilometers of plateau which
constitute the southern limit of the plains of the World Island. A billion
human beings live in the monsoon countries; only some tens of millions in the
tropical forests of Africa or South America. At present humanity is commonly
divided into developed and underdeveloped populations, or the Soviet bloc
as distinguished from the Western bloc and the rest of the world. Mackinder
does try to relate the modalities of human population to the geographical
conditions. But he would be the last to suggest a determination of the size
of populations by environment, since political problems, in his eyes, are
precisely altered according to the modifications which intervene in the dis¬
tribution of human masses over the surface of the planet.
The geographical vision of universal history is instructive, though it is
partial and schematic, because it emphasizes facts of enormous consequence:
there have been, over the centuries, two kinds of conquerors, two kinds of
nomads—the horsemen and the seafarers; many times over, the vicissitudes
of diplomacy are controlled by the struggle of land and sea, the victory going
to one or the other in turn, depending on whether the continental power
or the maritime power possess more resources, and on whether technology
favors one or the other. The major facts are linked to the geographical frame¬
work. The nomadism of the horsemen and the seafarers is a mode of adapta¬
tion to the environment, a human way of life which must be situated in a
certain kind of space in order to be understood. Mongols or Arabs developed
as they were, on the steppes or on the desert. Yet they have not, except in a
symbolic sense, been created by the fiat spaces, under the enormous immen¬
sity of the sky. Genghis Khan and Mohammed are historical persons for
whom geography shows at most something of their origin. Hence it would be
wrong, though it is tempting, to derive either predictions or ideologies from
a geographical reading of universal history.
0 A 11 these figures, given by Mackinder, date from about twenty years ago.
SOCIOLOGY
I98
Geopoliticians, especially German ones, have not always resisted the tempta¬
tion. Since the thirties, still more today, one question arises, following the
dual consideration of land and sea forces: in a conflict between a continental
empire and a maritime empire, which from this point on lias the best chances
of winning? As a matter of fact, nowhere does Mackinder explicitly answer
such a question. The only universally valid rule to be derived from his
writings is the reasoning of the man-in-the-street as well: in the long run,
the strongest (the most numerous, the richest, the most productive) conquers.
As a theoretician, Mackinder appears in certain respects to be a kind of
anti-Mahan. Whereas the theoretician of naval warfare, writing at the end
of the nineteenth century, is struck by the decisive role of naval supremacy,
the geographer, interrogating the future, fears that the favor of the gods is
shifting to the land. Railroads and engines permit man to triumph over solid
space as effectively as the steamboats triumph over liquid space. What dis¬
tressed the English patriot awakens the hopes of the German nationalists.
The age of maritime power is ending, that of continental power beginning.
The economy of great space will inherit the world market. Whatever the
consequence of these general views, it would have been vain, yesterday, to
conclude from them the result of the Second World War, and it would be
vain, today, to conclude from them the victory of the continental empire.
Probably the number of causes which determine the fortune of states or
coalitions is too great for any short-term estimate as to the outcome of a polit¬
ical or military crisis to be scientifically possible. But in any case, an estimate
of this order should result from a consideration of all the data and not from
a deliberately partial analysis.
Nor did Mackinder formulate a geographical ideology, if we are to under¬
stand by this concept the justification, by an argument of a geographical
order, of goals or ambitions of a political order. Yet he nonetheless arrived
at the source of many geographical ideologies. The latter, in effect, always re¬
turn to a fundamental idea: the idea of space itself—by its extension or by
its quality—as the stake of the struggle between human collectivities. As a
result the ideologies of space-as-stake are divided into two categories, depend¬
ing on whether the necessity invoked is economic or strategic. The ideology of
vital space (espace vital) belongs to the first category, the ideology of natural
frontiers to the second. The ideology of vital space has enjoyed its greatest
success in Germany, the ideology of natural frontiers, in France. Mackinder
did not subscribe to the German ideology of vital space, but he laid the
ground for it, by a curious conception as opposed to Manchester liberalism:
the “protection of a predatory type.”
He had understood, better than many of his contemporaries, the nature of
what we call industrial society, and what he calls a “going concern.” A mod¬
em nation is comparable to an industrial enterprise: rich in relation to its pro¬
ductive capacity, by the measurement of labor output. The number of men
capable of living in a given space increases with the labor output. It is to
ON SPACE
I 99
modern industry that Germany owes the fact that she has been able to double
the size of her population in half a century.
From these facts Mackinder did not deduce that the struggle for the earth
is losing its violence and its significance, since the growth in intensity makes
it unnecessary to enlarge the available surface. He suggests, on the contrary,
that the concentration of populations in a confined space feeds new hatreds
among the nations by waking the fear of collective famine. The more Ger¬
mans there are inside the frontiers of the Reich, the more they fear the lack
of space, hence someday of bread or raw materials.
The harmonious development of industrial society, during the course of
the period previous to the First World War, seemed to Mackinder to have
been compromised as much by Manchester liberalism as by protectionism in
the German style. In his eyes, both tended to prevent the balanced growth
indispensable to each nation or, at least, to each region of the globe. By
balanced growth he meant, according to the philosophy of F. List’s national
economy, the presence in each great economy of all the important industries.
Now, free exchange ultimately accorded the advanced nations the possession
of certain key industries. The most-favored-nation clause, as Germany had
imposed it upon France in the Frankfurt Treaty and, later, upon Russia even
in a simple commercial treaty, had comparable consequences.
The Germans, Mackinder wrote, need the Slavs, who must produce a part
of their food for them and purchase from them their manufactured products.
Thus they are driven by the spirit of panic to ventures of conquest, obliged
to maintain a domination indispensable to their existence. But to this end
they must first of all eliminate the bridgeheads of island or maritime powers
on the Continent. Whereas England doggedly clings to a liberalism that has
become anachronistic, Germany, in her anxiety, is ready to fall back into
cannibalism, while Bolshevik Russia collapses into the anarchy whose con¬
clusion, the geographer prophecies, will be a pitiless despotism. A balanced
development of national economies first of all, a balance among the nations,
among the regions of the globe next—such is the sole path to peace.
It was easy to manipulate ideas in order to make them yield a geographical
ideology. It was enough to insist on the danger incurred by a collectivity
whose existence depends on lands, mines or factories situated heyond its
frontiers. More simply—more crudely, too—it was enough to attribute to col¬
lectivities a natural desire for expansion in order for space to become the
stake and no longer the theater of foreign policy. The German doctrine of
vital space and the Japanese doctrine of co-prosperity were both inspired by a
naturalist philosophy according to which political units are comparable to
living units whose will to live is identified with the will to conquest.
In their propaganda Germans and Japanese were wary of referring to the
principles of their metaphysic. They condemned the lack of space from which
they suffered ([Volk ohne Raurn), hence the need (that they were obliged
to satisfy at any cost) to occupy a more extensive territory, to possess more
200
SOCIOLOGY
cultivable land in order to feed their people, more sources of raw materials
in order to supply their factories. Imperialism became inevitable and legit¬
imate, since it was a question of life or death. Such an argument is obviously
based on the hypothesis that the planet is too small for all tine peoples on it to
prosper: the lack of space affects all humanity, and the pitiless struggle among
states and peoples is the inexorable result.
Such an ideology is contemporaneous not with the great invasions, but
with the awareness of what Paul Valery once called the world finite (Ie
monde fini )JIH The great conquerors, from the Mongols to the Spaniards,
were not concerned with justifying their enterprises and, insofar as they
did so, invoked the superiority of their strength, of their civilization, or
of their gods. From the sixteenth century to the twentieth the Europeans
have prodigiously enlarged their vital space. It was in the twentieth century,
when the planet was or appeared to be entirely occupied, that the Germans,
who had come last on the scene, rationalized their bitterness and their ambi¬
tion by biological-geographic ideology.
In i960, current opinion, subject to sudden reversals, no longer sees any¬
thing but lies and sophisms in the propaganda of yesterday’s imperialists. How
can one admit that the losers of the last war could not survive without addi¬
tional space, whereas the hundred million Japanese, crowded within their
four islands, enjoy a standard of living previously unknown to the Japanese,
lords of the sphere of Asian co-prosperity, and whereas the fifty-five million
Germans of the Federal Republic, in the last ten years, show the highest
population increase of the Occident? And that this increase seems due, in
large part, to the influx of millions of refugees—that is, to the population
density which yesterday’s propagandists denounced?
Inevitably, today’s observers conclude that the imperialist ideology, de¬
rived from geopolitics, marks a transition phase. Mackinder and his German
disciples clearly confirmed that the industrial system permitted a tremendous
increase in the number of men settled on a given surface. But they failed
to carry their analysis to its conclusion: they did not appreciate the possibil¬
ities of a growth in intensity. Prisoners of old concepts, they supposed those
nations were in danger when they were obliged to seek their supplies abroad.
Further, they endorsed the old concept according to which farm workers
should represent an important percentage of the total population, and sug¬
gested that in certain cases only territorial expansion would make it possible
to maintain this percentage. Lastly, they did not understand that in our own
day, taking possession of a space has a radically different meaning, depending
on whether or not that space is empty. By losing Korea, Formosa and Man¬
churia the Japanese lost their controlling position with respect to the popula-
HHActually, Valery was thinking less of the occupation of the entire earth than of
the communication of every fraction of mankind, of every region of the planet, with
each other.
ON SPACE
201
tions of their colonies and protectorates. But they have thereby evaded the
obligation of dispersing their investments. In the case of Japan the ruin of the
empire has favored rather than compromised, accelerated rather than slack¬
ened the development of the national economy.
This interpretation of geographical ideologies and of the Japanese and
German empires, created and destroyed by the preceding generation, does
not entirely convince the historian. Is it possible that we are so much more
intelligent than those who immediately preceded us, than we ourselves were
twenty years ago? Was Hitler’s undertaking, and Japan’s, not only criminal
but absurd, since the punishment of defeat is prosperity thereafter?
Things are not so simple. Military strength is not proportional to the
volume of production and the level of productivity. Japan, disarmed within
her islands, lives better or less badly than yesterday's imperial Japan. But the
latter was a great power, the former is not even a second-class power: in
military terms, Japan is incapable of defending herself: she is a burden and
not a help to her allies. Similarly, the Federal Republic of Germany is
richer than the Third Reich: it achieves a per capita production which the
latter did not attain. It also assures each man a higher revenue than the
revenue of Hitler’s subjects. But Hitler’s subjects participated in the glory of
a great power. The citizen who relied on Chancellor Adenauer owes his
security to the strength of the United States. He is a spectator of the great
conflicts of history. In other words, the imperial attempts were perhaps not
irrational if their goal was collective power, the capacity to affect the course
of history.
Even on the economic level, the problems did not appear so clearly twenty
years ago as they do today. The danger of dependence on external sources of
supply did not seem, at the time, exclusively military; it was regarded as
economic too. In 1919 Mackinder wrote that the Germans were obliged to
reduce the Slavs to the role of purveyors of food and purchasers of manu¬
factured products. Such a theory incorrectly assumes that the industrialization
of one country requires the non-industrialization of another. I believe this
proposition is false in general; it was false, in any case, at the beginning of
the twentieth century, concerning the relations between Germans and Slavs.
The events of the thirties and the great depression have given an ephem¬
eral probability to these ambiguous conceptions, deduced from an incomplete
analysis of the industrial system as well as from the persistence of traditional
ideas. Access to raw materials seemed jeopardized by the lack of currency.
The barriers raised against the Japanese exports created legitimate anxiety in
Japanese public opinion and among the leaders of the Nipponese Empire.
The disintegration of world economy, the return to bilateral agreements, the
multiplication of protectionist measures, all these consequences of the great
depression were indeed of such a nature as to render precarious, in appearance
and even in reality, the fate of nations whose existence was subject to the
hazards of international exchange. That such, today, is the fate of all or of
202
SOCIOLOGY
almost all nations, and that their peoples have grown accustomed to it, does
not prevent us from understanding that during the thirties this dependence
should have seemed terrifying and caused panic.
Thus the fortune of the geographical ideologies seems linked to three kinds
of circumstances. The sedentary peoples, for whom cavalcades and combats
are no longer the normal manner of living and who no longer dare invoke
the god of battles, were prompted, by a dialectical reversal, to deduce spirit
from nature, law from fact and historical legitimacy from physical necessity.
Incomplete comprehension of the industrial system emphasized the risks
rather than the opportunities of the growth in intensity, of the increase in
the number of inhabitants in a given space. Finally, an exceptionally violent
crisis suddenly seemed to confirm these fears and revive the specter of famine.
Therewith Germans and Japanese believed they were back in the distant
ages when populations sought safety in migration.
The ideology of natural frontiers offers, historically, certain features com¬
mon to the ideology of vital space. The latter supposes that conquests need
to be justified and that this justification cannot readily be furnished by
spiritual doctrines. Similarly, the ideology of natural frontiers serves to justify
the frontier when one does not possess a better argument.
In the age of kings and of the dynastic principle, monarchs determined
the possession of cities or provinces among themselves. The will of the popu¬
lations played virtually no part and would not have sufficed to confirm the
legitimacy or illegitimacy of a transfer of sovereignty. The conquests of Louis
XIV caused a scandal because they were effected by force, in certain cases
without even a declaration of war, not because they ignored the sentiments
of populations. The idea of natural frontiers found acceptance in the nine¬
teenth century and appeared all the more convincing to the revolutionaries
because it filled a gap in the new ideas. The French Republic could not take
or yield provinces in the manner of the kings who actually treated their lands
and their subjects as personal property. In its periods of glory and fervor, the
Republic did not annex territory, it liberated peoples from tyranny. Still,
it was necessary that the peoples be prepared to hail as liberators the soldiers
who deposed their kings, to recognize in the French Republic, or in any
satellite republic, the consecration of their own liberty (the point had not
yet been reached of organizing demonstrations of enthusiasm). Vanquished,
France invoked against the German Empire the right of peoples to self-
determination. Victorious, she was tempted to appeal to the notion of natural
frontiers which authorized her to ignore the will of populations.
A natural frontier, if this formula has any meaning, is a frontier traced in
advance on the physical map, indicated by a river or a chain of mountains,
hence easy to defend. A natural frontier should be called strategic or military.
The military argument is the equivalent of the biological or economic argu¬
ment of vital space—it is the substitute for a moral argument. The need for
ON SPACE 203
security justifies the annexation of a province as vital necessity justifies vast
conquests.
The geographical study of frontiers offers virtually no arguments to the
doctrine of so-called natural frontiers. In fact, political frontiers, down
through the centuries, have diverged from the lines of physical separation
(rivers or chains of mountains) as often as they have followed them. The
Alps have marked the frontier between Italy and France for only a century.
The Pyrenees constitute the political but not the linguistic frontier between
Spain and France: on either side of the Pyrenees there are Catalans and
particularly Basques. Nor has the Rhine, which does not mark a linguistic
frontier, become a political frontier between Germans and French.
Can it be said that a political frontier is stronger, has more chances of being
maintained when it consecrates a fiat of geography? This is an illusion. The
stability of a frontier depends only to a small degree on physical or strategic
conditions. It is a function of the relations between the collectivities which
it separates. When in agreement on ideas concerning legitimacy during a
particular period, it creates no occasion for conflict. In this sense, a frontier
regarded by neighboring states as equitable is, in itself, the best frontier,
whether good or bad in military terms. Further, according to the technique
of arms and the configuration of alliances, a frontier changes its meaning.
In the Europe of i960, the Rhine has ceased to be a sensitive area. It has
always favored contact among people and the exchange of goods and ideas.
With the end of Franco-German rivalry, it changes its political-military func¬
tion, since it henceforth flows not between enemies but partners.
Is the frontier between zones of civilizations more visible, more constant
on the map than the frontier between political units? It is along the line
extending from the Baltic to the Adriatic, from Stettin to Trieste, that the
Asian invasion petered out. It is not impossible to find the causes for this
almost natural occurrence: the conqueror’s impulse is exhausted with distance.
We should be nevertheless wrong to rely on geography alone as a guarantee
for the security of Western Europe. If the West were protected only by the
Stettin-Trieste line, there would be reason to fear for its future.
No so-called natural fortification is sufficient to repulse the aggressors. The
outcome of the struggle between nomads and sedentary peoples has never
been predetermined solely by geographical conditions. A fortiori, the victory
of Communist despotism or of the Western democracies, the coexistence of
these two civilizations, the future frontier of two worlds, all are events of
which space will be the theater, but not the exclusive or principal deter¬
minant.
4. Space in the Scientific Age
Is the geographical perspective of history now losing its meaning? Is
humanity liberating itself from the constraints of environment as it acquires
the mastery of natural forces? Will the collectivities, capable of prospering
204
SOCIOLOGY
without conquests, not become more peaceful, once space has ceased to be
the preferred stake of the struggle among peoples?
It is difficult to deny that the progress of technology involves a certain
liberation of humanity, a reduction of environmental constraint. The number
of men capable of living in a given area is no longer rigorously limited in
advance. The choices available to a human group settled in a particular
territory are increased as the trades and professions accessible to each in¬
dividual increase. Means of mastering cold or heat permit us to inhabit re¬
gions of the globe formerly abandoned. We can foresee the time when
scientists will be in a position, without excessive investments, to modify
climate itself. More than ever, the earth is the work of mankind, though it
has pre-existed and might well survive it.
Yet it would be dangerous to compare this liberation, though it may be
gradual and partial, to a total freedom. To take only one example, but the
most important, the number of men capable of living upon given surfaces,
though no longer rigorously limited in advance, has nonetheless not become
unlimited. Thus the judgments of historians or geographers as to the impor¬
tance of space proceed from one extreme to the other.
One American historian, W. P. WebbJUD regards that part of the earth’s
surface which the Europeans possess and have possessed since the sixteenth
century as the major factor which has determined and which today explains
certain features of their societies (liberalism, mobility, etc.). In 1500, 100
million Europeans lived on a territory of 3.75 million square miles, in other
words a density of 7.6 human beings per square mile. With the conquest of
America they acquired some 20 million additional square miles, or about five
times the surface of Europe. Thereby, each European possessed, so to speak,
148 acres instead of 24, not to mention the natural resources (gold, silver,
furs, etc.). The modern period, that which extends from the sixteenth cen¬
tury to the twentieth, was abnormally favorable to the population of Europe.
It has enjoyed advantages which no other population has enjoyed in the
past, which no other, probably, will enjoy in the future.
In the course of these fortunate centuries, the population of Europe has
continually increased. In 1900 the density per square mile had returned to
27; by 1940 it reached 35. Elenceforth, space was more nearly filled, the house
more crowded than at the dawn of modern times. The American historian
thereby concludes that the features peculiar to European societies, especially
the liberal institutions, will disappear with the exceptional circumstances
that have brought them into being. The European societies will return to
the common fate, one like the other.
It is easy to object that Webb exaggerates the significance of his statistics.
A density of 27 in 1900 has not the same value as this same density in 1500.
Density must be measured in relation to technological means, that is, in rela-
0T he Great Frontier, Boston, 1952.
ON SPACE
205
tion to productivity, either by surface unit or by worker unit. If we adopt this
mode of calculation, which is the only valid one, the actual density, even if it
were double or triple that of 1500, would be inferior to it in terms of social
reality. In this connection, one demographer, M. A. Sauvy, asserts that no
portion of the planet today suffers from absolute overpopulation—except per¬
haps Holland. Everywhere else, the difficulty stems from the inadequacy
of development, not the excess of men.
Without discussing this concept at present, which we shall return to in the
following chapter, the present distribution of men and resources on the sur¬
face of the earth suggests that the struggle for space might not be over, de¬
spite the partial independence acquired by the human collectivities with re¬
gard to their environment. M. Vermot-Gauchy has published an interesting
study of this distribution, from which we borrow the following statistics!^
The surface of the earth above water is 52.5 million square miles. The
population being 2784 million in 1955, the average unitary surface (that is,
the available surface per human being) is 12.0 acres. Now let us define two
concepts: we shall call a nation’s individual productivity the quotient of the
national revenue divided by the number of inhabitants; we shall call its
spatial productivity the quotient of the national revenue divided by the num¬
ber of square miles of its territory.
The United States has a huge area of 3.7 million square miles, a national
revenue of $324 billion, a population of 167 million. Its average unitary sur¬
face is 14.0 acres, its individual productivity $1940, its spatial productivity
$34,100. In the U.S.S.R. the unitary surface is 27.5 acres (for an area of 8.6
million square miles, and a population of 200 million), the individual pro¬
ductivity $600 (for a national revenue of $120 billion), the spatial produc¬
tivity $5400. In Europe the unitary surface is 2.8 acres (for an area of 10.1
million square miles and a population of 360 million), the individual produc¬
tivity $650 (for a national revenue of $232 billion), the spatial productivity
$58,000.
On the American continent, Canada has a unitary surface of 156.2 acres,
an individual productivity of $1320, a spatial productivity of $2100. In Latin
America the unitary surface is 28.2 acres, the individual productivity $280,
the spatial productivity $2500.
In the Soviet Zone the European satellites have a unitary surface of 6.25
acres, an individual productivity of $600, a spatial productivity of $26,000.
China has a unitary surface of 3.75 acres, an individual productivity of $100,
a spatial productivity of $6200. Non-Communist Asia has an individual pro¬
ductivity of $100, and a spatial productivity of $5200.
These figures are approximate because of the uncertainty of the calcula¬
tions of national revenue. Further, they are distorted to a degree because the
designated surface does not specify the quality of the land and the nature of
EsS] 1955 figures published in the Bulletin of the S.E.D.E.I.S., No. 726, July 1959.
2o6
SOCIOLOGY
the climate. The northern space which Canada and the Soviet Union possess
is not the equivalent of the fertile lands of Western Europe. But these in¬
contestable errors, though difficult to correct (the distinction between culti¬
vable and non-cultivable land is relative), do not eliminate the significance
of the major data.
Among the developed nations we perceive two categories: those in which
individual productivity exceeds the average (360) more than spatial produc¬
tivity (this is the case of the United States and even of the Soviet Union);
and those, on the other hand, in which the spatial productivity exceeds the
average more than individual productivity (the case of Western Europe).
Even in absolute figures, the spatial productivity of Western Europe (58,000)
exceeds that of the United States (34,000).
Now, on the military level, mediocre unitary surface is a double source of
weakness: it prevents the dispersion which, in the age of thermonuclear
weapons, offers advantages; and it increases the dependence on the supply of
men and factories. Nations with a high spatial productivity—and England,
with her $250,000, is the most striking example—are condemned to buy and
sell a great deal abroad. During preceding centuries this international com¬
merce took place in the shadow of the Union Jack flying aft on the
ships of the Royal Navy. The European population could not do without
food and raw materials from overseas, but armies and fleets guaranteed the
loyalty of the purveyors. In our century this military guarantee has collapsed.
In the name of vital space or the sphere of Asian co-prosperity, Germany and
Japan have sought to escape dependence, or rather to escape economic soli¬
darity. Renouncing these ambitions or these illusions, the Europeans have
subsequently preached the vanity of conquest, the fruitfulness of exchange:
there is room for all. This theory also corresponds to the new situation. Com¬
pared to yesterday’s imperialist ideologies, it also has the advantage of teach¬
ing states the trade of merchants and no longer that of armies.
Similarly, among the so-called underdeveloped nations, two categories are
immediately apparent: nations of relatively strong spatial productivity
(China: $6200) and nations of relatively weak spatial productivity (Latin
America: $2500). China already has a dense population before the process
of industrialization begins. Latin America has an individual productivity
which is nearly triple China’s, and possesses eight times more space per capita.
The basic data are much more favorable for Latin America than for China
—which does not mean that the latter will not progress more rapidly than the
former.
These figures in no way suggest that the people without space will some
day resume the forward march that was interrupted by the irreversible defeat
of German and Japanese imperialism. On the contrary, everything indicates
that in the short run, in terms of decades, unitary surface matters less than
the technological capacity of populations. The nations of the Common Mar¬
ket already have a spatial productivity of some $200,000. They have nonethe-
ON SPACE
207
less experienced since 1950—that is, since the end of the reconstruction period
—the highest rate of increase in the free world. In peacetime, purchases
abroad of a share of the supplies for men and factories involved dependence
(the maintenance of competitive prices is indispensable) but also advantages
(the seller of raw materials depends on the purchaser at least as much as the
latter on the former: in 1956 Europe was afraid of not having enough oil,
the nations which live on royalties are afraid of not finding customers).
Similarly, among the underdeveloped nations, it is not those possessing the
largest unitary surface that will develop most rapidly in the coming decades,
but those likely to establish the most effective industrialization policy. In
other words, during the present historical phase, the ideology of vital space
will not he invoked by the imperialist states, and the lack of space will not
he the direct cause of possible attempts at conquest. Yet we cannot thereby
conclude that the discrepancies in spatial productivity will always remain
without influence. At present, in the race for power, Russians and Americans
have the advantage, in relation to Europeans, of a relatively low population
density, which permits extensive agriculture, allows a broad margin of demo¬
graphic and economic growth, guarantees that at the end of one or of several
centuries, an increase—however slow—in productivity, combined with a
substantial growth of the number of inhabitants, will be expressed by a con¬
siderable increase in total resources. In Europe, France remains below the
demographic optimunUi] of power and well-being, hut Western Germany and
Great Britain cannot increase the size of their population without also raising
the percentage of externally purchased supplies, for both men and industries.
This is not an insurmountable obstacle (the Federal Republic of Germany
has shown this for ten years). It is nonetheless, in general, an unfavorable
circumstance. More clearly still, the Chinese might some day compare the
unitary surface they possess with that of their neighbors. In any case, whether
nations tend to modify the distribution of space by force or accommodate
themselves to the present distribution, correcting by trade the disparities of
density, unitary surface will remain one of the factors which controls the
course of demographic advancement. The Frenchmen in Canada, number¬
ing sixty thousand at the time of the Treaty of Paris, today have more than
five million descendants. They were not different from those in France, but
in the vast spaces of the new country, the majority of their children survived.
The temporary suspension of the struggle for space, as a result of the re¬
sources available to peoples by the growth in intensity, coincides with the
transformation of what we might call the sense of space (the expression was
coined by Professor Carl Schmitt: RaumsiniS) . The sense of space has
been, in each period, determined by the image which men have made for
[IlSee below, Chap. VIII.
[ULSee Carl Schmitt, Land und Meer, eine weltgeschichtliche Betrachtung, Leipzig,
1944.
208
SOCIOLOGY
themselves o£ their habitat, by the style of movement and of combat on land
and at sea, by the stake for which societies came into conflict.
Today humanity as a whole conceives its habitat differently from the river
civilizations of the Egyptian type, from civilizations of closed seas like those
of the Greeks and the Romans, or even from the continental-oceanic civiliza¬
tions, that is, from Western civilization since the voyages of exploration up to
our own period. Lines of communication and thereby those of strategy are
no longer those of yesterday. Planes take passengers from Paris to Tokyo via
the Pole. The United States and the Soviet Union are no longer separated by
Western Europe and the Atlantic: given the speed of strategic bombers or
ballistic missiles, they are quite close to each other and they have the Arctic,
one might say, as a common frontier.
The opposition of land to sea—the one which symbolized the contrast be¬
tween the remote control of the ocean and the yard-by-yard occupation of the
earth, or even between the possessive and stay-at-home spirit of the territorial
power and the adventurous and commercial spirit (pirate or merchant, it
matters little) of the maritime power—tends to lessen or to assume a new
character. Vessels and their crews are no longer isolated, depending on their
own resources for weeks at a time. Corsairs are located by airplanes nowa¬
days, and radio communication permits an orderly regrouping of ships, even
when dispersion is required to avoid destruction.
In terms of myth, we might say that earth and water are henceforth sub¬
ject to the law of air and fire. The same spirit is imposed upon land and sea
forces: that of science. In both cases the leader manipulates men, maneuvers
units, aircraft carriers or divisions according to a plan coordinating the units.
If the spirit of individual initiative, of a surprise attack, of heroic piracy, of
terrorism by alternately noble and sordid passion still finds occasions to mani¬
fest itself, it is no longer on the desert of sand or waves, where rebels are
helplessly hunted down by the air police, but in the mountains and by the
maquis. Because of the aerial weapon, the sea is no longer the province of
adventure. Because of fire, the bases are losing their military importance or,
at least, the bases no longer have a fixed site. The protection of the United
States against a surprise attack is no longer the passive defense of shelters for
the population, nor the active defense of cannons or planes or engines, nor
the military system of fortifications, airfields or ports, but the retaliatory force.
Yet the latter’s security is insured less by the depth of underground protection
or by distance in relation to the enemy than by ubiquity. Atomic submarines,
armed with Polaris rockets, are everywhere and nowhere, they are somewhere
on or under the seas, invulnerable and pacifying. History has decided be¬
tween the theory of the res nullius and the res omnium: the sea belongs to
all. The air, too, starting from a certain height, will belong to all because of
satellites. Rockets strike down spy planes of the U-2 type, but satellites photo¬
graph the earth and transmit photographs.
Having conquered the oceans, and then the air, European man, subse-
ON SPACE
209
quently relayed in his race by all humanity, turns his eyes and his ambitions
toward interstellar space. Will the closed societies pursue their provincial
disputes beyond our planet and our atmosphere, as the English and French
fought each other in the snows of Canada? Or will the rulers of industrial
society finally bring about the reign of order and peace, leaving to the re¬
bellious no other refuge than secluded caves or the solitude of consciousness?
chapter VIII
On Number
We Lave often touched on the problem of number in the preceding chap¬
ter. Indeed, how can we deal with space without suggesting the number of
men who populate each of its pieces? It is the link between the distribution
of natural resources and the distribution of population on the earth’s surface
which suggested to Mackinder the geographical design we have studied
above. It is through the intermediary of number that, to a large degree, space
affects the course of history and the fortune of nations.
The number of men capable of living on a given surface of the earth ob¬
viously varies with their technological means. If we suppose that the latter
are constant—and, for long periods of historyP this supposition was not far
from the truth and even closer to men’s awareness of that truth—events and
institutions, victories and disasters, the ownership of property and public
safety, the attitude of the rulers to trade and wealth, all are justifiably re¬
garded as the direct causes of variations in number.
But this mode of consideration, legitimate in itself, sometimes deceived
the most learned authors into making erroneous propositions. Montesquieu
believed that the population of Europe, in the eighteenth century, was
diminishing!!] He accused the centralization around Paris of causing this
diminution:
"It is the perpetual reunion of many little states that has produced this
diminution. Formerly, every village of France was a capital; there is at present
only one large one. Every part of the state was a center of power; at present
all parts have a relation to one center and this center is in some measure the
state itself.”
Number is a determinant odious to men and, for this very reason, myste¬
rious. It is anonymous, imperceptible. Men have personified, transfigured
fFLet us repeat, once and for all, that by bistory we designate tbe brief period known
as that of tbe higher societies or civilizations, about six thousand years.
fH/Esprit des his, XXIII.
ON NUMBER
211
into a benevolent or malevolent divinity the land or the sea, fire or air, oil or
coal, socialism or capitalism, trusts or the masses. Only a military genius could
admit, without being accused of cynicism, that the favors of heaven went
by preference to the biggest battalions.
Number is the best explanation of events for the man who prefers to
demystify. He also risks discouraging or exasperating those who refuse to re¬
duce their ambitions to the measure of their resources.
I. The Uncertainties of Number
The first question number raises is also the one most difficult to answer.
To know to what degree number determines the strength of armies, the power
of nations, the result of combats, the greatness of states, we would have to
establish exactly the size of populations, the strength of troops in conflict.
Now the figures given by the chroniclers have often been not only false but
foolish. It is as if exactitude, in these matters, filled them with horror.
According to Herodotus, the Persians who besieged the Greek city-states
numbered two million (not counting servants or slaves). We need merely
calculate the distance between the head and the Tear of such an army in
columns to perceive at once the absurdity of the estimatelH Historians have
long been impressed by these assertions from witnesses who in other re¬
spects deserved to be believed. Even today, many hesitate to accept Del-
brlick’s demonstration (which I find convincing) that the Athenians at
Marathon—an infantry of citizens—outnumbered the Persian cavalry^
Perhaps more moderate in their errors, the chroniclers of the Middle Ages
are no more accurate. They count 120,000 Burgundians at the battle of
Grandson; Delbriick reduces the number to I 4 ,oocGD There is no doubt, as
can readily be proved by reference to the possibilities of quartermaster service
and supply, that the great battles of history, before the eighteenth century,
were waged by several thousand combatants. The army with which Alex¬
ander set out for the conquest of Asia, more than forty thousand men, was
not, as we were taught at school, a small army but an enormous one, by the
calculations of the period.
Two psychological mechanisms account for these fantasies in calculation.
iln this chapter I am using Hans Delbriick’s Geschichte der Kriegskunst, irn Rahmen
der politischen Geschichte, Vol. I, Berlin, 1900, I, p. 10. Herodotus attributes to
Xerxes’ army a total o£ 4,200,000, who would have formed a column of 420 miles.
When the head of the column had reached Thermopylae, the rear would still have
been at Suva, beyond the Tigris.
hid., pp. 38 f£. Apropos of Herodotus' figure of two million Persian soldiers, Jean
Berard (Population, 2nd year, No. 2, 1947, p. 304) writes that the figure must be at
least five times too large, perhaps more. If it were only five times too large, there would
still have been four hundred thousand Persian soldiers, which is as improbable as two
million.
HJlbid., pp. 8-9. The argument summarized by Delbriick is to be found in the lectures
published in English, Number in History, London, 1913.
212
SOCIOLOGY
I shall call the first the illusion of multitude. We can all the more readily
understand this mechanism since it continues to function in our own period.
In 1940 the French believed that the number of German parachutists, tanks
and planes was enormous. As a matter of fact, only several thousand para¬
chutists were engaged in the battle (4500). The tanks which broke the
French lines numbered no more than 2580, and there were no more than
3000 airplanes supporting the army; this number was multiplied by the suc¬
cesses they won. Similarly the Normans, the Hussites, and the Mongols who
terrorized Europe numbered no more than several thousand.
A somewhat different mechanism accounts for the apparently involuntary
errors committed by the British in their count of the German planes shot
down in the Battle of England during the summer of 1940. The 185 planes
were actually only 46. The same victim was claimed, perhaps justifiably, by
several pursuit pilots. By attributing to each of the latter a different victim, the
true figure was ultimately multiplied by three or four. The illusion of multi¬
tude appears not only when each witness feels he is in the presence of a
tremendous host, but also when each witness is supposed to have seen a
different enemy.
It is only a step to the second mechanism, which I shall call interested
falsification. The number of those who paraded in Paris from the Place de la
Republique to the Place de la Bastille in May 1958 varied, according to the
political preferences of the newspapers, as much as three times the actual
figure. Each camp exaggerates the losses suffered by the enemy and system¬
atically underestimates its own.
Sometimes the illusion of multitude is combined with interested falsifica¬
tion. Did the Greeks believe in the forces they attributed to Xerxes, or did
they wish to magnify their own merits? Were hordes of German tanks and
planes necessary to excuse defeat, or had the French convinced themselves
of the exactitude of the figures which furnished an excuse and, simulta¬
neously, corresponded to the truth of their impressions?
Despite the critical studies of historians, the number of combatants has
not been established for every great battle with unquestionable precision.
Thus the role of numerical superiority or inferiority remains, by definition,
uncertain. Such uncertainty seems to me still greater when the size of popu¬
lations is in question. It is often difficult to distinguish the partial depopula¬
tion which affects the privileged classes or, at least, the combatant classes,
from total depopulation. The ancient authors leave us no doubt as to the
first phenomenon: we know, with great exactitude, the number of citizens
in Athens and Sparta at different dates. Yet this does not warrant our draw¬
ing conclusions concerning the total population, including foreigners and
slaves. And indeed, depending on whether we are concerned with citizens
or total population, the phenomenon is not the same. In one case it is a
question of differential fertility according to class, for which social organiza-
ON NUMBER
213
tion is responsible; in the other it is a question of a kind of exhaustion of
vitality.
Even if the first obstacle were surmounted, if we established the numerical
data concerning the forces of the combatants and the size of populations, it
would not he easy to isolate the influence of number. Let us take a historical
example, a well-known one, in which the figures are precise and certain.
The Franco-German War of 1870 is subdivided into two phases: during the
first the regular armies of the Second Empire, composed of professional sol¬
diers, were defeated by the more numerous armies of Prussia and her allies.
During the second phase the armies improvised by the Government of Na¬
tional Defense, despite their numerical superiority, were also defeated. Must
we impute the defeat of Napoleon Ill’s armies to numerical inferiority, to
the better quality of the Prussian cannon, or to the deficiencies of the French
command? To what degree to each of these causes? Rarely, down through the
centuries, have authors invoked number in order to explain the fortune of
arms, but, even today, it is difficult for us to specify the role such explana¬
tions play in a given circumstance or at any one period of history.
As it is not our intention to analyze specific cases in detail—and only such
analyses would permit us to reduce the margin of uncertainty—we shall try to
develop propositions of a certain generality bearing on two chief problems:
the influence of number on strength or power, and the relation between
population (or overpopulation) and wars.
Let us first note the changes in the order of size. There were probably
three to five thousand Athenian combatants on the battlefield of Marathon.
Alexander set out for the conquest of Asia with an army (enormous for the
period) of some forty thousand warriors. Napoleon mobilized ten times as
many men in order to cross the frontiers of Russia in January 1812. The army
which Hitler had amassed in 1941 with a view to the same enterprise num¬
bered in millions and not in hundreds of thousands of men. There were only
one hundred million people on earth at the time of the birth of Jesus Christ,
about six hundred million at the beginning of the seventeenth century; today
there are three billion.
The force and cultural contribution of the collectivities have never been
proportional to their respective size. Whether we attribute the miracle of
Greece and the creations of Athens to social circumstances or hereditary gifts,
the fact remains that one man has never, historically, been “equal to another”
on a one-to-one basis. Within political units as in the competition among
them, the smaller number has more than once been the artisan of fate.
On the battlefield, number has almost always been an important factor. In
particular, within a zone of civilization, when neither arms nor organization
were essentially different, it tended to force the decision. Still we may modify
or correct the preceding proposition by two remarks. In the case of a conflict
between combatants who belong to fundamentally heterogeneous collectivi-
214
SOCIOLOGY
ties, a small troop is capable of scoring spectacular successes. The term “con¬
quest a la Cortez” has become classical in the literature. Several dozen
Spanish cavaliers represented a force of the first rank, facing the Aztecs of
pre-Columbian Mexico. Similarly, in Europe, a few thousand Asian barbar¬
ians have more than once spread terror among populations incomparably
larger.
Moreover, in antiquity, and even more generally down through the cen¬
turies preceding modern times, there did not exist a rigorous ratio between
size of population and number of combatants. The most enormous empires
could be built on a limited base, as in the case of the Romans, the Arabs or
the Mongols. As the result of a high degree of mobilization, a more effective
organization and the extension of citizenship to the conquered, a city-state
could subject an entire zone of civilization to its rule without ever losing
equality or numerical superiority on the battlefield. The capacity to arm a
great number of men was a proof of political art, as the capacity to concen¬
trate one’s forces is still a proof of strategic art.
To proceed beyond these generalities, we must consider separately two
typical periods, antiquity on the one hand, nineteenth- and twentieth-century
Europe on the other. In the Greek world Athens was a giant unit because
it included, on the eve of the Peloponnesian War, forty thousand citizens
and, with foreigners and slaves, over two hundred thousand souls. In nine¬
teenth-century Europe, France seemed doomed to decadence because her
population rose only slowly. Turning from the Athens of five centuries before
Christ to the France of nineteen centuries after Christ, we substitute for the
thousands (or at most the tens of thousands) of the Greek authors the mil¬
lions of the contemporary demographers and for static consideration (what is
the ideal volume of the city-state?) dynamic analysis (what is the preferable
rate of increase?).
Further, the relations between the forces of the city-states and the forces
of the armies, the size of populations and the number of soldiers, are not the
same and cannot be the same in the age of heroism and the age of petroleum
or of the atom, to employ the expressions of J. F. C. Fuller^ As long as
weapons are simple and cheap, the degree of mobilization is a result of the so¬
cial regime. In our period this degree depends on economic resources and on
the solidity of the central power. The number of machines is more important
than the number of men.
It is from these two points of view—the way of dealing with the demo¬
graphic problem, the relation between the size of the population and the
number of soldiers, between the strength of the city-states and the strength
of the armies—that we shall sketch a comparison between antiquity and mod¬
em times.
GDrfee Influence of Weapons on History, New York, 1945.
ON NUMBER
215
2. Ideal Stability and Demographic and Political Instability
The Greek philosophers posed the problem of what we shall call the
population optimum^ which can scarcely surprise us, since they were not
content with an objective, neutral study of facts and causes, but attempted
to grasp the finality of order or of the good. The city-state, in their eyes, was
the unit in which social life had to be organized. Thus Plato and Aristotle
both queried not so much the ideal as the natural size of the city. Ten in¬
dividuals do not make a city-state, Aristotle writes, nor do ten times ten thou-
sandPO Plato, in the Laws, suggests the number 5040. “The number 5040
offers remarkable arithmetical properties: it is the product of seven whole
prime numbers; therefore it has the advantage over other numbers of being
the one which permits the greatest number of divisors. This results in great
administrative convenience, when it is a question of subdividing the popula¬
tion, distributing the citizens or recruits, arranging them in columns on pub¬
lic registers, on tax rolls or in the field. 0
These strange speculations are neither senseless nor even entirely anach¬
ronistic. The goal of the city-state, that is, of politics, is not power, but a life
according to reason. Since the virtuous life is possible only in society, we
must therefore determine the number of citizens that favors or makes possible
an order that accords with reason. Two considerations are or risk being in
conflict: the necessities of defense against an external enemy require a large
number; moral cohesion demands a small number. The compromise must be
within a just proportion: the city-state must be neither too small nor too large.
An Athens of forty thousand citizens suffers from gigantism.
“The facts prove that it is difficult if not impossible to govern properly a
state whose population is too numerous; at least we see that none of those
which have the reputation of being well-governed can increase its population
without measure. This is evident and confirmed by reason: for the law is a
certain order, and good laws necessarily constitute good order; now a too-
numerous population cannot lend itself to the establishment of order ... a
city-state that has too many inhabitants cannot be self-sufficient; now the
quality of a city-state is to be self-sufficient. The city-state in which the pop¬
ulation is too large can no doubt care for all its needs, but then as a tribe,
and not as a city-state. It is not easy to organize a political order there. What
general can command an excessive multitude? . . . What herald could make
himself heard if he had not a stentor’s voice? Therefore the city-state is nec¬
essarily formed once it is composed of a sufficient multitude to have all the
conveniences of life according to the rules of political association. It is pos¬
sible that the city-state in which the number of inhabitants exceeds this mea¬
sure is still a city-state on a larger scale; but, as we have said, such excess has
1 Nichomachean Ethics, IX, 10, 1170, b3i-32.
BDCf. J. Moreau, “Les Theories demographiques dans 1 ’antiquite grecque,” Population,
Alb. year, No. 4, October—December 1949, pp. 597-613.
@Laws, V, 737e~738a.
2 l6
SOCIOLOGY
limits. And what are these limits? The facts themselves readily indicate them.
Political acts derive from those who command or from those who obey; and
the function of those who govern is to command and to judge. In order to
judge the rights of each and to distribute judgments depending on merit, the
citizens must know and appreciate each other; when this is impossible, the
judgments are necessarily bad. In this regard, it is not just to act without
reflection, and yet this is obviously what happens in a very populous city.
Further, it then becomes easy for foreigners and slaves to involve themselves
in government; for it is not difficult to escape surveillance in an excessive
multitude of inhabitants. It is therefore obvious that the most convenient
limit to the population of a city-state is that it should include the greatest
possible number of inhabitants to suffice for its needs, but without surveil¬
lance ceasingto be easy. Let us here end what we have to say on the size of
a city-state.
Since the goal is a city-state that conforms to the just measure, neither too
large nor too small, large enough to be self-sufficient and capable of defend¬
ing itself, small enough for the citizens to know each other and for the gov¬
ernment to be good, the population policy conceived by Plato or Aristotle
tended to avoid overpopulation or depopulation. In other words it aimed at
maintaining a stationary population, since the danger, in the classical period,
was that of excessive numbers or of insufficient space, stenochoria. The
Greek idea that beyond a certain size a population can no longer be governed
according to reason has today fallen into disuse, but it was long regarded as
obvious by Western thinkers. We find an echo of it in the first books of
L’Esprit des lots, in which the type of government is made to correspond
with the dimensions of the territory and where despotism is regarded as in¬
evitable in the vast empires of Asia.
This ideal of stability was, in fact, the counterpart of an extreme instabil¬
ity of number on the one hand, and of the political fortune of collectivities
on the other. "One generally thinks of ancient Greece as the country in
which Athens and Sparta prevailed. But this simplified image is quite in¬
exact. Athens and Sparta disputed hegemony in the fifth and fourth centuries
b.c., and were the great centers of Hellas in the period that marks the apogee
of ancient Greek civilization, but they were such centers only at that period.
In the Mycenaean period, the greatest centers were the city-states which, like
Pylos or Triphylia, had ceased to exist in the classical period or, like Mycenae
and Tiryns, had lost all importance. In the archaic period, from the eighth to
the seventh centuries b.c., the great metropolitan centers were Chalcis and
Eretria in Euboea, or Corinth and Megara in Greece proper. In Asia-Minor,
they were Phocaea and Miletus. By the fourth century', the hegemony that
Athens and Sparta had disputed in the fifth soon passed to Thebes in Beoetia,
whose inhabitants had the reputation of being dull-witted, then to Mace-
[i 2 l Aristotle, Politics, IV (vii), 4, 1326 aiy-b24.
ON NUMBER
217
donia, which had hitherto developed on the fringe of the Hellenic world and
which to the true Hellenes seemed only half-Greek .’0 How could fortune
fail to be fickle when a city-state of ten thousand citizens already passed for
a great one?
A “giant” city-state, like Athens, had a future that was still less certain.
The population of Athens could live only by importing a great share of its
food, at least half, perhaps more. The city-state had begun to perform ac¬
tivities which, in our century, are called industrial. She was selling the prod¬
ucts of her mines (silver from Laurium, marble from Pentelica), of her
artisans (ceramics, textiles, naval construction); she depended as much on
her non-Athenian residents and her slaves as upon her customers and her
purveyors. Yet such a dependence, at the time, had a significance entirely
different from that of our own period. The maritime empire of Athens, grad¬
ually formed in the early stages by alliances among city-states against the
Persians, was maintained only by the superiority of the fleet and the tributes
paid by allies which had become satellites. Those economic activities which
are not based upon the development of the means of production, which are
linked to the primary sector (mines) or to the tertiary sector (commerce, ser¬
vices) have been, down through the ages, sensitive to the vicissitudes of
military victories and defeats. In the ancient world, imperial greatness and
wealth were in fact inseparable.
The ideal of a stationary population was not only a reaction against the
fickleness of fortune, but also corresponded to the excess and lack of men
from which Greece alternately suffered. The excess of men was the source
of the vast movement of colonization of the eighth and seventh centuries
b.c. It was also the origin of the surplus of warriors who were ready to serve
as mercenaries. This abundance of men dedicated to the profession of arms
permits us to explain Alexander’s conquests. In the fourth century b.c. Greece
was still a vast reservoir of soldiers. The unification of the city-states, even in
servitude, created the equivalent of a great power. Independent, the city-
states exhausted themselves in sterile conflicts. Subject to one master, they
were capable of vast conquests. In the fourth and even more in the third
century b.c. the contrary evil, that of oliganthro'py, was rampant. At the be¬
ginning of the fourth century the number of Athenian citizens diminished by
one fourth (from forty to thirty thousand). Still more striking is the depopu¬
lation of Sparta. According to Herodotus, the hoplites, in 480 b.c., numbered
eight thousand. There were no more than two thousand of them in 371, on
the eve of the battle of Leuctra. They numbered seven hundred by the mid¬
dle of the third century b.c. Jean Berard quotes Polybius, who observes and
explains the phenomenon:
“All Greece suffers from a check in procreation and a dearth of men, such
that the cities are depopulated because the men of the times, loving luxury,
iiUjean B&ard, op. cit., p. 309.
2 l8
SOCIOLOGY
money, and idleness as well, no longer wish to marry, or, if they marry, to
raise a family, and because they all consented to have two children at most
in order to bring them up in luxury and leave them rich when they die.”
And, commenting on the ancient historian, the modem one, discussing the
first centuries of our era, writes:
“The qualitative and quantitative diminution of the population which suc¬
cessively affects all the provinces of the Empire is particularly manifest in
Greece. A disconcerting observation: as if security infallibly softened peoples,
as if effort and struggle were necessary to temper them and condition them
for a high birth rate. "EH
In the case of Sparta, there is no doubt that the laws were the direct cause
of the depopulation. The citizens were warriors all their lives. They had no
right to undertake lucrative employment. In order for each man to keep
enough funds to pay his share of the common meal, a system of inalienable
entail had been established, which naturally exercised a Malthusian influ¬
ence. Similarly, in all the Greek city-states, the methods conceived to prevent
population increase (delayed marriages, exposure of children, infanticide)
were put into practice, even in the classical period. They were not abandoned
in the following centuries. Malthusianism was implied by the structure of
the city-state, by the distinction between slaves and free men, by the es¬
sentially political and military vocation of the citizens.
The dimension of political units therefore exerted a major influence on the
course of Greek history. The city-state was the typical form of the collective
organization (whatever the causes of this organization). The city-states to¬
gether were capable of resisting the Persian Empire by the simple recourse
of temporary alliances. They were capable of setting out for the conquest of
Asia once they were subject to the will of a Philip and an Alexander. But
when Alexander had subjected to his ambition the forces of Greece, which
had remained unrealized in the period of jealous emulation (to borrow
Hume’s expression), the city-states no longer had a future, a raison d’etre. De¬
prived of their independence without a Caesar to carry them off on some
vast enterprise, they inexorably died out.
How and why did a city-state, located on the fringe of the so-called Hel¬
lenic civilization, transcend this final stage and effect a lasting peace not only
over the Greek city-states, as Macedonia had done, but over an incomparably
more extensive historical space? Admirers of the Roman works, like Arnold
Toynbee and Jerome Carcopino, emphasize characteristically political or
moral causes. ToynbedSD lists five: a favorable geographical situation, gener¬
osity toward the peoples who became the allies of Rome and accepted her
hegemony, generosity in granting Roman citizenship to allies and subjects,
the liberal institution of double citizenship, and finally the practice of es-
Elljean Berard, op. cit., p. 312..
HUA Study of History, Vol. XII, Oxford, 1961, pp. 380 ff.
ON NUMBER
219
tablishing colonies in newly conquered territories. Simone Weil counters this
analysis by another element of Roman policy whose reality is indisputable:
the unfortunately indubitable effectiveness of terror: “No one has ever
equaled the Romans in the skillful use of cruelty. When cruelty is the effect
of a caprice, of a diseased sensibility, of rage, of hatred, it often has fatal
consequences to its employer; the cold, calculated cruelty which constitutes a
method, the cruelty which no instability of mood, no consideration of pru¬
dence, respect or pity can temper, which one can hope to escape by neither
courage, dignity and energy, nor by submission, supplications and tears—
such cruelty is an incomparable instrument of domination. For being blind
and deaf as the forces of nature, yet clearsighted and far-seeing as human
intelligence, by this monstrous combination it paralyzes the spirit with the
sense of a fatality.’^ Simone Weil does not hesitate to compare the Romans
with the Nazis, and, employing modern concepts, she comes to the following
conclusion: "The Romans conquered the world by seriousness, discipline,
organization, continuity of outlook and method; by the conviction that they
were a superior race bom to command; by the calculated, methodical use of
pitiless cruelty, of cold perfidy, of hypocritical propaganda, employed simul¬
taneously or alternately; by an unshakable resolve always to sacrifice every¬
thing to prestige, without ever being sensitive to pity, to peril, nor to any
human respect; by the art of decomposing under terror the very soul of their
adversaries, or of lulling them by hope before enslaving them by arms; lastly
by so skillful a manipulation of the crudest lies that they deceived even
posterity and deceive us still. ’EH
It would be difficult to deny the share of this psychologico-military tech¬
nique in the Roman conquests as in the building of all empires. It is none¬
theless tme that after the terrorist phase, the generosity of the victor granting
citizenship to the vanquished and the spread of double citizenship contrib¬
uted to the strengthening of Rome’s power and gave some substance to the
eulogy of the Empire intoned by the descendants of those who had lost their
freedom.
But, curiously, neither the admirer nor the detractor of the Roman achieve¬
ment attempts any analysis of what was, and remains, the primary condition
of an empire: the fortune of arms. Empire builders, by definition, generally
gain it on the battlefield or, in any case, win the last battles. On what did
Rome’s military superiority depend?
On the whole, we might say that Rome did not possess an incontestable
or overpowering superiority in the quality of weapons. Of course, the peoples
of antiquity did not all utilize the same weapons. The mode of combat de¬
pended on the mode of life and the social organization. Horsemen or foot
soldiers, heavily or lightly equipped, using impact weapons or projectiles, the
S 3 Ecrits historia ues et volitiques, Paris, i960, p. 28.
USlfeitJ., p. 24.
220
SOCIOLOGY
warriors of the ancient world were not interchangeable, nor did they do
battle according to one typical method. But the principal city-states were
capable of procuring most kinds of arms, and if their metal was not always of
the same quality, the fact remains that the determinant of superiority was not
the quality of the weapons.
The superiority of the Roman legions on the battlefield was essentially that
of an organization, of a tactic, one might say of the capacity to maneuver.
According to Delbriick, whose authority we accept liere as well, it was
heavy cavalry that constituted Philip's decisive weapon: the Macedonian
horsemen were capable of collective order in the heat of combat. The com¬
bination of brutality and discipline was the secret of victory at the time, since
neither side’s weapons were fundamentally different.
The Romans owed the fusing of their legions into tliree echelons to the
discipline achieved by Philip with his heavy cavalry, thus making the latter’s
men less vulnerable than the Spartan, Theban and Macedonian phalanx.
Whereas the latter was incapable of protecting itself on its flanks or at the
rear, the Roman legion, even after the outset of the encounter, could reverse
its fronts. Whether it be Philip’s cavalry or the legions of Rome, their greatest
effectiveness lay in the category of "capacity for collective action." This
original order of battle generally requires some modification in armament, a
new combination of types of combatants and of combat weapons (longer or
shorter spears, heavier or lighter body armor, different distribution of infantry
and cavalry, etc.). But above all, the superiority based on a capacity for col¬
lective action, in the realm of military disciplined is not immediately trans¬
missible, for it is linked to the social structure and requires a considerable
training. The Romans gradually perfected the legion’s organization, tactics
and armament; they developed its effectiveness under fire; but they would
never have possessed such an instrument of war had the struggle with Car¬
thage not transformed the mobilized citizens into professionals^
The capacity of the Roman legions for maneuver was one necessary con¬
dition of its victories; the number of legionnaires was another. In periods of
crisis the degree of mobilization was, in Rome, exceptionally high, io pei
cent of the free population, 30 per cent of the adult males, according to this
same author.^ Rome’s “generosity” to her conquered enemies permitted hei
to enlarge her armed forces as the zone of Roman sovereignty increased. Nc
matter how enormous this zone was, the Romans generally equaled or out¬
numbered their enemies on the battlefield. The Empire was not maintained
Nh. Delbriick, I, 1, p. 239.
lllRbid., pp. 277 and 333.
EUH. Delbriick estimates at a million the free population of Rome at the beginning
of the Second Punic War. The mobilization of twenty-two to twenty-three legions, ir
212 or 211 b.c., represents a considerable effort.
ON NUMBER
221
by the prestige of a small minority, but by the permanent mobilization of the
legions.
The power of the Roman legions was nonetheless limited in space. As a
result of the immensity of their territory, its forests and sparse population, the
Germans escaped, whether for their good or evil fortune, the fate of the Celts
of Gaul. The Germans were not Romanized, they continued to speak their
Ursprache, an original language and not one derived from that of the con¬
querors. Confronting the Parthian Empire, Rome was content with a peace of
coexistence.
Of these elements of the Roman success, that of number (the number of
combatants) is almost always omitted, while the maneuverability of the le¬
gions is scarcely indicated and intentionally identified with virtue. Now ef¬
fectiveness in action deserves to be regarded as a political if not a moral
virtue, but it implies neither cultural or spiritual values. Since the historians
have paid homage to the Roman virtu of the imperial edifice, they cannot
fail to attribute the decline to corruption. Military force is a function
of the number of soldiers the Empire can mobilize, of the discipline of the
legions, of their martial ardor. When the legions include more and more
barbarians, and are incapable of raising an impenetrable blockade on the
frontiers and sometimes even of conquering on the battlefield, it is evident
that the system is weakening, a weakness which reflects the decomposition of
the state and the loss of civic virtues^
It is difficult for the historians, after having exalted the Roman Empire,
not to deplore its fall. But it would be paradoxical, in a period when we de¬
nounce the colonial empires under the name of colonialism, still to take the
side of the conquerors without reservations.
3. The French Experience
According to the Greek philosophers, a sufficient number is a condition of
security, but security’s goal is friendship among the citizens, impossible in a
city-state whose population is too numerous. According to modern authors,
number is the condition of power and the latter, in its turn, a condition of
rank. Since nations are engaged in a permanent rivalry and since some of
them grow' rapidly, the others must do the same, or risk decadence. The
comparison of rates of growth, both demographic and economic, is substituted
for the search for the mean.
A century ago, in a book which enjoyed a tremendous success, Prevost-
Paradol wrote: “When the present leader of our country declares that a na¬
tion’s rank is measured by the number of men it can arm, he has only given
[HI For example, Jerome Carcopino writes in Les Eta-pes de I’imperialisme romain, Paris,
1961: “Rome’s military decadence can, on reflection, be reduced to two causes which
no longer function in our modern world: the sudden multiplication of enemies whose
weapons were virtually equivalent to her own and the specialization of a professional
army whose civic ardor would be harmed.”
222
SOCIOLOGY
too absolute a form to a true idea, for we must take into account the relative
quality of men as well as their number. Xerxes, for example, armed infinitely
more men than Greece, and yet the great spirit of Greece conquered him.
But in a case of nations equally civilized and of courageous citizens equally
sustained by a sense of honor, this maxim becomes strictly true, and political
and military ascendancy goes to the most numerous nation, with all the ma¬
terial and moral advantages which derive from it.’®
It is in France, the first European nation affected by the lowering of the
birth rate, that the various problems of number have been looked upon with
most anxiety. The first theme is the one which the preceding quotation ex¬
presses: to what degree is there a proportion between a nation’s size, the
strength of its army and its place in the world? The second problem is raised
by France’s conquests in the nineteenth century: is it possible to compensate
by recruiting soldiers in Asia and Africa for the relative decline of metro¬
politan France?
By the thirties another fear was expressed: did not demographic stagnation
involve economic stagnation? Far from small families guaranteeing the for¬
tune of each child, experience proves that in dynamic and not static con¬
sideration, in national and not microscopic accounting, the result is entirely
different. Demographic growth, at least in certain cases, provokes a more
than proportional growth in resources.
Finally, since the Second World War, it is no longer France but the West
which apprehensively questions the comparative statistics of populations. Will
not the disparity between the standard of living of the privileged white mi¬
nority and that of the colored masses be increased by a disparity in the op¬
posite direction, numerical growth being faster precisely where poverty
makes numerical stabilization desirable?
If we take an inclusive view of France’s experience in Europe in the last
century, it seems difficult to deny that the law of number has functioned.
There were about 28 million Frenchmen in 1800, 4T.9 million in 1940. Over
the same period the population of the United Kingdom increased from 11 (16
with Ireland) to 46.4 million, that of Germany from 22.5 to 70 million, that
of Italy from 18 to 44 million,^ that of the United States from 5.3 to 131.7
million. The population of Tsarist Russia, known with less exactitude, in¬
creased about two and a half times during the nineteenth century.
In 1800 France with 28.2 million represented 15 per cent of the European
population; Austria-FIungary, with 28 million, 15 per cent; Italy with 18 mil¬
lion, 9.2 per cent; Germany with 23 million, 13 per cent; the British Isles
(including Ireland) 9 per cent; Russia, with 40 million, 21 per cent. In
f 20 jLa France nouvelle, Paris, 1868, p. 174.
These figures do not take emigration into account. The nations whose population:
rapidly increased could, at the same time, contribute to the population of America
and the Dominions: 17 million people left the United Kingdom between 1825 and
1920, 6 million Germans emigrated to the United States during the same period, and
9 million Italians between 1876 and 1925.
ON NUMBER
223
1900 France’s percentage had fallen to 10 (40.7 million); Austria’s to 12 (50
million); Germany’s had risen to 14 (56.4 million); Great Britain’s to 10.6
(41.5 million); Russia’s to 24 (100 million). In the twentieth century the
comparison between France and her European rivals is still more unfavorable.
France’s population is not increasing at all, that of her rivals continues to do
so.
In general, the relation of forces follows fluctuations in size. Yet some
reservations immediately come to mind. At the beginning of the nineteenth
century, England played a part on the world stage out of proportion to her
human resources. Her island position, as long as she had no battle to wage
on the Continent, afforded incomparable advantages (which no longer exist
today). In the contrary sense, the case of Russia reminds us that the law of
number functions, in our times, only in combination with the law of the
number of machines. In 1914, lacking adequate industrialization, and lacking
too, perhaps, a political regime capable of leading the nation, Russia’s strength
was far from being proportional to her population statistics.
In France’s case, success in war was not directly determined by number in
1870 or in 1939. In 1870, assuming that the major cause of the initial de¬
feats was the numerical inferiority of the imperial armies, this inferiority was
attributable to the military system, not to the nation’s human resources (which
were, at the time, of the same order as the enemy’s). Similarly, though the
superiority of the Third Reich’s human and industrial potential to that of
France was enormous, it was not this superiority which determined the over¬
whelming victory of May-June 1940. The numerical superiority of tanks and
above all of planes was one 'of the causes of the lightning campaign, but the
principal cause was a piece of inspired strategy (the plan proposed by General
von Manstein to split the Franco-English armies along the Ardennes hinge)
and an original tactic, a new combination of firepower and mobility, assault
tanks functioning en masse and planes attacking the combatants and the im¬
mediate rear lines of the battlefield. It was in 1914-18 and at the end of the
1939-45 conflict that the Second and the Third Reich were finally over¬
whelmed by number—the preponderance of soldiers and still more of cannon,
tanks and planes.
France’s European experience reveals the influence of number on the course
of diplomatic and military history, hut more subtly. Indeed, if France nearly
perished from the victory of 1918, she was tragically saved by her defeat of
1940. Of all the belligerents, it was France that, from 1914 to 1918, made,
relatively speaking, the most considerable efforts, in both industrial and in
human mobilization, and it was also France that suffered proportionally the
highest losses (nearly 1.4 million men as opposed to 2 million in Germany).
At the peace conference France shone with a glory that was dearly won, hut
she was also, without a sudden rise in her birth rate, the most weakened of
all the European nations. In 1940, with a military establishment adapted to
mechanized and motorized war, France—in theory—could have fought for
224
SOCIOLOGY
months, perhaps for a year or even two. While the battle continued in the
West, the Soviet Union would have played the role of tertius gaudens and
the Anglo-American forces would have left to France the heaviest burden.
Yet German war industry, reinforced by that of central Europe (Czecho¬
slovakia, Austria) outclassed that of France (that of England would not have
been mobilized before 1942). In 1941 Germany could have put several dozen
additional divisions into the lines. Had the French campaign lasted twelve
to eighteen months, material destruction and human losses would have been
three or four times greater, perhaps more. Would France have recovered,
after a new bloodlettingf^H
The paradox of France’s recent history is the coincidence of demographic
decline and imperial expansion. It is tempting to resolve this paradox by ex¬
plaining the latter by the former, France seeking in Africa a reservoir of
additional manpower to re-establish equilibrium with her rivals’ potential.
Such an interpretation is almost the only one which gives an apparent
rationality to France’s foreign policy, particularly under the Third Republic.
Why did France, which had neither a surplus of men nor of manufactured
products to export, why did the opportunist, then radical Republic conquer
the second largest colonial empire in the world? Of course, the historians
who are content with historical explanations—explanations which philoso¬
phers and sociologists delight in heaping with scorn—may recall that once
the city of Algiers was taken, it was even more difficult to evacuate Algeria
entirely than to complete its occupation HD Subsequently, French Algeria
could not be secure unless it was shielded by a double protectorate over
Tunisia and Morocco. As for the race for equatorial Africa QAfrique noire),
it was European rather than specifically French. France’s originality was the
ideology of her civilizing mission, which implied a certain assimilation of
the colonies to metropolitan France. Conscription was the first translation of
this doctrine, not devoid of a certain abstract generosity.
The reinforcement of the conqueror by his conquests and the mobilization
of the conquered are endemic phenomena down through the centuries. Even
in i960, despite the almost universal diffusion of nationalism, thousands of
Moslems fought under the French flag, perhaps indifferent to the nation the
FLN claimed to be, or animated by resentment against the underground
fighters, or simply impelled by poverty. Rarely, in the past, have men known
HUAnd would the war itself have been won had the British finally lost their expedi¬
tionary corps after a year of battle?
iMlln a speech to the Chamber of Deputies on January 15, 1840, General Bugeaud
said: "Limited occupation seems to me a chimera and a dangerous chimera.” Later in
the same speech: “Abandonment: official France, to employ an expression not in my
habitual vocabulary, official France does not want it; that is, the writers, the
aristocracy of the inkwell, do not want it.” And lastly: “Yes, in my opinion, the tak¬
ing of Algiers is a mistake; but, since you want to take it, since it is impossible for
you not to take it, you must do so on a grand scale, for that is the only way to
obtain results. Therefore the whole country must be conquered and the power of Abd-
el-Kader destroyed. . . .” The speech is published in Par Ve-pee et far la charrue,
Bugeaud’s writings and speeches, Paris, 1948, pp. 61-71.
ON NUMBER
225
(or needed to know) why they were fighting. Loyalty to the leader, submis¬
sion to the existing order, pure and simple discipline have constituted the
cement of armies more often than faith in a nation or in an idea.
In this regard, the European empires, until 1945, have followed the ex¬
ample of their predecessors. The United Kingdom could not have exerted a
dominant influence in Asia and in the Near East if it had not had the Indian
army with which to complement the Royal Navy. It was with the Indian
army, under British command even when the majority of the officers were
Indian, that the Crown imposed peace from the Persian Gulf to the Suez
Canal and, eastward, to the borders of Indo-China. Similarly, Algerians,
Moroccans and Senegalese fought on the battlefields of World War I. Thus
Algerians had contributed to the pacification of their own country as they
had participated in the remotest conquests of the French Republic.
Does the reinforcement of the metropolitan army by the mobilization of
non-native populations have as its condition or limit a specific percentage of
non-Romans in the Roman legions, of Vietnamese in the French expedition¬
ary corps in Indo-China, of Africans in the African army? It is obvious that
in each period it is dangerous to exceed a certain percentage, yet this per¬
centage is not always the same.
In our period the British Indian army or the French African army on the
one hand, the “yellowing” of the French expeditionary corps in Indo-China
on the other, differ fundamentally. The British Indian army faithfully served
the Crown during World War II, despite the Congress party’s refusal to
cooperate. Similarly, the Moroccan regiments, of which only the officers and,
to a degree, the non-commissioned officers were French, fought for France in
1939-40, in 1943-45 ar) d, even in Indo-China, until 1954. If France had
pursued a policy of force in North Africa for a few years more, would the
Moroccan troops under French command have remained loyal? Would the
more than two hundred Moroccan officers in the regular cadres of the French
army have yielded to the nationalism which animated their compatriots? We
do not know. In fact, these armies have tended, in our period, to abide by
a strictly military discipline—which does not mean that the best-organized
troops remain insensitive to the passions of the people from which the soldiers
have been recruited.
The integration, in a relatively high proportion though scarcely more than
a third, of Vietnamese or Algerians in metropolitan units already represents
a half-surrender. The government can no longer trust heterogeneous con¬
tingents whose officers alone are recruited from the imperial population. The
command accepts a loss of effectiveness, accommodates itself in advance to
the anticipated desertions. The method is dangerous: in case of a reverse, the
number of desertions rises steeply (as was discovered in Indo-China, after
Dien-Bien-Phu).
Is the imperial capacity to mobilize subject populations a function of the
numerical relation between the latter and the imperial population? Number,
226
SOCIOLOGY
in this crude form, does not decide the fate of empires. If such were the
case, the British Empire would never have existed. But the British Empire
is, in many respects, exceptional. That a people numerically so inferior could
rule so many territories, so many millions of men without even submitting
to the demands of obligatory military service, that the sailors, the subjects,
and relatively few professionals could maintain the Empire was a miracle
requiring abnormal circumstances as well as political genius. This empire, if
it was one of the largest history has ever known, was also, in the scale of
centuries, one of the briefest. England ruled from afar by the intermediary
of her Indian Empire. It was difficult to transform India into a modern state
in military and administrative terms without provoking national claims. Ulti¬
mately, the relation between conquerors and conquered develops either to¬
ward integration into a single community or dissociation into two distinct
collectivities. In one way or another the strictly military inequality is forgotten
or effaced. Equality tends to be re-established either by enlarging imperial
citizenshipP^or by the autonomy or independence of the non-national pop¬
ulations. The British were numerically too inferior, too conscious of their
race, possessed lands too remote and governed populations too heterogeneous
to envisage another conclusion than the disintegration of the Empire into
many totally sovereign political units (despite a Commonwealth which, in
the eyes of the non-British, seems increasingly fictitious).
The numerical disproportion within the French Empire between imperial
and non-French populations was less extreme, yet could not produce another
result. Integration, another name for assimilationpll requires that citizenship,
whether Roman or French, be offered to the subject peoples. It raises the
latter to the dignity of citizens, but it condemns them to competing for posts
with the citizens bom in Rome or in France.
The nature of modem economy renders difficult an imperial policy of in¬
tegration which does not tolerate too great a disparity in the standard of living
between parts of the same whole (particularly when men themselves have
neither the same language nor customs). But, aside from these reasons of an
economic orderjUl citizenship satisfies the non-national populations only on
two conditions: it must be desired and received as an honor, and it must
offer more opportunities than it retracts. Even in 1936, full French citizen¬
ship would have been regarded by the Algerians as an honor. In i960 it was
ElThe inequality may exist between citizens and non-citizens or, within the single
community, between castes whose origin and hierarchy date back to the conquest.
Within political units the social inequalities may be, in part, the crystallization of the
relations of military forces.
UlThe integration of non-national populations in a metropolitan political unit does not
imply the suppression of particularities of language, religion and customs, which as¬
similation seems to suggest. But these two words imply the uniformity of political
citizenship.
[HlWhich we shall study in the next chapter.
ON NUMBER
227
an honor no longer. How many Algerians, in a French Algeria, competing
with those of French stock, could raise themselves to that society’s highest
positions?
The disintegration of the French Empire, which various events precipi¬
tated, was the logical conclusion of conquests which the stagnation of the
French population rendered precarious from the start. France could arm the
soldiers recruited among the non-French populations; she could not grant
French citizenship to the populations themselves, universally and without
reservations. She was unwilling to grant that citizenship as long as it was
desired. She offered it in vain the day the elites of the formerly subject
peoples aspired to the responsibilities and advantages of state sovereignty.
We must observe, with the insight afforded by the knowledge of a future
which is now the past, that the hope (cherished by several authors of the last
century) of compensating the relative decline of French population by Afri¬
can conquests was illusory. If the declining birth rate had been ascribable
to lack of space, the annexation of Algeria would have sufficed to bring this
deplored development to an end. But was it enough that Frenchmen should
consent to cross the Mediterranean for their fertility to become again what it
had been in centuries past and that their children should survive, as in Can¬
ada? In French Algeria it was not the European minority but the Moslem
majority that multiplied. The French Empire in the Mediterranean, of which
Prevost-Paradol dreamed and in which he saw the supreme hope that France,
in a universe dominated by the Anglo-Saxons, would avoid a fate comparable
to that of Athens in the Roman Empire, disintegrated because it was popu¬
lated not by citizens but by subjects. We may remark, with a certain sadness,
that the conclusion is more in accord with the laws of history than the en¬
terprise itself; a nation with a dwindling population has little likelihood of
preserving an empire, even when it finds an occasion to build one.
The fact that colonization temporarily reinforced the power of metropolitan
France does not mean that decolonization is always a cause of diminution. It
is false, in fact, to compare what the independence of the colonies or pro¬
tectorates costs the metropolitan country with the profit it derives from these
same territories and populations when it exercises a peaceful authority there.
In Africa, for instance, France obviously loses military bases, a potential
source of soldiers, a vast zone of sovereignty, which afforded both prestige
and means of action. But we must compare the cost of a rejected decoloniza¬
tion with that of a decolonization accepted in time. Would France have been
more powerful between 1946 and 1954 without the Indo-Chinese War?
Would she be more powerful today had she come to terms with Ho Chi
Minh in 1946 or in 1947? Was she reinforced or weakened by the Algerian
conflict? In 1840 Marshal Bugeaud considered that the maintenance of some
hundred thousand soldiers on the other side of the Mediterranean weakened
France on the principal terrain, i.e., the Rhine frontier. The same question
could have been asked in i960.
228
SOCIOLOGY
In other words, empires are a source of strength as long as they are cheaply
held. In 1961 there were as many soldiers in Algeria as there were adult
Europeans to protect. Bugeaud’s colons, instead of guaranteeing French
peace, cannot remain among the Moslem masses except when each is flanked
by an armed man from metropolitan France. When an empire requires more
troops than it furnishes, what is the most rational policy, by realistic calcula¬
tion: abandonment or resistance^!
French defeatism, nourished in the mid-nineteenth century by little else
other than the relative decline in the population, was aggravated, in the
twentieth, by the relative slowness of economic growth and by the theory that
paired demographic with economic stagnation. States would be doubly weak¬
ened if their populations were stationary or decreasing: they would possess
fewer soldiers and fewer workers; the labor output or, if one prefers, the per
capita income would be less or would rise less quickly than in nations with
high birth rates.
To deal with this problem completely, we should have to envisage it
from two points of view: WTat is the influence of the demographic movement
on the economic movement? What, inversely, is the influence of the latter
on the former? We shall say only a word concerning this second question.
The demographers are far from agreed as to the facts and their interpretations,
even when they confine themselves to recent centuriesP^ Some believe that
the increase in the number of men, from the sixteenth or seventeenth century,
has been relatively independent, since we observe it even on the continents
which exhibit little or no economic advance. The population of China be¬
tween 1650 and 1930 rose, according to some, from 70 to 340 million, accord¬
ing to others, from 150 to 450 million. If the demographic movement, in
certain cases, does not seem subordinate to the increase of resources (improve¬
ment of production techniques, commercial organization, security, etc.),^
must we attribute it to the changing vitality of populations? Or does the ap¬
parently biological formula of vitality conceal many complex phenomena of
a social order?
With regard to the contrary influence—of the number of men on the
volume of resources—everything depends, of course, on the elasticity of re¬
sources (which varies according to the period) and the density of the exist¬
ing population. We might posit constant technical means (as Montesquieu im-
plicity does): the elasticity of resources, and hence of the number of men,
will be a function of social causes such as public order, distribution of
IH The numerical relation between the metropolitan troops needed to build the empire
and the contingents raised within the empire depends on the numerical relation on
the battlefield between regular troops and rebels. This question is discussed below.
ISSJCf. E. F. Wagemann, Menschenzahl und Volkerschicksal, Lehre von den optimalen
Dimensionen Gesellschaftlicher Gebilde, Hamburg, 1948.
ESlThe introduction of the potato, according to William Langer, was the principal
cause of the European and Asian population increase in the seventeenth century.
ON NUMBER
229
property, balance of foreign trade, importance of arts or industry. It would
occur to no one, today, to posit constant technical means. Indeed the danger
is the converse one. Analysis posits as a possible population the one which
could live by the application of known techniques, and not the one defined
as a function of the technique which the population under consideration is
actually capable of putting into effect.
Abstractly, the economic-demographic potential, like the military poten¬
tial, depends on three variables: space, tools, capacity for collective action
(for production or combat). Traditionally, analysis aimed chiefly at determin¬
ing at what point the curve of average individual production reversed its
direction. Whatever the technical level, a certain population volume is neces¬
sary to exploit a territory, to profit from the division of labor, from the addi¬
tion made to individual productivity by the productive force bom of coopera¬
tion. The welfare optimum occurs at the point where the law of decreasing
returns begins to function, that is, when the productivity of the additional
worker becomes inferior to the average productivity. It is easy to conceive of a
plurality of points of welfare optimum in terms of the social organization
and technological means. Technological and economic progress is defined
precisely by the fact that it displaces the point where the curve of average
productivity (relation between total production and number of workers)
changes direction. The welfare optimum differs from the power optimum,
if we agree that power is measured by the material and human resources
the state possesses to achieve its external goals. The additional worker who
produces less than average, beyond the point of optimum welfare, produces
still more than the minimum indispensable for subsistence. The state is in
a position to take a share of this production from the additional worker.
The average revenue decreases, the state’s resources increase.
These theoretical definitions, which we borrow from Alfred SauvypS
illuminate an idea which is treated by most authors in this realm. Given
a technology and a social organization, the preoccupation with political-mili¬
tary power often inspires the desire for a population size superior to that
which the mere consideration of welfare would suggest. The "dominant”
minority wants as many subjects as possible, not only to recruit soldiers
but to levy taxes with which they will maintain state and armies.
In our period, the absolute figures of economic growth, the statistics of
the national product—gross or net—simultaneously include the results of the
increase in the number of men and the results of individual productivity. A
population which grows rapidly may have a national product which also
increases rapidly without any consequent improvement in individual pro¬
ductivity. On the other hand, a static population is capable of economic
growth insofar as the average productivity increases either because the worker
produces more at the same job or because workers shift frrom jobs with low
\Mirheorie generate la population, 2 vols., Paris, 1952 and 1954.
230
SOCIOLOGY
productivity to jobs with high productivity. The relation, which French ex¬
perience has at least made likely, would be as follows: the slowing down of
increase in the number of men would contribute (sometimes? often? always?)
to slackening the increase in productivity. In an industrial age, military
strength depends as much on labor productivity as on the number of men
(the higher the productivity, the greater the margin of resources, above
the subsistence level, of which the state can take a share). The demo¬
graphic decline, in this hypothesis, would doubly involve a political-military
decline: by the diminution or at least slackened augmentation of the human
as well as the economic potential.
There is no doubt that the French national product, between 1850 and
1913, increased less than that of Germany. The former, according to the
figures of Colin Clarlc^ shifted, between these two dates, from 16.6 to 36
billion francs, the latter, from 10.6 to 50 billion marks. In the first case it
slightly more than doubled, in the second it almost quintupled. The disparity
is less if we eliminate the influence of number and consider the real product
per employed person. The latter, in France, shifts from 426 in 1850-59 to
627 in 1911 (in international units), in Germany from 406 to 930.
Theoretically, a low birth rate creates circumstances favorable to growth.
A family with only two children has greater possibilities for savings. The
collectivity has fewer investments to make for the education of the younger
generation, and is in a position to invest more for each employed worker.
But, in the case of the French, other causes have been of more importance.
Growth is not determined by specifically economic causes alone, or at least
the latter (volume of savings, encouragement to invest, etc.) are in turn
controlled by attitudes adopted by the economic subjects (entrepreneurs, the
state). It is conceivable that demographic stagnation encourages attitudes un¬
favorable to growth.
That this was the case, in France, in the nineteenth century and in the
first half of the twentieth, statistics do not permit us to doubt. But the
precise action of demographic stagnation on the conservative attitude of the
bourgeoisie or of the French state is not easily isolated. Neither the leg¬
islation nor the ideology of French society was oriented toward growth.
That demographic stagnation permitted conservatism cannot be disputed. That
it made conservatism inevitable cannot be ascertained. That in the absence of
demographic growth, nations are doomed to a rate of little or no economic
growth has not been proved.
At present the phenomena of expansion are better known than they once
were. The authorities responsible, in a planned regime, have the means of
determining the increase in investment, which of itself determines, to a
degree, the rate of expansion. Even in a regime of the Western type, the state
H 3 Conditions of Economic Progress, 2nd edition, London, 1951.
ON NUMBER
23 1
has means of intervening to correct, whether rising or falling Cmore naturally
when rising), the rate of expansion which results when the mechanism is
left to itself or from the spontaneous behavior of the economic subjects.
In France, where the population was stagnant and the knowledge of the
economic phenomena inadequate, expansion was relatively rapid between
1900 and 1910, again between 1920 and 1929. The 1930—39 depression
can be attributed to circumstances. Certainly the Japanese and German eco¬
nomic "miracles” after World War II do not gainsay the lesson of the French
experience. The return to the Japanese islands of some seven million men
after the defeat, and of more than ten million men to Federal Germany,
created a population pressure which constituted the equivalent of a high
birth rate. Yet, no one dares assert that economic expansion will necessarily
slacken once the generations replace each other without numerically increas¬
ing. The graph of the number of men, the graph of the average productivity
are not independent of each other, but they are not linked to each other by
the direct and unconditional causality of numerical increase over that of pro¬
ductivity.
Are the fears of the French, which started in the middle of the last
century, now spreading to the West as a whole? Lately, France has advanced
less rapidly than her rivals in the Old World. Are the Western powers, taken
as a whole, being outstripped in the race for numerical superiority? Before
answering this last question, I should like to discuss the so-called demographic
theory of wars, according to which societies fight in order to eliminate the
surplus of men, this elimination being indispensable.
4. Overpopulation and War
One fact is evident, incontestable: war consists in killing men, or if a
more neutral formula is preferred, war has as its constant result the death
of men. The hunter kills animals, the warrior kills his own kind. A first
version of the theory we are examining is afforded by the shift from the
constant effect to that of function. Since every war reduces the number
of living men, may we not say that numerical reduction is the social function
of this singular pheomenon that is simultaneously social and antisocial? Then
we can formulate another version of the same theory: if war kills, it is
because there are too many men alive. All societies have waged war: if there
is no other datum than the surplus of men which appears down through
the ages with the same regularity as war, must we not conclude that the
general cause of the phenomenon of war is quite simply this surplus of
menpl]
The shift from constant effect to function seems to me, for methodological
Eil n France it is Gaston Bouthoul who has most forcefully presented the so-called
demographic theory of war. We refer the reader to his principal work, Les Guerres.
Elements de polemologie, Paris, 1951.
SOCIOLOGY
232
reasons, either problematical or else meaningless. To assert that a constant
effect reveals the goal of the phenomenon under consideration implies a
teleological mode of interpretation of a rather crude type. The common
character of all wars does not necessarily express the essence of armed con¬
flicts. The death of men can be the inevitable accompaniment of other ef¬
fects or other functions of wars, the reinforcement of existing collectivities
or the constitution of new collectivities.
The numerical reduction of the living is not the only result of armed
conflicts between political units. Such conflicts always have an effect on the
units: either they consolidate their inner coherence and their separation in
relation to others, or else they create a new unit which absorbs the belligerent
units. If we observe states and their wars statically, we are inclined to see
the latter as a rupture of the social links—as Sorokin says, an example of
anomie. If we consider wars down through history, we cannot fail to see in
them an elasticity of movement, more precisely, of the progressive widening of
the zones of sovereignty, hence of the zones of peace.
Let us add Anally that wars are not always bloody; they far from effectively
fulfill, in every circumstance, the function attributed to them. Epidemics
annihilate with far more rapidity. Even in Europe, after the Great War of
1914-18, Spanish influenza cut down about as many men as the machine
gun had in four years. The rites or regulations which preside over combats
often have the effect of reducing losses—that is to say cost, the concern of
the moralist, effectiveness of methods, that of the sociologist, who believes
that the function of war is to provoke a “demographic relaxation.”
Let us now consider not the function but the cause, first repeating the
same reasoning: the surplus of the living (whatever the manner in which
this surplus is evaluated) is not the only phenomenon which we observe as
regularly as war. The division of humanity into politically distinct units is
also present wherever the phenomenon of war occurs. To reason that the
final cause of war is the phenomenon which always precedes or accompanies
it does not seem to me to he valid: it implies, in effect, that all wars belong
to the same species. But even if we regard this reasoning as valid, it does not
conform to the so-called demographic theory. There is, in fact, at least one
social phenomenon that occurs throughout the history of civilizations as
regularly as the surplus of men: namely, the plurality of collectivities, political
units being the expression, in the form of military sovereignty, of the plurality
of social entities, one might almost say of social humanities.
Going beyond these generalities, how may we demonstrate or refute the
thesis which maintains that overpopulation is the cause of war, of the pro¬
pensity of autonomous collectivities to fight each other? Since the “method of
presence” does not afford the desired proof, the cause envisaged not being
the only one regularly present whenever the phenomenon to be explained ap¬
pears, we might turn to the "method of absence.” When overpopulation is
eliminated, do collectivities cease to wage war? Unfortunately, for humanity
ON NUMBER
233
as a whole, this is only an intellectual experiment, for, according to the very
theory we are discussing, overpopulation is endemic.
Partial experiments have been made by history: Does a bellicose nation
become peaceful when the population pressure diminishes? Did imperialist
France of the Revolution and the Empire become peaceful in the nineteenth
century with the lowering of the birth rate? Did romantic Germany become
imperialist as the number of Germans—of young Germans—increased? Let us
note first of all that France, supposedly converted to pacifism, certainly fought
no fewer wars in the last century than during the preceding ones. She has
fought more in the twentieth century. That Germany has replaced France
as “troublemaker” is incontestable, but proves nothing more than a kind of
imbecile truism: the state which appears to threaten the freedom of others
is, in every period, the one whose strength increases fastest. In 1850 France
was no longer the “troublemaker” of the European system, just as the Bonn
Republic, in 1950, was no longer the troublemaker of the global system. Do
the sentiments of men automatically conform to their diplomatic role? This
is highly doubtful. Outbursts of aggressive chauvinism have been frequent
in France during the last century. Japan after 1945, confined to her islands
with a higher population density than in 1938, is as peaceful, even anti¬
militarist, as it was imperialist twenty years ago.
To transcend the oscillation between a vague and a likely proposition-
war, which results in the death of men, must be linked to the facts of demog¬
raphy—and precise and unproved propositions, we must first of all define more
rigorously the phenomenon to which we impute a causal action: overpopula¬
tion or population pressure. It goes without saying that the number of men
does not adequately measure the population pressure. In the eighteenth cen¬
tury France would have been overpopulated by forty million people, today
it is underpopulated by the same number. Two centuries ago a figure of
forty-five million would have been above the welfare optimum and the power
optimum; today it is certainly inferior to the second, and in all probability to
the first.
Overpopulation, in a given space, is defined in relation to resources, them¬
selves a function of technological means. But if it is absurd to evaluate
population pressure by population figures alone, it would not be any more
rational to measure it by referring to the number of men capable of living
in that space if they used all the methods that science and industry afford.
By this second method we would arrive at Sauvy’s conclusion, according
to which only Holland experiences absolute overpopulation!!: the number
of people in that country would involve a diminution of per capita income,
even using the most advanced methods of production. We must further add
“diminution of average income in relation to welfare optimum,” that is, in
[^Moreover, according to Sauvy ( [Population , July i960), the per capita income, in
Holland, continues to increase faster than in the nations of stagnant population.
234
SOCIOLOGY
relation to the income each man might enjoy if there were fewer men. This
diminution in relation to a theoretical optimum does not involve an actual
diminution: quite the contrary, in the case of Holland, total expansion con¬
tinues, the per capita production increases. It is the statistician who decrees
that this production would increase faster if it were not for the law of dimin¬
ishing returns—if the investments necessary to win an additional area of
cultivable land from the sea did not also increase with the rise in population.
In other words, in order to define the notion of overpopulation we must
simultaneously consider space, means of production and social organization.
When the geologists or biologists tell us that eight or ten billion human
beings could live in comfort on the planet today, provided they applied the
knowledge that they have acquired, they are telling us something about sci¬
ence but little about society. The volume of the world harvest of tea or rice
which would result from the diffusion of the Japanese methods is interesting
in itself. It indicates the margins still available to growth, but leaves us in
complete ignorance as to overpopulation as a social fact and the eventual
influence of this fact on the frequency or intensity of wars.
Must we no longer define overpopulation in static but in dynamic terms,
assuming overpopulation to exist when the number curve rises faster than
that of resources? 3 * Such a definition would be satisfactory if each society
were homogeneous, if all societies were of the same kind. In the past, dis¬
tribution of income has sometimes been such that the misery of the masses
rose with their numerical increase (lowering of wages), while the wealth
of the privileged also increased. Do we speak of overpopulation in this case?
It is a question, it seems to me, of overpopulation if the latter is characterized
by “the impoverishment of the great number” (that is, the impoverishment of
the people because the people become increasingly numerous). Yet the com¬
parison of the graph of number and that of resources would not confirm
overpopulation, according to the preceding definition. Further, the rapid in¬
crease of number, the accumulation of young men, a typical European
phenomenon in the nineteenth century, one which Bouthoul considers char¬
acteristic of an explosive situation, is not contained within the concept of
overpopulation as defined by the comparison between the graph of number
and the graph of resources. The European population increased in the nine¬
teenth century more than in any other, though millions of men, as we have
seen, emigrated. The increase in the number of men remaining on the soil
of the Old World was considerable without the graph of number ever rising
faster than that of resources. The German per capita income continued to
increase until 1914: hence there was no overpopulation, in the strict sense
of the term. Were the Germans warlike out of simple biological vitality?
I myself had envisaged another definition: might we not say that there
is a surplus of men once a certain number among them, idle by constraint,
E3Cfi G. Bouthoul, of. cit.
ON NUMBER
23 ?
as a result of social circumstances, are available for tbe profession of arms,
because their elimination would not bring about a decrease of production? I
must conclude, upon reflection, that the phenomenon thus defined, which I
shall henceforth call surplus of men, is too frequent to permit a study of all
the relations between number and belligerence. The ancient societies had a
permanent “surplus of men” of this land. The very notion refers to a society
in which labor is regarded as a primary activity, and combat as a kind of
luxury: the opposite being the case for the citizens of the Greek city-states.
The obvious fact that labor was necessary to insure existence was not over¬
looked, but it was to politics and war that the citizen devoted himself. In the
European societies which did not know slavery and in which only the nobles
had the duty of risking their lives in combat, the rigidity of the social
organization, even more than the stagnation of technology, created, in an
endemic fashion, a surplus of men. The armies seemed all the more normal
in that they mobilized those idle by vocation (the nobles) or by servitude
(the unemployed or the vagabonds). The death of the former was regarded
as glorious—a state privilege—of the rest, as indifferent. The democratic age
and the civilization of labor rejected, in principle, these two categories of the
idle.
Surpluses of men have not disappeared with modem society. Agricultural
overpopulation, so frequent in the underdeveloped nations, is a phenomenon
of the same order. Until we succeed in mobilizing for labor the “useless
hands” (as Communist China claims to have done), the majority of the
world’s agricultural regions will count a surplus of men, since production
would not be diminished in the case of the sudden elimination of a part
of the rural population. Historians noted that even in France, when she was
in the process of modernizing herself during the last century, great numbers
of men were idle on account of the slowness of industrialization and the
rigidity of the social stmcture. To explain by the pressure of the unemployed
the wars with Spain, Algeria, Italy or Mexico would be absurd. To explain
by this fact the government’s propensity to wage these wars and the indif¬
ference with which public opinion receives them would be impossible.
Three population phenomena, distinct though related, can be connected
with the propensity to wage war: surplus of men, overpopulation (global or
partial), biological vitality. None of these can be called, in a general or
dogmatic way, the cause of wars or of warlike propensity (moreover a causal
relation presupposes that all other things are equal; in this case all other things
cannot be equal). But each of them has certain links with war, though
these links are difficult to determine. Surplus of men, in the most general
sense of the term, is an endemic phenomenon in all human societies whose
technology is virtually stationary and whose organization is crystallized. What
R l call partial overpopulation the gap between the curve of number and the curve
of resources for a fraction, and not for the whole, of a population.
SOCIOLOGY
236
is called the historical phase is characterized by two so-to-speak negative
features: numerical equilibrium is not maintained by a quasi-natural mecha¬
nism, as in the small, closed and archaic collectivities^, the capacity for
initiative, innovation, technological or social adaptation is still weak (not in
itself, but in relation to the problems raised). Men of no use to production
have of necessity almost always existed. Since, at the same time, conquest,
exploitation of the conquered, and pillage constitute sources of enrichment,
the transformation of the idle into combatants, who when victorious bring
back spoils, is strictly rational. Even if these collectivities had thought in
economic terms, they would not have been wrong to set the combatant above
the laborer. Not only did the former protect the latter’s life, but quite often
he produced more. In the last century the hierarchy of values was quite
different: the economic productivity of wars (particularly the wars waged by
Napoleon III in Italy or Mexico) could no longer be compared to that of
labor. Only the officers somewhat retained the ancient prestige of heroes. I
do not mean that the wars would cease if the surplus of men were eliminated,
nor that the wars were determined in their frequency and intensity by the
number of idle men. I simply regard the “surplus of men” as a concomitant
phenomenon of the phenomenon of war which helps make the latter intelligi¬
ble. Most societies possessed economically unemployed men who, under arms,
■produced glory or rapine.
Global or partial overpopulation is tantamount to the accentuation of the
preceding phenomenon. Under certain circumstances the number of unem¬
ployed in rural areas exceeds the norm. The poor, the homeless, the non-
integrated grow more numerous. Competition for jobs causes wages to be
lowered, even if the worker’s productivity is stationary or increasing. Neither
experience nor abstract analysis suggests that such a situation necessarily
provokes wars or that wars are generally the expression of such a circumstance.
Disease eliminates the non-integrated as well as the machine gun. The abun¬
dance of manpower tends rather to weaken the claims of the non-privileged.
Certain historians, it is true, explain the fluctuation of Chinese history by
the fluctuations of number. Even in this hypothesis, overpopulation would be
at the source of internal difficulties, revolts, conspiracies, dynastic changes,
rather than of wars between sovereign units.
With regard to European history, demographers note a certain population
increase from the tenth century to the thirteenth, a falling off in the four¬
teenth century after the plague, a stagnation in the fifteenth century, a sub¬
stantial increase in Central Europe in the sixteenth century, a stagnation or
falling off in Central Europe in the seventeenth century, an important and
general increase in the eighteenth century, a tumultuous increase in the
iMlHere, too, equilibrium is not maintained constantly in fact. Certain collectivities
contract, others expand. There are societies without writing, there are none without
changes. Yet these societies are not historical for themselves.
ON NUMBER
2 37
nineteenth century. Now the period that followed the plague should have
been less bellicose, and the three periods of wars—the Crusades, the Thirty
Years’ War, and the wars of the twentieth century—should have been pre¬
ceded by phases of demographic growth. It is possible that a massive diminu¬
tion of the population attenuates the violence of the conflict, but, of the
three examples, the first two do not exemplify the thesis. It is difficult to
measure the intensity of war in the Middle Ages, for it varies with the cen¬
turies. The shift from number to the true impulse of the Crusades remains,
at the least, obscure. As for the third example, that of Europe in the twentieth
century, it brings us to our third phenomenon, biological vitality.
In effect, we have said, neither Germany nor Europe suffered in 1913 from
overpopulation. The ideology of the people without space (Volk ohne Rawin')
had not yet become common. The Reich’s leaders and its public opinion
knew that total wealth was increasing faster than the number of men. If
demographic growth was the cause of German imperialism, a cause of the
wars in which the European civilization collapsed, we must seek the essential
facts not in mere numbers or comparisons of graphs, but in the unconscious
or the obscure life of collectivities.
Germany and Europe had no need to lose tens of millions of men in
order to assure their survivors a higher standard of living. No nation had
exceeded the welfare optimum. None could even suppose it was staggering
under the burden of quantity. In Germany as in every nadon with a high
birth rate, young men were proportionally more numerous than in the coun¬
tries where the birth rate permits no more than the replacement of one gen¬
eration by the next. The potential supply of combatants might have inspired
the leaders’ ambitions; it could not inspire their anxiety for themselves and
their regime. If the European wars of the twentieth century have had a func¬
tion of “demographic relaxation,” to borrow M. Bouthoul’s formula, it is be¬
cause the numerical pressure which creates the fury of combat is not created
by either population density or collective impoverishment, but by a kind of
vital exuberance, comparable to that which sweeps into fights or games those
youths whose blood is too hot for their veins. We do not know enough
about the laws which control the development of collectivities to exclude
the hypothesis of a link between fertility and aggressiveness. Still, we can
assert with certainty that this relation is not always to be found and that, in
the case where we suppose we perceive it, other explanations come to mind.
The very author regarded as the theoretician of the explanation of wars
by number, explicitly states: “Overpopulation does not necessarily lead to
foreign or civil war. ’fell Overpopulation, he says, calls into being institutions
which result in the elimination of men, war being only one of these institu¬
tions among others. Such a formula is obvious, but not instructive. It is
equivalent to the proposition that in a given space, with given resources, only
MiG. Boutfioul, Of. tit., pp. 323-24.
SOCIOLOGY
238
a certain number of men survives. Since this number constantly tends to be
exceeded, social mechanisms eliminate the surplus.
On several occasions in the past the Japanese have taken deliberate and
systematic measures to prevent the surplus from appearing at all. Aside from
this rare practice, mortality by epidemics, hunger and labor conditions have
regularly eliminated the surplus. Are we to regard war as a complement of or
a substitute for elimination by delayed marriages, infanticide or the deliberate
and organized special mortality of the young? That wars kill and, especially
in the modern period, kill the young, I grant. That we can compare and
contrast the “Asiatic solution” (high mortality as a result of labor conditions)
and the European solution (relaxation by periodic wars), I do not believe.
Until the last century the “European solution” did not differ by nature from
the Asiatic one: diseases and high mortality rate among the young per¬
formed, in the main, the function of eliminating idle hands. In the last
century the function was no longer performed under the same conditions in
Europe. But demographic growth did not bring with it an absolute surplus
(in relation to the subsistence volume) nor even a relative surplus (in relation
to the welfare optimum). If it made Germany imperialist and the Europeans
bellicose, contrary to economic rationality and without necessity, we should
have to conclude that fertility, the accumulation of young people, in certain
unspecified circumstances, impelled peoples, leaders and public opinion to
wage war. But if the “explosive situation” incites to imperialism, centuries
of experience remind us that neither Caesars nor peoples have required this
incitement to feed ambition and to believe in their vocation as rulers.
5. From Petroleum to the Atom and Electronics
The historical period that begins in 1945 differs profoundly, with regard
to the operation of numbers, from both the preceding decades and from the
centuries of European expansion.
In modem times, Europeans have benefited from a unique combination
of circumstances. The empty spaces of North America were open to them.
Between 1840 and 1940 fifty-six million of them left the Old World, thirty-
seven million for the United States. At the same time, thanks to the superiority
of their means of production and combat, they imposed their rule upon Africa
and Asia; they were both rich and powerful, as though to prove once and for
all that the so-called alternative of welfare and glory was an anachronism.
The peopling of empty space, the extension of the zone of sovereignty was
succeeded, after 1945, by the dissociation from the empires the Europeans had
built in Asia and Africa. The “European minorities” left the nations that
had become independent and flowed back to the metropolitan countries. It
was the non-Europeans’ turn to possess the machines with which the little
Asian cape has ruled the world. Since the populations of the so-called under¬
developed nations have an average birth rate superior to that of the eco¬
nomically advanced nations, it is easy to spread through Western Europe,
ON NUMBER
239
through the entire West, the fear of being overwhelmed by numbers which
have inspired the French, since 1850, to so many gloomy speculations.
Let us recall, first of all, that in 1700 the Europeans represented about a
fifth of the human race (118 million out of 560 million). In 1900 they
represented a fourth (400 million out of 1,608,000,000). On the eve of the
last world war they still represented approximately a fourth. Were this per¬
centage to diminish and fall from a fourth to a fifth, the decline would
still be no more than a return to a numerical relation which already existed
scarcely three centuries ago.
Moreover the European-non-European relation means little enough, since
the Europeans are divided into two hostile blocs, one of which feels (or acts
as if it felt) allied with the revolt of the colored peoples against white
domination, the other linked both militarily and morally with the United
States. Now the comparison of the rates of demographic increase on either side
of the Iron Curtain does not justify the defeatism of those who are obsessed
by numbers. It is probable that the population of the United States is increas¬
ing today as fast as that of the Soviet Union (the annual rate of increase in
the United States has been approximately 1.5 per cent during the last few
years). The rate of increase in the Western part of the Old World is lower
than that on the other side of the Iron Curtain. But the new advance in the
birth rate in France and Great Britain, which were particularly threatened
by depopulation, as well as the tendency to a decline in the birth rate in the
industrializing nations of Eastern Europe, make it impossible to find this
inequality in growth a disturbing characteristic.
Suppose we consider the comparative rates of increase in the United States
and in Latin America, taken as characteristic of industrialized nations on one
hand and of nations in the process of development on the other. There
is no doubt that the rise is more rapid in the latter countries. Between 1940
and 1950 Brazil’s population increased at the annual rate of 2.7 per cent,
Mexico’s at the annual rate of 3.1 per cent. In thirty years the population
of Latin America, on an average hypothesis with regard to birth rate, will
double. It will probably exceed, between now T and the end of this century,
the population of English-speaking America, but such fluctuations of nu¬
merical relations are not directly dangerous for the peoples that multiply less
rapidly and grow rich faster.
The peoples whose per capita income is relatively low, whose farmers are
unacquainted with modem methods of agriculture, and whose industry em¬
ploys only a relatively low percentage of the manpower have a tendency, in
our period, to “increase and multiply.” Let us concede the fact, which is
explained, generally speaking, by the maintenance of a traditional birth rate
and the diminution of mortality, this diminution being the consequence of
an improved hygiene (an improvement which no longer implies a substantial
increase of resources). The rapid numerical increase tends to weaken the new
24 °
SOCIOLOGY
states rather than to reinforce them: it weakens them economically as well as
politically.
The abundance of young men, which Bouthoul considers an incitement
to war, serves the cause of the nationalists who are eager to drive out the
colonists. Ho Chi Minh, before the Indo-Chinese War began, might have
said to a French interlocutor: “You will kill ten of our men for every French
soldier that we will kill. But in the long run, we will be the winners.” In i960
half the Algerian population was under twenty, and all these Algerian young
people were nationalists. Once independence is acquired, however, the situa¬
tion is reversed and what had been an effective weapon in the struggle against
the colonizing power becomes a source of weakness in the struggle against
poverty. As long as the cumulative process of economic expansion has not
been set moving, the investment indispensable to the education of the young
has to be subtracted from investment for raising the productivity of adult
labor. The taxes which the state levies for its diplomatic and military pur¬
poses curtail either the share of national revenue reserved for consumption
or the share set aside for investments. Except for the pitiless regime, military
expenses compete with these investments. India would have greater diplo¬
matic possibilities today if her birth rate were cut by half.
Such a proposition does not contradict the lessons of French experience.
Once a nation has created the administrative and intellectual infrastructure
which modernization of the economy demands, the maintenance of a rela¬
tively high birth rate (or, barring this, the immigration of foreign labor) has
shown itself to be favorable to the increase of productivity or of the per
capita income. Even in the course of the ten years 1950—60, production per
active person has increased 5.6 per cent per year in Japan, where, in ten years,
manpower has increased 37 per cent; 5.8 per cent in Federal Germany, where
manpower has increased 28 per cent; 4.4 per cent in the Low Countries,
where manpower has increased 15 per cent; 4.4 per cent in Italy, where
manpower has increased 14 per cent. The corresponding percentages are 2.6
and 8 for the United States, 1.9 and 4 for Norway, 2.2 and 4.5 for Great
Britain. At the level of development which the "Western nations have reached,
an increase of manpower, which facilitates transfers from job to job and
maintains the creative impulse and the conviction of a future, seems then, for
the moment, favorable not only to the increase of the national product (which
follows as a matter of course), but also of per capita productivity. This is not
true for the Asian or Latin American countries nor for rates of demographic
increase exceeding 2 per cent. If overrapid numerical increase constitutes a
danger to the West, it is because of revolutions and authoritarian regimes
which could result from the poverty of the too-numerous masses, the
increase of idle hands.
Yet we must not underestimate the present relations between population
volume and military strength, between military strength and diplomatic power.
The defensive or revolutionary power of high-birth-rate populations has be-
ON NUMBER
241
come irresistible. Partisans are incapable of defeating regular armies, but they
render maintenance of order costly and pacification impossible. Once the
prestige of the conquerors has vanished, the number of the colonized in¬
evitably overwhelms the superior equipment of the colonists, so that by a
strange paradox the latter are obliged to mobilize hundreds of thousands of
soldiers against several thousand guerrillas. Nine million Moslems against
one million Europeans, twenty thousand regular combatants in the army of
liberation against four hundred thousand French soldiers, losses in human
lives ten or twenty times higher among the Algerian nationalists than among
the French, expenses ten to twenty times higher on the French side. Had
they reflected on the meaning of these figures, statesmen would have had no
doubt as to the outcome.
Prolific and poor populations, impregnable on their own territory, are im¬
potent beyond it, for the concentration of economic resources necessary to
manufacture decisive weapons has advanced along with the destructive power
of the weapons themselves. It required the administrations of the European
monarchies to finance the mobilization of the armies of the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries. Only the states known as great powers were capable,
in the First and especially the Second World War, of furnishing millions of
men with scientific weapons—artillery, tanks, aviation. In the age of the atom
and of electronics, the club of the great powers is still smaller: only those
known as super-powers possess, for the moment, the thermonuclear arsenal
and the latest-model delivery vehicles, ballistic missiles and strategic bombers.
The influence of number is different, in our times, because the modes of
combat are many. The law of number functions differently in daily machine-
gun engagements and in a possible combat with weapons of mass destruction.
The Arabs are shaking off the yoke of the Western powers, but they are not
about to extend their cavalcades as far as Poitiers. The Western powers are not
being impoverished as their space of sovereignty shrinks: on the contrary,
they wall grow richer faster. The instability in the relations of force derives
in part from the numerous territories on which the competition between peo¬
ples takes place. It derives, too, from the rapidity with which different peoples
acquire the industrial weapons of power.
In the Greek world the great powers were based on ten to twenty thousand
citizens: it is easy to understand why the great powers did not last long and
why, from one century to the next, the virtu, as Machiavelli called it, shifted
from Athens to Thebes, or from Macedon to Rome. In the twentieth century
it takes only a few decades to create a heavy industry. In i960 the Soviet
Union produced more than twice as much steel as the great German Reich of
1939. And China will perhaps in one generation increase her steel production
by some twenty million tons, that is, by an amount exceeding the present
production of France. The superiority of certain nations in their industrial
career, which they owed in the first place to a head start, is shrinking and
tends to disappear as the industrial type of society becomes more widespread.
242
SOCIOLOGY
Relations of force depend on the relative number of men and the relative
number of machines: the latter has fluctuated in the last century even more
rapidly than the former.
Is it conceivable, beyond the phase of industrialization, and once every
nation has achieved a comparable productivity', that the relation may depend
exclusively on the number of men? Or, on the other hand, is it henceforth
the quality of machines that will be decisive? What can millions of assault
tanks do against one thermonuclear bomb? What could dozens of thermo¬
nuclear bombs do against a state possessing an invulnerable defense against
bombers and ballistic missiles? We shall not play the prophet, confining our¬
selves to observing that between rivals of the same order of greatness (or of
size), it is quality that is likely to gain the decision. What the tactical
capacity of the Roman legions did for the ancient world, a defense against
ballistic missiles could do for the Northern Hemisphere. But the scientists
have replaced the strategists.
chapter IX
On Resources
Space and number generally escape the awareness of the actors: gold, sil¬
ver, slaves, petroleum have been recognized, down through the ages, as the
stakes of conflicts between states. Historians and philosophers have not had to
discover that the collectivities in conflict thirsted for precious metals or raw
materials: they have more often had to correct cynicism than to unmask
hypocrisy. Men, they said, are also animated by the desire for glory or the
ambition to conquer. It is in our period that the so-called economic interpreta¬
tion pretends to originality. Since our civilization grants primacy to labor,
scientists and ideologists readily suppose that they are discovering profound
and mysterious forces when they explain the course of diplomatic history
by economic causes.
I have intentionally chosen the vaguest and most general term, resources,
in preference to the term economics. It is wise, indeed, to leave the latter
its precise and limited sense. By resources I mean the sum of material means
collectivities can use to assure their subsistence. Men comprise part of re¬
sources when they are slaves, in other words when they are treated as ob¬
jects. In all other cases, they are subjects of the activity by which things are
transformed into goods, that is, serve to satisfy men’s needs or desires. The
concept of resources covers the widest field, from the soil and what lies un¬
derneath it to food and manufactured products. It includes in a certain way
the realities to which the two notions of space and number refer. The relation
between space and number depends on resources, that is, on both the natural
milieu (or on material things) and on the capacity for utilization, a capacity
itself dependent on the knowledge of men and the efficacy of collective action.
The economic concept does not apply to an isolable fragment of the sum
of resources, but to an aspect of the activity by which things are transformed
into goods. Let us call labor the activity by which men act upon things in
order to use them. This activity involves a technological aspect and an
economic aspect. The first is logically reduced to the combination of means
244
SOCIOLOGY
with a view toward ends. Since the neolithic revolution, societies have been
able to cultivate the soil, inciting biological phenomena as a result of which
the fruits of the earth ripen and the human race increases and multiplies.
But since the dawn of history, the laboring activity has involved another
aspect, that of the choice of scarce means with alternative uses and, above
all, of the means that are scarce in essence: the time of each laborer and of
the laborers taken collectively. It is not impossible to distinguish technology
and economics at the lowest level, that of the individual worker. But con¬
sideration of the collectivity is preferable. The disparity between desires (at
least in essence) and possibilities of satisfying them is thus explicit, just as
the necessity of the choice to which any social existence is subject is also
made clear. A collectivity chooses a certain distribution of available labor
among various jobs, a certain distribution of goods among classes. We shift
from the distribution of labor to the distribution of incomes by the in¬
termediary of a mode of circidation. Every economic system, that is, the sum
of institutions by which needs are satisfied, involves three characteristics, de¬
pending on the systems of division of labor, of circulation of goods, of
distribution of incomes.
Hence, if we consider the relationship between resources and foreign pol¬
icy, it seems that we must distinguish three kinds of data likely to be causes:
raw materials, afforded by the natural milieu; knowledge and ‘‘know-how,’’
which permit the exploitation of these materials; and the mode of organiza¬
tion applied to the production and the circulation which determine the
economic system, that is, the manner in which the obligations of labor and
the incomes from the collective effort are distributed among individuals. It
appears that an exhaustive study should constitute types for each of these
aspects of the economic system, and determine the action of each one of
them upon the behavior and fortune of states. But such a method is likely to
lead to virtually endless research. Hence it seems preferable to me—and the
experiment will perhaps justify this simplification—to focus our analyses on
three problems, analogous to those treated in the preceding chapters: first of
all, resources as means of force, next resources as objectives of the belligerents,
stakes of rivalries, or causes of war. In conclusion we shall briefly compare
the influence of various systems of modem economy on the external behavior
of states.
The first theme suggests the classical questions: what is the relation be¬
tween prosperity, wealth and welfare on the one hand, and political or
military force on the other? The second brings us to the eternal question:
why do men fight? For gold or for glory? When do they fight for wealth and
when for the intoxication of conquest? Lastly, the third theme is oriented
toward the future: will labor and war be indefinitely complementary ac¬
tivities, or does a certain kind of labor make the elimination of war inevi¬
table or probable or desirable?
ON BESOUECES
245
1. Four Doctrines
Economists, historians and philosophers have for centuries discussed the
problems we have just formulated. But they have not discussed them sepa¬
rately. The answer given to one of these problems almost necessarily involves
the answer given to the other. Depending on the meaning the authors assign
to labor or trade, they regard wealth as fatal or favorable to the greatness of
peoples; commerce and war as one and the same, or not one and the same, in
essence; conflicts as either provoked or pacified by trade.
I shall therefore try to present four ideal types which I shall call mercantil¬
ism, liberalism, national economy and socialism. Historically, each of these
doctrines has been set forth in various ways. Composite or modified doctrines
are more frequent, as a matter of fact, than these pure ones. The following
summaries do not aim at reproducing the exact thought of any of the thinkers
connected with the four schools I have just listed. I am trying here to set
forth the logical framework of four intellectual structures.
The mercantilist doctrine of the relations between economy and inter¬
national relations has as its initial principle the celebrated formula "money
is the sinew of war.” Let us quote, among the many possible sources, the
following lines from Montchrestien’s Traite de Veconomie politique (1615):
“He who first said that money is the sinew of war spoke to the point, for
though money is not the only consideration, good soldiers being absolutely
necessary along with it, the experience of several centuries teaches us that it is
always the principal. Gold is many times more powerful than steel.’B The
inverse relation is asserted by Machiavelli in a celebrated text®
If precious metals are the sinews of war, they are also the measure of the
strength of nations, since in the last analysis strength is measurable by what
we call “trial by force.” The will to power is thus expressed logically by the
effort to amass the greatest possible amount of gold and silver. Now there
are two methods to achieve this end; one is war, the other commerce. Each
state increases its reserve of precious metals by plunder or by exchange.
But—and this is the second proposition which dominates mercantilist thought
—there is no difference in nature between these two methods. In depth, they
are of the same essence.
As ColbenH] says: “It is only the abundance of money in a state that
makes the difference as to its greatness and its power.” If this is the case,
how could commerce, on which depends the reserve of gold and silver, and
thus the power of states, not be a kind of war? “Commerce causes a perpetual
0 Paris, 1889, pp. 141-42. This Montcbrestien quotation and the Machiavelli
one following are from E. Silbemer, La Guerre dans la pensee economic du XVIe au
XVlIIe siecles, Paris, 1939. Another hook by this same author, La Guerre et la Paix
dans I’histoire des doctrines economiques, Paris, 1957, discusses the nineteenth century.
LflMachiavelli, Discourse on the First Decade of Titus Livius, II, 10.
[HLettres, instructions et memoires, Paris, 1862, t. II, l e partie, p. CCLXIX. Cited by
Silberner, op. cit., p. 261.
SOCIOLOGY
246
combat in peace and in war among the nations of Europe as to which will
gain the upper hand.®And further: “Commerce is a perpetual and peaceful
war of spirit and industry among all nations.’H] In the next century Dutot
(1738) develops the idea: "To make peace in order to procure for ourselves
all the advantages of a great commerce, is to wage war upon our enemies.®
Certain British authors echo the continental ones. They, too, refuse to
distinguish between commercial supremacy and political hegemony: “Who¬
ever Commands the ocean Commands the Trade of the World, and Who¬
ever Commands the Trade of the World Commands the Riches of the World,
and whoever is master of that, Commands the World itself.S Consequently,
“in no other way can the balance of power be maintained or continued but
by the balance of trade.®
The identification of trade with war derives from the following reason¬
ing: since a positive balance of trade is necessary in order to accumulate
precious metals, and since all the states cannot have a positive balance, trade
cannot be profitable to all. He who buys more than he sells loses gold and
silver, and is therefore ruined by the exchange or, we would say, loses in the
exchange. The race for precious metals creates a difference in nature between
foreign trade and domestic trade, since the latter does not modify the stock
of gold and silver and the former, on the contrary, determines its volume.
Even as late as the middle of the eighteenth century a French author expressly
formulates the thesis: “The true commerce of a nation consists essentially
in the course of exchanges which it makes with foreign nations. On the other
hand, exchanges which are made only between the subjects of one and the
same state are less a true commerce than a simple displacement of conve¬
niences which facilitates consumption but adds nothing to the total wealth
of a nation and in no way extends its advantages.®
The search for precious metals attaches an aggressive character to com¬
mercial expansion and foreign trade among nations, for the stock of gold
and silver is limited, as are the amount of possible exchanges. The mer¬
cantilists reason within a finite world, in a static universe. Exchange is not
favorable to the buyer as it is to the seller. But, according to the expression
of an Italian author, Botero: “The verycommon means of enriching oneself
at the expense of others is commerce.’® “We lose as much as the foreigner
gains.®-!
To depend as little as possible on foreign purveyors, to produce as much
Wtbid., t. VI, p. 266.
CO bid., t. VI, p. 269.
EjQuoted by Silbemer, p. 53. Dutot, Reflexions sur la commerce et les finances,
f Quoted by Silbemer, p. 106, note 57. John Evelyn, Navigation and Commerce, 1674.
aaQuoted by Silbemer, p. 106, note 60. The Golden Fleece, 1737.
ElQuoted by Silbemer, p. 109. Goyon de la Plombanie, La France agricole et mar-
chande, 1762.
IlSIQuoted by Silbemer, p. 108. G. Botero, Raison et gouvernment d’Etat, 1599.
ElQuoted by Silbemer, p. 108. Montchrestien, op. cit.
ON RESOURCES
247
as possible of what the nation needs, to protect the national artisans against
the dangerous rivalry of foreign artisans, such counsels follow, quite strictly,
from the effort necessary in order to have a positive balance of trade. “A
kingdom that can itself satisfy its own needs is always richer, stronger and
more to be feared.’^
Within this doctrine, the question of the responsibility for conflicts does
not arise. Conflict is natural, inevitable, since the interests of states are funda¬
mentally contradictory. “Those who are members of the government of states
must have the latter’s glory, augmentation, and enrichment for their principal
goal. ’HD If the French cannot increase their commerce save by crushing the
Dutch, why should they hesitate to resort to force in order to realize
a legitimate ambition? The mercantilists are not, as such, warmongers. To
say that “the advantages of a great commerce” are equivalent to a war
against our enemy is in a sense to admit that commerce is a substitute for
war. But, if we posit the essential rivalry of states, war is, so to speak,
permanent, whether it assumes the open form of combats or the camouflaged
form of commerce. For princes, the choice of one or the other is a matter
of opportunity and occasion.
Bodin is not a firebrand, but he reduces the choice between peace and
war to a rational calculation. A prince, even a powerful one, even if he is
wise and magnanimous, “will demand neither war nor peace if necessity,
which is not subject to laws of honor, does not force him to do so; and will
never wage battle, provided there is no more apparent profit in victory
than in loss if the enemies were victorious.’^ Perhaps this formula of Sir
William Temple’s, in its frankness and its moderation, expresses all the
pacifism of which mercantilism is capable: “It is a maxim whose truth I
believe one can never deny, that no wise state will ever undertake war save
with the intention of making conquests or in the necessity of protecting
itself.’®
The liberal has not only a different objective from the mercantilist, he
interprets the facts differently. What I gain, the other loses, affirms the
mercantilist. In a free exchange he who profits least still profits, answers
the liberal (or at least the liberal type). The demonstration of this formula
assumes several more or less refined forms. But the core of the argument is
as simple in the liberal doctrine as it was in that of the mercantilist.
According to the latter, commerce is not a means of obtaining the goods
one desires by giving up others one is not using, but an apparently peaceful
method of enlarging one’s own share of a given stock of precious metals.
Once the obsession with precious metals disappears, once the development
of the means of production dissipates the illusion of a permanently fixed
ip Quoted by Silbemer, p. no. Montchiestien, op. cit.
E^Quoted by Silbemer, p. 26. Montchrestien, op. cit.
EDQuoted by Silbemer, p. 20. J. Bodin, De la Republique, 1576.
IHOQuoted by Silbemer, p. 65. Sir William Temple, 1693.
SOCIOLOGY
248
volume of goods to be distributed or of trade to be shared among the nations,
the belligerent character of the exchange disappears of itself and, hitherto
unnoticeable, its pacific character appears evident. If each of the parties to
the exchange decides of his own will, it cannot be that either of them “loses in
the exchange,” even if, in monetary values, one party or the other does not
make equal gains.
When the obsession with precious metals disappears, so does the idea of an
essential difference between foreign trade and domestic trade. Perfect liber¬
alism assumes, by hypothesis, a universal republic of exchanges. Whether or
not a province is outside the national borders matters little: buyers will obtain
the goods produced in this province only in return for the goods they possess.
Ideally, in relation to humanity taken as a whole, there is only a single
trade, which the military force of states is impotent to modify. According to
Bentham’s celebrated formula: “Conquer the whole world, it is impossible
you should increase your trade one half-penny.’®
From this the liberals conclude just as logically that trade is essentially
contrary to war. Trade pacifies, whereas political rivalry inflames passions.
Already in the eighteenth century, formulas opposed to those of mercantilism
are more frequent. Quesnay no longer assumes that foreign trade accounts
for the greatness of nations and is, in essence, aggressive. “The reciprocal
commerce of nations is mutually sustained by the wealth of the sellers and
the buyers. ’H 3 “Custom duties,” Dupont de Nemours writes, “are a kind
of reciprocal hostility between nations.® And in a formula which makes an
admirable pendant to those of Colbert a century earlier, the Abbe Baudeau
writes in 1771: “The opposition of interests constitutes the essence of the
policy of usurpation. The unity of interests constitutes the essence of eco¬
nomic policy.’^
Once it is assumed, as J. F. NelsorHslput it, that “the spirit of conquest and
the spirit of commerce are mutually exclusive in a nation,” the liberals (dif¬
fering from the mercantilists, for whom international conflicts did not raise
any problem because they belonged to the natural order of things) must
account for the existence of wars. On the whole, it seems to me, there are
three possible answers. The first is to establish that commerce and politics
belong to two fundamentally different orders. States are in permanent rivalry
not because they have contradictory economic interests but because the
princes or the peoples are eager for glory or land. A second answer emphasizes
the gap between the true interests of states or nations and the consciousness
EIlQuoted by Silberner, p. 260, note 18. Bentham, Principles of International Law,
rl 43 '
^Quoted by Silberner, p. 196. Quesnay, article “Grains” in the Encyclopedic.
[i®lQuoted by Silberner, p. 204. Declaration by Dupont to the Council of Elders (Ses¬
sion of the Fourth Floreal, Year IV). Moniteur universel of April 28, 1796.
LLiilQuoted by Silberner, p. 207. Abbe Baudeau, Premiere introduction a la philosophie
ecq nomique.
LSHjQuoted by Silberner, p. 172. E ssai politique sur le commerce.
ON RESOURCES
249
governments have of them. Or again, the liberals distinguish between the
economy as it might he in a republic of exchanges and the economy as it is,
distorted by private monopolies. Lastly, a final answer is to invoke the factor
of overpopulation. Malthus’s precursors are numerous. The same author who
maintains that the spirit of commerce and the spirit of conquest are mutually
exclusive admits that overpopulation is a legitimate motive for conquest.
The first answer is approximately limiting the scope of the economic inter¬
pretation of politics. It is unwarranted to conceive of the world as if it
resembled a universal republic of exchanges. The political rivalry of states is
the first datum, advantages and disadvantages of such an economic method
must not be judged in relation to the whole of humanity, imagined as one,
but in reference to the consequences which this method entails for states
which are in fact rivals. (We need merely return to this proposition and to
combine it with the relatively new fact of industrialization in order to have
the principle of the national-economy school.)
The second interpretation, the more usual one, explains the conflict in
terms of the gap between the economy as it should be and the economy as
it is. The essential notion, which runs through the entire literature of the
last century and which results in books like those of Hobson and Norman
Angell, is already to be found under Quesnay’s pen: the distinction between
merchants and commerce, between the private interests of some and the
well-understood interest of the collectivity. “The merchants participate in the
wealth of nations but the nations do not participate in the wealth of the
merchants . . . all wars and all reservations relating to commerce can only
have monopoly as an object, perhaps involuntary on the part of the kingdom’s
traders, but always fatal to the nations that do not distinguish their interests
from those of their merchants and that ruin themselves by undertaking wars
in order to assure the national agents of their commerce an exclusive privilege
which is prejudicial to themselves. "El
At the limit, the liberal a la Bentham declares that wars always cost more
than they achieve, even for the conqueror, that conquests are in essence bad
business. What is the use of assuming the expenses of administrating a foreign
territory? If the latter were both sovereign and open to commerce, the metro¬
politan nation would enjoy the benefits which it might derive from its colonies
without the expenses which the latter impose upon it.
The events of the twentieth century have not so much refuted this doc¬
trinal optimism as incited the economists of liberal inspiration to become more
aware of the gap between nations of a capitalist regime as they are and an
ideal type of liberal economy. L. Robbins’s book on the economic causes of
conflictJsHor J. Schumpeter’s on imperialism^ take their place in the lineage
H 3 Quoted by Silberner, p. 197. Quesnay, of. cit.
UjjJTka Economic Causes of War, London, 1939.
HH Imperialism and Social Classes, Oxford, 1951.
250
SOCIOLOGY
of Quesnay and Adam Smith, that is, of the economists who impute re¬
sponsibility for war to the spirit of monopoly and to the residues of mer¬
cantilism. Only Thorstein Veblen opens a new chapter by reviving the idea
of the similarity between the spirit of commerce and the spirit of war and
by locating the seat of the spirit of peace in industry.
The economists of the historical and national school would not subscribe
to either of these two themes. They would reject the mercantilist formula
that commerce is the continuation of war by other means, but they would
also reject the Bentham liberalist formula that “all trade is in its essence
advantageous, even to that party to whom it is least so. All wars in essence
ruin us.” Or again: “Between the interest of nations, there is nowhere any
real conflict; if they appear repugnant anywhere, it is only in proportion to
their being misunderstood.’®
The historical school, by definition so to speak, takes historical reality for
its point of departure. Now this reality involves the compartmentalization
of space, the fractionalization of humanity. The rivalry o£ states is not re¬
duced to economic competition. The nations do not fight each other merely
to gain wealth or to favor trade. The balance-sheet of wars is not to he
established in relation to the total number of men and in terms of goods
or merchandise. In preserving a nation from invasion, armies are productive
to the same degree as the wealth which they save. Victorious, they may afford
the state and the people not only spoils but occasions and means for pros¬
perity.
This temperate and reasonable interpretation of the relations between
economy (or commerce) and wars (or conquests) would probably have been
admitted by most liberals in the last century as corresponding to experience.
If we concede the primacy and the fatality of humanity’s splitting up into
rival states, armies are indispensable to nations, even if they are costly. We
may say, with Quesnay, “the statesman regrets the men destined for war as
the landowner regrets the land used for the ditch necessary to irrigate the
field.® If the field is lost when the ditch is filled in, the latter, though
representing a loss in relation to the optimum, remains profitable in the real
world, if space is no longer compartmentalized. Similarly, the liberal may with
some difficulty plead that all war is costly, even for the victor, if he refers
to the model of a universal and pacific republic which ignores frontiers and
soldiers. But history being what it is, it is difficult to deny that victorious
wars have sometimes gained advantages for peoples and increased the pos¬
sibilities of welfare.
Therefore the new, important idea which dominates the thought of the
school I shall call national rather than historical concerns neither the
balance-sheet of armed conflicts nor the judgment passed on soldiers. The
E 3 Quoted by Silbemer, p. 261. Bentham, op. cit.
DUlQuoted by Silbemer, p. 193. Quesnay, op. cit.
ON RESOURCES
251
originality of the national school lies in its rediscovery of certain arguments of
the mercantilists, renewed by the consideration of industrial economy. F. List
denies neither that the welfare of individuals is the goal nor that wars in
themselves destroy wealth. But the existence of separate political units is a
fact. The economist has no right to ignore the fate of the collectivity to
which he belongs and to reason in relation to a humanity without frontiers,
ideal perhaps but temporarily inaccessible. Now, at the present moment, free
exchange does not contribute equally to the prosperity of all nations. It tends,
on the contrary, to consecrate, even to reinforce the supremacy of the most
advanced nations, that is, those which already possess an industry. How will
the less advanced nations manage to progress in their turn in the industrial
world if they open their borders to manufactured products? Free trade would
condemn them to remaining indefinitely providers of raw materials and pri¬
mary products. In the century when industry is a condition of power, the
suppression of tariff barriers would tend to eternalize the present disparity
between agricultural and industrialized nations, and hence the inequalities
of power and standard of living, contrary to justice and even perhaps to peace.
List clearly conceived the theory, which we have indicated abovep! of
harmonious development. Since the latter is possible only within a sufficiently
extensive framework, it is easy to shift to the notion of great space. The
creation of vast economic-political units is the first stage of the republic of
exchanges. The partisan of national economy does not deny that this first
stage may require the use of violence. For a nation to be able, in essentials,
to be self-sufficient, it must first protect its new industries, and always protect
its vital ones. It must also on occasion round out the territory of its sov¬
ereignty.
Ultimately, F. List does not exclude a peace based on the equilibrium of
nations and national economies. Beyond the formation of great wholes, free
exchange would reveal itself to be fruitful because it would bring into rela¬
tion equal partners. Universal peace will not emerge from free exchange, but
free exchange will perhaps be the ultimate result of a pacified humanity, as a
result of temporary protectionism, as a result of the reinforcement of the
political-economic units into which humanity is naturally divided.
Probably the socialist school is the one whose doctrine it is most difficult
to summarize in a few propositions relating to conflicts and wars. The Utopian
socialist is inclined to believe that peace among states will of itself follow
peace within nations. As long as poverty is rampant, as long as injustices are
not eliminated, the struggle between individuals and classes will continue.
The Utopian socialists have not had, it seems to me, a single and coherent
theory of the relations between the class struggle and rivalries among states.
But they have postulated, more or less clearly, that the reconciliation of men
113 Cf. Chap. VII, Sec. 3.
252
SOCIOLOGY
and of groups within an equitable order would lead of itself to the reconcilia¬
tion of states.
The socialism of Marxist inspiration, on the other hand, professes a few
simple and categorical ideas. It regards wars as inevitable in the capitalist
system. It borrows from one of the sections of the liberal school the explana¬
tion of wars by the rivalry of economic interests. It adds the assertion that
with the advent of socialism, the occasions or the causes of armed conflicts
would disappear. Simplifying, one is tempted to say that according to the
Marxists, the mercantilists faithfully describe the belligerent character of com¬
merce in the capitalist regime, the liberals the pacific character of commerce
after the capitalist regime.
The economy is bellicose in a capitalist system; it will be pacific in a
socialist one. The question is: why should this be so? The liberal econ¬
omists have incriminated the spirit of protection and monopoly, the action of
the great corporations or trusts which seek to reserve the domestic markets for
themselves and to conquer foreign markets. Lenin summarizes all the accusa¬
tions formulated by the economists of liberal inspiration against the leaders
(private interests, privileged groups) of imperialism. But he transfigures this
interpretation by decreeing that imperialism, far from being imputable to
minorities, is the necessary expression of capitalism that has reached a certain
phase of its evolution (the so-called monopolistic phase). Under the influence
of J. A. Hobson and of Rudolf Hilferdingjsil Lenin insists that capitalism
is condemned to imperialism and that the peaceful division of the planet
among private monopolies or states is impossible. Thus, Leninism reverts to
the essential relationship of commerce and war. But the mercantilist dialectic
was clearer than that of Leninism: the search for precious metals, whose
quantity was not expanding, naturally created rivalries and conflicts. Is the
same true of the search for markets, for raw materials, or for opportunities for
surplus profit?
Why will the economy be peaceful in a socialist regime? The Marxists
have asserted more than demonstrated this proposition, which seemed to them
self-evident, because they accepted as obvious the theory according to which
conflicts among states have economic causes; but Jaur&s’ indefinitely repeated
phrase, “capitalism bears war within itself as the cloud bears the storm,” does
not constitute a proof. The question remains: what are the aspects of capital¬
ism-private ownership of the instruments of production, mechanism of the
market, concentration of property or power in national or international cor¬
porations—which accidentally or inevitably provoke wars among states?
These four schools do not oppose each other on all points. On the question
of political conflicts, certain liberal!^ are in agreement with most of the
Ell n Das Finanzkapital, eine Studie iiher die jiingste Entwicklung des Ka-pitalismus
^published in 1909), Vienna, 1920.
Isslcf. for instance Lionel Robbins, op. cit.
ON RESOURCES
253
mercantilists and the economists of the national school in proclaiming that
the rivalry of states is primary and that wars are not always caused by op¬
posed commercial interests. The socialists, like the liberals, have as their final
objective, in doctrine, the welfare of individuals. The national school, like the
mercantilists, claims to be in the service of the greatness of nations. These
schools define themselves and oppose each other by their interpretation of
commerce (or of exchange) considered as the essence of economic life.
According to the mercantilists, commerce is war, according to the liberals
commerce is peace, on the sole condition that it be free. According to the
national economists, commerce will be peace when all nations are developed;
according to the Marxists commerce is war under capitalism, commerce will
be peace with socialists.
2. Historical Interpretation of the Doctrines
Theories are always partially explained by historical circumstances.
Whether the supreme goal is the power of the state or the welfare of the
citizens, it suffices that the conditions of power be different for the econo¬
mists' judgments of men’s activities to vary legitimately.
In the age of courage, in antiquity, military force was essentially dependent
on number, on the physical vigor of the soldiers, on the organization of the
army. Hence the mode of life favorable to the quantity and quality of com¬
batants, that is, the peasant mode of life, was adorned for centuries with all
the virtues, both pacific and martial. In 1940 Marshal Petain still praised
the earth “which never lies”; he was ready, under the inspiration of reac¬
tionary advisers and age-old beliefs, to prepare France’s revenge by a return
to the fields. Sully had more justification in assuming, at the end of the
sixteenth century, that “strong peoples are peasant peoples because industry
causes the citizens to lose the habit of painful and laborious operation in
which they need to be trained in order to become good soldiers.” Arts and
cities seem to be causes of corruption. The industries debilitate the people,
luxury softens men. States prosper by simplicity and frugality.
Although these theses, up until the middle of the eighteenth century, were
constantly explored by the philosophers, they have been since the dawn of
modem times no more than a partial truth. Soldiers using powder and cannon
need some instruction. "In the days of courage,” as Fuller calls them, the
citizens of Rome acquired their tactical mastery only as a result of the Punic
Wars: the very length of their service had made professionals out of them.
The elite soldiers who in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries dominated
the battlefields on land and even more on sea were no longer amateurs,
whether noble or bourgeois. In matters of armament or training, they de¬
pended on the political authority—city, principality, state—which possessed
enough financial resources to mobilize and equip the troops or crews, to buy
or manufacture vessels and cannon.
Machiavelli, at the beginning of the sixteenth century, is reactionary as a
254
SOCIOLOGY
military theoretician: he does not believe in the effectiveness of artillery; he
is mistaken as to the necessity of the “sinew of war.” Out of love for antiquity,
by political doctrine, he longs for an army of citizens, and continues to regard
the infantry as the queen of battles. In an age when wars of privateering
and piracy afforded considerable spoils, when foreign trade required warships
as well as cargo vessels, the mercantilists were closer to historical truth, less
perverse in their counsel to princes than they seem to us today. Political
units did not differ so much from each other by the number of men or the
potential of manufactures as by the unequal capacity to mobilize resources.
Military force was the primary consequence of this capacity for mobilization.
A city enriched by commerce, such as Venice, could become a great military
power by buying mercenaries, both soldiers and sailors. A vast kingdom lost
its possibilities for action if an empty treasury kept it from mobilizing national
troops or recruiting volunteers. Machiavelli’s formula: “he who has soldiers
finds money,” became true, but in a sense which the Florentine had probably
not envisaged: the state, which had monopolized police powers, acquired
thereby the capacity to draw on an important share of the nation’s resources
for its own needs. Military force continued to be a function both of the
potential and of the capacity for mobilization. But since the latter seemed
henceforth to belong to all states, it was the potential which occupied the
foreground and represented the differential factor.
At the end of the eighteenth century, the arguments about the respective
effectiveness of steel and gold, of infantry and artillery, were exhausted.
Whatever the price still attached to precious metals, the wealth of nations
(what we now call economic growth or expansion) no longer appeared to be
a consequence of the stock of gold and silver possessed and held by each of
them. Peace, public order, the activity of merchants and manufacturers, the
spirit of initiative—these were the profound causes of the swifter enrichment
of some rather than of others. The age of pirates was over. When peace
rules, commerce becomes authentically pacific and no one henceforth calls it
“camouflaged war.” The British authors were all the more inclined to ac¬
centuate the peaceful essence of exchange, since their nation bad the better
share of it.
At the same time, it is enough to open one’s eyes to observe that “virtue
is always rewarded”: by devoting themselves to works of peace, nations guar¬
antee their security, enlarge their power. Adam Smith notes that the condi¬
tions of military force are no longer what they were in the past. In the past,
the poor peoples were also the strong ones. Arms and weapons were simple,
differing little from each other: the differential factor was physical vigor, mar¬
tial ardor. Arts and luxury were more likely to enervate the combatants than
to perfect the instruments of combat. The stereotypes were those of the
Roman Republic, which had reached supremacy by frugality and the virtue
of its peasant citizens, and which had been precipitated into the abyss by
wealth the corruption of the imperial city. It was at Capua that Han-
ON RESOURCES
255
rubai's soldiers had discovered their pleasures and prepared their defeat.
Henceforth, another image replaces the one which modem authors had bor¬
rowed from ancient literature. Civilization, thanks to the arts, henceforth
triumphs over barbarism. Wealth and power go hand in hand, since each has
industry as its basis.
It is at this point that the “national economists” raise their objection. If
industrial development governs both wealth and power, it constitutes the
crucial objective. Trade, free trade, is at best only a means. Yet, these
economists declare, free trade between political-economic units which have
not reached the same phase of development paralyzes or retards those which
are behind. The industrialist thesis is maintained, but on the behalf of tariff
protection and harmonious growth.
These schools exist in the middle of the twentieth century, as they did in
the middle of the nineteenth, although the doctrines have meanwhile as¬
sumed subtler forms: one favoring, in principle, freedom of trade, the other
emphasizing the necessity of harmonious growth and of industrialization. To
a degree, the divergence concerns questions of fact: what is the influence of a
liberal policy of foreign trade on industrialization in the case of an under¬
developed nation? No economist would answer such a question by a simple
and categorical proposition. The economist of liberal tendency would recog¬
nize the necessity for protective measures, at least partial and temporary ones.
The economist of protectionist tendency would recognize the utility of cer¬
tain kinds of trade. But the two orientations exist, either toward the largest
possible self-sufficient space, or toward a worldwide solidarity created by the
most active commerce possible.
The preference for the formula of great space is generally dictated by
political-military considerations as much as by economic ones. The state’s
power is a function of its dependence on the outside world, at the same
time as of its resources and degree of mobilization. An industry, an army
can be paralyzed by the lack of a raw material or of a particular product. The
problem of productivity leads to an international division of labor that is as
extensive as possible. The problem of power forbids the sacrifice of any vital
piece of the machinery of production. The reasoning of the “national econ¬
omists” is convincing in a universe fragmented into rival sovereignties; that
of the liberal economists supposes a universal republic or aims at creating its
conditions.
Thus, the theories concerned with the relation of resources to military
force or to the power of states are readily explained. All contain, for the
period in question, a share of truth. None is entirely true because none
systematically considers the multiple determinants. If we assume the weapons
to be analogous, then number, vigor and organization of the combatants de¬
termine the relation of forces. If we except number, there subsists the duality
of primitive ardor and organization. If is the differential factor, characteristic
of a period, which the theoretician retains and transforms into a unique cause.
SOCIOLOGY
256
Yet let us not forget to note that in each period there are marginal, ex¬
ceptional or aberrant causes. The military power of Athens was based on its
mines, commerce, fleet, and its empire. This power was, therefore, precarious
and of short duration. It nonetheless dominated the system of the city-states
for a time. Similarly Carthage would have subscribed to the mercantilist
formula: money is the sinew of war. The citizens of Carthage had fought
the Roman soldiers for years before succumbing at the end of the Third Punic
War. Yet Hannibal, who made Rome tremble, led an army of mercenaries
and foreign units furnished by his allies.
In our own age no one would go so far as to proclaim that the quality of
the combatants is the result of the frugality of their mode of life. In piloting
planes or driving assault tanks, the level of instruction is much more impor¬
tant than the simplicity of manners. But in the djebels of Algeria, the for¬
mula of the ancient authors recovers a degree of truth. The Kabyl peasant
is much more adept at night fighting, at hand-to-hand combat and ambushes
than the young Frenchman of a unit accustomed to cities and electric lights.
The French unit remained the master of the terrain thanlcs to number, or¬
ganization and certain technical weapons. Yet qualitative superiority, in a
particular kind of combat, is not on the side of civilization, even in the age
of industry.
There subsists a more general share of truth in the proposition attributing
martial superiority to a poor people over a rich one. We agree that the strength
of regular armies is a function of their equipment and the latter, in its turn,
of industry. Military force would thus be proportional to the human and in¬
dustrial potential, if the capacity for mobilization were taken to be equal in
the various states. But this capacity, as a matter of fact, is never equal. It is
controlled by two variables: administrative effectiveness and the people’s con¬
sent to privation. The volume of resources available for the war effort is
measured by the gap between total production and the minimum necessary
for subsistence. Habits of frugality reduce the supplies necessary for the army
in the field. They permit a lower standard of living for the civilian popula¬
tion and thereby enlarge the gap between total production and the irreducible
minimum of civilian consumption.
Lastly the regime, in its turn, is more or less capable of convincing, per¬
suading or obliging the people to accept a lower standard of living. To a
degree, the distribution of collective resources, in peacetime and in wartime,
is controlled by the mode of government. In the industrial age, the modem
alternative of welfare or power reproduces, in a renewed form, the ancient
alternative of frugality, the mother of virtue, and luxury, the principle of
corruption. It remains to be discovered whether frugality by constraint, which
the modem despotisms impose, is morally and politically similar to the virtue
praised by the Greek or Roman authors.
If it is relatively easy to explain, by referring to historical data, the theories
concerned with the relation between resources and force; the same is not true
ON RESOURCES
257
of the theories concerned with the economic causes of conflicts. The theories
of the first type are not a faithful expression of reality, they distort it, simplify
it, transform it, but they regularly retain one truly essential aspect of it. On
the other hand, the economic interpretations of conflict seem to be fashionable
to the very degree that they are contestable.
During the ages of stationary or slowly advancing techniques, force was a
much more effective method of acquiring goods than trade. The quantity of
wealth which the conquerors could seize by arms was enormous compared
to the quantity which they created by their labor. Slaves, precious metals,
tributes or taxes levied on the foreign populations, the profits of victory,
were obvious and rewarding. Yet the classical authors, without ever admitting
or denying the economic productivity of empire, almost all asserted that the
latter was desired for itself.
On the other hand, in the modem age, the economic profits of victory,
however substantial they may be on occasion, have become insignificant or
absurd compared to the additional wealth which the>yearly progress of tech¬
nology or organization furnishes the industrialized peoples. Yet it is in our
period that the influential authors believe that imperialism remains mysterious
as long as the pressure of “trusts” and the appetite for money have not been
exposed behind the activity of diplomats and soldiers.
This apparent paradox is, in fact, the best introduction to the problem of
economic interpretation of inter-state conflicts. During the millenniums of
the historical period, inequality has been extreme between the privileged and
the masses within the complex societies, between the various collectivities.
The low labor yield did not permit giving the benefits of luxury or leisure to
all. Whether he owned land, precious metals, slaves or castles, the property of
one man signified the privation of another. Property was, in essence, monopo¬
listic. Abstract economic theory demonstrates that, given a certain distribution
of goods, the mechanism of free exchange is the most advantageous for all.
It does not demonstrate that the disfavored must passively accept the distri¬
bution made at a given moment in history. The use of force by the have-nots
in order to take from the haves was readily intelligible.
The poverty of all known societies from the dawn of civilization, the un¬
equal distribution of wealth within and among collectivities, the extent of
the wealth to be seized by violence in comparison with the wealth produced
by labor, all these facts have constituted the structural condition of conflict
between classes or states, and account in retrospect for the wars of conquest.
Must we conclude that this has always been the motive of the conquerors,
down through the centuries? No historian would be so insane or rather so
stupid as to say so. The nomads of the deserts or the steppes, the Arabs or
the Mongols, lived the kind of life of which combat was the spontaneous
expression, the principal activity. They waged war for its own sake, they at¬
tacked sedentary populations because battle was their pleasure and empire
their vocation. Bonaparte’s orders of the day to the Italian army, contrasting
SOCIOLOGY
258
the soldiers’ poverty with the w r ealth before their eyes, was not necessary to
hurl the Asian horsemen to the assault.
The imperialism of Athens or of Rome would be more consonant with an
economic interpretation. Greatness, as we have said, was inseparably political
and economic, naval and commercial. Athens could not subsist as a city-state
of more than forty thousand citizens, reveling in the splendor of her festivals,
without a commercial network and the tribute of her allies. In defeat she
saved neither her fortune nor her glory. Yet Thucydides does not consider—
and we are tempted to agree with him—that the Athenians were especially
greedy for wealth. What animated them was the pride of dominion, which
knew no bounds and which swept them into catastrophe.
Roman imperialism, especially starting from the end of the Republic and
under the Empire, had many causes of an economic order. The city, having
grown huge, needed the African wheat. Without tribute paid by the con¬
quered, handouts to the crowd and public games would have been impos¬
sible. Romans of the privileged classes, partisans or knights, went to the
provinces to make their money as proconsuls or tax collectors. None would
have thought, and none would think today, of applying Bentham’s calculus
to the Roman Empire: the cost of the colonies to the metropolitan nation.
Nor would any have regarded Virgil’s advice to the Roman people as merely
the camouflage of avarice: tu regere -populos memento. The Empire had no
need for a justification when it w y as economically profitable.
Why has empire, in the course of modem times, been increasingly in¬
terpreted in economic or in philosophical terms, and less and less in frankly
political terms, following the example of the Greeks? During a first phase, say
from the sixteenth century to the eighteenth, imperial conquests were obvi¬
ously profitable. It would be absurd to claim that explorers or even merchants
were animated by the mere desire for profits, by the mere thirst for gold and
silver. The psychology of the Spanish conquistadors in America does not
lend itself to crude simplification. Perhaps the religious mission was invoked
in order to calm consciences which were troubled by the enormity of the
profits and the cruel fate inflicted upon the natives. The advent of precious
metals, the possession of distant lands covered Spain with power and wealth.
Why question the respective share of the various motives in the behavior of
the conquerors?
The French and English empires in India or America, different as they
were from each other and from the Spanish Empire, were scarcely more prob¬
lematical. The motives for which Englishmen, Frenchmen, Spaniards or
Dutchmen went to settle in America, on the territory of what is today the
United States or Canada, were many. Some set out by order of the authori¬
ties, others to protect their right to worship according to the imperatives of
their conscience, others to find opportunities for a broader, freer life, still
others to reap the profits of a distant and speculative commerce. The creation
of a new France or a new England in an almost empty territory was self-
ON RESOURCES
259
explanatory, like the attraction of the Indies trade or the creation of military
bases by chartered companies whose explicit goal was money.
The errors of judgment committed by contemporaries at the period of the
Treaty of Paris and so often repeated by French authors were due to the
disparity between the actual importance and the virtual importance of this or
that territory. In 1763 Santo Domingo represented for France a more precious
possession than Canada, whose icy wastes offered the metropolitan nation
little more than furs or a few rare metals. Space for population growth was
not yet recognized as the supreme wealth. The link between the spirit of
commerce and the spirit of adventure, between curiosity and greed, between
the advantages of commerce and the rapine of conquests, between the monop¬
oly of the flag and political sovereignty were sufficiently apparent for a strictly
economic theory of European expansion to have had, before the nineteenth
century, neither the merit of originality nor that of cynicism. It would have
seemed an arbitrary and futile design for explanation.
The intellectual climate changed slowly in the nineteenth century. Philos¬
ophers and moralists questioned the legitimacy of wars and conquests just
when the liberal economists began to doubt the advantage of empires or
colonies for the metropolitan nations. The imperialists found themselves
doubly on the defensive. Henceforth they were obliged to justify what had
hitherto seemed to correspond to the accepted order of things, to account for
empire both on the level of ideas and on that of advantage, against those who
denounced it as unjust and against those who denounced it as costly. Which
explains the conjunction, in the speeches of Jules Ferry 7 , of phrases about the
civilizing mission of France (or of the white man) and of others about the
necessity, for the sake of commerce and prestige, of hoisting the tricolor over
the four comers of the globe. The interpreters of British imperialism also
resorted to two kinds of arguments: Joseph Chamberlain’s prosperity by em¬
pire and Rudyard Kipling’s white man’s burden.
Simultaneously the theoreticians of socialism: humanitarians, interpreters
of the idealistic hope of the West attack class struggles, inequalities, wars.
They attribute armed conflicts to capitalism. And the imperialists as well as
the liberals furnish them proofs of capitalism’s responsibility. The imperialists
pride themselves on the wealth which the colonies afford the metropolitan
nation. The liberals, at least those hostile to the colonies and convinced of
the pacific character of modem economics, indict the damaging action of the
privileged groups. The Marxists use the arguments of both groups in order
to demonstrate that “imperialism is the final stage of capitalism.”
3. Imperialism and Colonization
Imperialism, according to the simplest and most general definition, is the
diplomatic-strategic behavior of a political unit which constmcts an empire,
that is, subjects foreign populations to its rule. The Romans, the Mongols,
the Arabs have been empire-builders whom we properly call imperialists.
260
SOCIOLOGY
Many dubious cases occur in the margins of this phenomenon, which is
never absent from the chronicle of the ages. Should we call it imperialism
when the populations of the conquering unit and of the subject units share
the same culture and, so to speak, the same nationality? CWas Bismarck, as
the creator of the German empire, an imperialist?-) Should we call it im¬
perialism when the rules of Tsarist Russia or of the Soviet Union seek to
maintain a state unity embracing heterogeneous populations? Can we say
that the German unification was not imperialistic insofar as it corresponded
to the aspirations of the Germans, that the maintenance of the Soviet
Empire is not imperialistic insofar as the non-Russian peoples consent to it? It
is not easy, even for the unbiased observer, to measure the respective force
of popular sentiments favorable or hostile to the construction or conserva¬
tion of an empire. To trace the limits of imperialism clearly, the frontiers of
nations would have to be visible on the map of cultures, of languages or of
popular aspirations.
Imperialism is also equivocal in another sense. Does it disappear by the
mere fact that state sovereignties are officially respected? Would the peoples
of Eastern Europe, liberated by the Soviet army and governed today by Com¬
munist parties, be wrong to denounce the imperialism of Moscow? The
frontier is vague between the so-called legitimate influence of great powers
and the so-called culpable imperialism. Within a heterogeneous system, every
ruling power is obliged to exercise an influence on the internal affairs of
secondary states, at least to the degree necessary to prevent the victory of the
party linked to the rival campUnI
Colonization, as practiced by the Greek city-states in the eighth and
seventh centuries b.c., by the Europeans in America since the sixteenth cen¬
tury, represents a different phenomenon. The Corinthian colonists who
founded Corcyra occupied an available space; the British Puritans from En¬
gland were less concerned to conquer the Indians than nature. In the long
run colonization has more influence on peoples’ respective place in the sun
than imperialism (unless the latter proceeds to the extermination of the con¬
quered) : India could not remain long under the sovereignty of Her Britannic
Majesty, but the United States will continue to speak English.
The European empires have been partly the result of imperialism, partly
the result of colonization. In North America colonization prevailed over im¬
perialism, in Asia and in Africa imperialism over colonization. The case of
the Spanish Empire in South America was intermediary. In both cases men
from the metropolitan nation came and settled in the conquered territory. In
an extreme case, this minority is reduced to soldiers and administrators who
HHThese questions are not rhetorical, nor do they seek an answer. I am simply con¬
cerned to clarify the concepts involved and to reveal the various aspects of the phe¬
nomenon.
Hohrhe dialectic of imperialism, in a heterogeneous diplomatic system, does not ex¬
clude discrimination between degrees of interference, influence or domination.
ON RESOURCES
261
wield the imperial authority. Generally, though, it includes civilians as well,
landowners or businessmen who enjoy the privilege of belonging to the ruling
power and who derive profit from it. When the imperial minority is defini¬
tively established and when it is numerous enough, it takes the initiative in
breaking with the metropolitan nation and constituting an independent state.
But it does not thereby lose its power and wealth. Imperial domination ex¬
tends within the new state: in extreme circumstances, there exists one state
and two peoples. When the minority from the metropolitan nation is not
numerous enough, or when it does not mingle with the native populations,
it is at the mercy of a turn of fortune. The “French colonies” of Tunisia or
Morocco are in the process of liquidation. They were able to imitate neither
the ruling classes of Spanish origin who "liberated” the republics of South
America from the metropolitan nation, nor the European immigrants in
North America.
Imperialism and colonization involve too many varieties for one and the
same interpretation to be applied to all centuries and all nations. It is tbe
Marxist theory of imperialism and the liquidation, by the European states,
of their empires in Asia and Africa which have made fashionable the con¬
troversies on the nature of the imperial phenomenon. Leaving aside the Greek
colonization in the eighth century b.c. and the European colonization in
America since the sixteenth century, we should like to raise a single question:
is nineteenth-century imperialism attributable to the capitalist regime?
It seems to me preferable to begin with historical considerations, which do
not avoid the theoretical question but which afford arguments in favor of
this or that interpretation. The three facts which the authors discuss at great
length are: the massive exports of European capital during the last decades of
the nineteenth and the first decade of the twentieth century, the race for
Africa during the same periodpH and the First World War. The Leninist
theory of imperialism demands a relation among these three events. The
theory is at least shaken if it does not link them together of necessity.
Historical studies of the export of capital and the colonial conquest have
been undertaken many timesPiLlNone confirms a simple and dogmatic in¬
terpretation.
The two nations which during the half century before the First World
War conquered the largest territories, France and Great Britain, were also
the nations which, economically, least needed to acquire new possessions.
France had a stationary population, a slow industrial growth, and therefore
suffered neither population surplus, lack of raw materials nor dearth of outlets
GEDThis period of diplomatic history has been studied by William L. Langer in a work
entitled Diplomacy of Imperialism, New York, 1935, and also by Parker T. Moon,
Imperialism and World Politics, New York, 1927.
HHThe classical works are E. Staley, War and the Private Investor, New York, 1935;
Herbert Feis, Europe as World Banker, New Haven, 1930; and A. K. Caimcross,
Home and Foreign Investments, Cambridge, 1953.
262
SOCIOLOGY
for manufactured products. Population and production increased more rap¬
idly in Great Britain, but tbe emigration valve remained open and, with the
dominions and its sovereignty over India, the United Kingdom was not
starved for space. It is true that both France and Great Britain had a surplus
of capital, since they had become bankers for the world, hut they invested
only a slight fraction of this surplus in their colonies.
Out of 40 to 45 billion gold franc^] invested abroad just before 1914, only
4 billion were invested in the Empire. The majority was invested in Europe
(27.5 billion, of which 11.3 was invested in Russia), 6 billion in Latin
America, 2 billion in North America, 3.3 billion in Egypt, Suez and South
Africa, and 2.2 billion in Asia. Of the British capital invested abroad, half
was invested in the Empire, but only a small share in the newly acquired
African possessions.
The first question is why France and England had so much capital avail¬
able for foreign investment. The standard answer is the inequality of the dis¬
tribution of income, but the figures do not entirely confirm this classical
explanation. The French saving^have been estimated at 2 billion for the
1875-93 period, at 3.5 billion for the 1900-11 period, and at 5 billion on the
eve of the war. Now the national income was on the order of 27 to 28 billion
in 1903, 32 to 35 billion in 1913, perhaps higher than 35 billion in 1914:
savings did not exceed an average of 10 to 12 per cent of the national income,
and the foreign investments represented some 35 per cent of those savings!!!
The total amount of savings not being abnormally high, the incitement to
export capital must have been exceptionally strong or else the demand for
investments in metropolitan France relatively weak (probably both at the
same time).
Similarly in Great Britain, for the year 1907, one British economist ar¬
rives at the following figures: the investment of fixed capital rose to £275
million, the addition to stocks rose to £20 million, the addition to the stock
of durable goods rose to £30 million; the maintenance of capital representing
£175 million, the net domestic investment rose to £150 million and the foreign
IssjThe national revenue was on the order of 35 billion gold francs.
H 3 Cf. R. Pupin, La Richesse de la France devant la guerre, Paris, 1916, and La
Richesse privee et les finances frangaises, Paris, 1919; J. Lescure, L’Epargne en France,
Paris. 1914.
H Furthermore, we must not forget that foreign investments were drawn increasingly
from the incomes of previous investments. French investments abroad began again,
after the War of 1870, starting in 1886. They reached an average of 450 to 550
million francs between 1886 and 1890, from 519 to 619 million francs between
1891 and 1896, from 1,157,000,000 to 1,257,000,000 francs between 1897 and
1902, from 1,359,000,000 to 1,459,000,000 francs between 1903 and 1908, from
1,239,000,000 to 1,339,000,000 francs between 1909 and 1913 (the figures taken from
H. Feis, op. cit., p. 44, referring to H. G. Moulton and C. Lewis, The French Debt
Problem, New York, 1925). The income from foreign investments is regularly equal to
or higher than the investments during these periods. (Feis, p. 44.)
ISSJA. K. Caimcross, Home and Foreign Investment, Cambridge, 1953, p. 121.
ON RESOURCES
263
investment to £135 million. In short, this latter represented nearly half of the
total net investment. “It was also symptomatic that Britain herself had in¬
vested abroad about as much as her entire industrial and commercial capital,
excluding land, and that one-tenth of her national income came to her as
interest on foreign investment.®]
Of these two causes, one, at least, is sufficiently well known from historical
study. French capital was drawn outside the country by excess profits not
always paid to the owners of this capital® but to the intermediaries, the
bankers. These excess profits would not have been enough to induce the
exodus of French capital to Russia or the Balkans had the government not
used the nation’s financial power as an instrument in its diplomacy. Some¬
times the loans served for the construction, in Russia, of strategically impor¬
tant railroads, sometimes they guaranteed projects for national industry,
sometimes they insured the loyalty of certain nations in which a party favor¬
able to the Central Powers opposed a party favorable to the Allies.
Investments made outside Great Britain were much less influenced by
diplomatic considerations than French investments, and it is not impossible
to argue, even today, that on the whole they afforded Great Britain at least
as many advantages as disadvantages!!!! The yield from foreign state bonds
and from shares in foreign corporations was, on the whole, higher than that
from domestic investments. The distribution of this capital among various
uses (£1,531 million in railroad stocks) and the various regions of the world
(over half in North and South America, almost half in the Empire) confirms
the economic motivation of the movement of English capital.
\Mllbid., p. 3. Perhaps the following indications are even more striking: “In the forty
years 1875—1914 capital at home (other than land) increased from about £.5,000 m.
to about £9,200 m., or by over 80%. Foreign investment rose from £1,100 m. to say
£4,000 m. in 1914, or by some 250%. Taking absolute figures, capital investment
probably constituted of three parts home and two parts foreign investment. Of the
investment at home a large part was needed merely to maintain capital per head, for
the number of employed persons rose by about 50% between the boom years of 1873 and
1913. Out of a surplus of £4,500 m. beyond what was necessary in order to keep
domestic capital per head constant, not far short of £3,000 m. or some 60-65% was
actually employed to increase Britain’s foreign investments” (p. 4).
l 88 lD id foreign investments yield the investor more than comparable domestic in¬
vestments?
Cairncross doubts this in relation to French investments: “It has been estimated
that in 1899 the yield on domestic securities at the price of issue averaged 4.28%,
while the yield on foreign securities was no more than 3.85%. At the market price
in 1900, the yields were 2.23 and 3.84% respectively. The difference, whether positive
or negative, was trifling” (p. 225).
Feis (p. 36), quoting French authors, states that the yield from foreign investments
was higher than that from the corresponding investments in France, 3.13 per cent and
4.20 per cent respectively in 1903; 3.40 per cent and 4.62 per cent in 1911.
In the case of England there is no doubt that the yield from foreign investments was
higher. In 1905-9, according to Cairncross (p. 227), the yields were as follows:
domestic investments: 3.61 per cent; colonial investments: 3.94 per cent; foreign in¬
vestments: 4.97 per cent.
Hcf. Cairncross, op. cit., pp. 224-35.
SOCIOLOGY
264
During the final period before the First World War, Germany, in its turn,
had joined the “club of lenders,” impelled both by political ambition and by
the desire for economic expansion. The German bankers were sometimes
seeking higher profits, sometimes vast enterprises that were expressed by in¬
dustrial projects. Occasionally, the German government, In its turn, counted
on capital to gain political influence or to orient the diplomacy of certain
Balkan or Near Eastern countries in its favor. However, the German econ¬
omy, which was developing more rapidly than that of Great Britain or of
France, had higher investment rates but also a greater need of its own
capital. German foreign investments were between 22 and 25 billion marks.
The annual long-term export of capital, during the twenty years that preceded
the war, rose to some 600 million marks; they represented in 1914 only 2 per
cent of the national income!^ at most.
It is not without interest to compare the export of European capital, before
the First World War, with the aid to the underdeveloped countries since the
Second. A double similarity appears. In both cases the export of capital con¬
tributes to the development of the nations in the process of modernization:
British capital, at the end of the nineteenth century and at the beginning of
the twentieth, helped Argentina to construct railroads, the United States to
build great industries; similarly, American capital has powerfully contributed
to the revival of Western Europe, Russian capital will permit the construction
of the Aswan Dam. Today, as yesterday, exports of capital are not entirely
disinterested: European loans were seeking a higher return or else were at
the service of national diplomacy; American gifts are governed, partially at
least, by political considerations. But it would be a mistake, in history, to
grow indignant over what Kant called “the radical evil”; let us not insist that
men do good for the sake of good, let us be satisfied that their selfishness or
their rivalry achieves the good results which might have been sought directly
by men of good will.
Both loans of capital in 1900 and aid to underdeveloped countries in i960
are linked to the strictly political competition of states. France loaned to Rus¬
sia so that the Russian mobilization might be accelerated in case of a gen¬
eralized war. It made loans to Rumania with the hope that the latter would
side with the Allied camp. The United States has aided Europe with the
hope that prosperity would raise a barrier against communism. They were aid¬
ing the underdeveloped countries to forestall Soviet aid, with the vague idea
that ideas accompany capital and technologists. On the other hand, one
difference strikes us: the order of magnitude is not the same. The income
from foreign investments represented 6 per cent of the French national in¬
come on the eve of the First World War, some 9 per cent of the British na¬
tional income. France’s annual loans on the eve of the war amounted to some
4 per cent of the national income in France; they rose to a still higher per-
Efcf. Feis, op. tit., pp. 71-72.
ON BESOUKCES
265
centage in Great Britain. One per cent of the American gross national
product would be equivalent, in i960, to five billion dollars, 3 per cent to
fifteen billion dollars. The needs of domestic investments no longer left so
large an amount of capital available. The cumulative surpluses in foreign
accounts which, before 1914, tended to the continuous increase of foreign
investments, have not been repeated since 1945. On the contrary, American
surpluses from foreign investments have been gradually balanced and then
exceeded by the export of capital, the expenses of maintaining American
troops and governmental aid to foreign countries.
Between 1880 and 1914 the volume of available French and English capi¬
tal prevented neither the growth of production nor the rise of the standard of
livingEUlt is not certain that the rich furnished the greatest part of the
savings. In France, the petite bourgeoisie followed a traditional way of life
and made every effort to save as much as possible. Durable consumer goods
were only beginning to appear. Occasions for spending did not multiply so
rapidly as today. Lastly, and perhaps this is the essential fact, in the pre-1914
capitalist regime, investments resulted chiefly from decisions taken by en¬
trepreneurs. The psychology of the latter is not reducible to the reasoning
elaborated by pure theory. The spirit of initiative, of creation, of investment
varies with the social context. It is different in i960 from what it was in 1910.
Whatever the case, surpluses of capital were not the direct cause of either
the colonial conquests or the First World War. Why would France have
conquered North Africa or Equatorial Africa because of such surpluses since
she was not investing them there? (The same reasoning applies to Great
Britain.) The rivalry for the profitable investment of surplus capital is not
a myth. What is a myth is that the capitalists, bankers or industrialists have,
as a class and to increase their excess profits, incited the European govern¬
ments to conquer colonies, that is, to wage war on each other.
As for the colonies, historical study readily demonstrates three propositions:
1. There is no proportion between the importance of the colonial conquests,
accomplished by the various nations of Europe at the end of the nineteenth
century, and the need each of these nations would have had for them if the
theory^ which explains colonial imperialism by “capitalist contradictions”
were true. 2. The colonies of recent acquisition, that is, essentially, the
French, English and German empires in Africa, absorbed only a small frac¬
tion of the foreign commerce of the metropolitan nations. Trade between
industrialized nations was more important in absolute figures than trade be¬
tween industrialized nations and non-industrialized nations. Political posses¬
sion involved neither generally nor immediately an increase of trade with the
metropolitan nations. 3. In some cases of armed conflicts or of colonial con¬
quests, private groups, great corporations or adventurers have played a role,
[HI The latter, however, seems to have made little progress between 1900 and 1914
in France.
EUWhether this theory invokes vital outlets or the search for excess-profits.
266
SOCIOLOGY
exerted a pressure on diplomats or statesmen. But, at the origin of the
“diplomacy of imperialism” (in the meaning W. L. Langer gives this
expression), the strictly political impulse seems stronger than economic mo¬
tivations. The desire for greatness and glory which animates the leaders of
men has had a more lasting effect on the course of events than the more or
less camouflaged influence of corporations.
It is impossible to measure precisely the strict efficacy of each cause or the
exact motive of each individual. If we consider the case of the French Em¬
pire in Africa without postulating an interpretation in advance, the facts do
not suggest that the French government intervened in Tunisia to safeguard
French interests in secondary companies; quite the contrary, the French
government invoked these interests in order to justify an intervention which
statesmen saw as a means of preventing Italian colonization, guaranteeing
the security of the Algerian borders and providing evidence of French re¬
covery. Similarly, in Morocco, the banks and corporations were attracted by
the opportunities offered to them by conquests more than they forced the
parliament and ministers to launch the enterprise. South of the Sahara,
missionaries, explorers and officers were, originally, more active and more
impassioned than big business. The American historian E. Staley, in his book
War and the Private Investor, has more often remarked on the desire of states¬
men than on the intrigues of capitalists as being the source of conquests.
Such an interpretation is not dogmatic. It does not exclude the fact that
the Boer War and the British protectorate in Egypt were entirely or largely
provoked by the action of private groups. It does not exclude the fact that
after taking possession, individuals or societies have profited by French or
British sovereignty, either to obtain concessions of territory, or to reserve for
themselves a profitable trade, or to insure high profits by the exploitation of
rich natural resources and payment of low salaries. To say that the nations of
Western Europe were not obliged in order to maintain the capitalist regime
or the welfare of the people to take possession of Africa is not to say that once
the conquest was made the colonists did not dominate and exploit the van¬
quished, as all conquerors have done down through the ages.
What makes European imperialism in Africa spuriously mysterious, in the
eyes of certain historians, is that it is not modern if only those phenomena
determined by economics are modern. Even if, following Lenin, we de¬
scribed the capitalist economies as involved in spite of themselves in an end¬
less expansion toward exploitation and the division of the planet, we could
not thereby explain the fact that a France without dynamism established her
sovereignty over territories to which she sent neither surplus population nor
surplus capital nor surplus manufactured products. Imperial conquest re¬
mained, in the minds of the European statesmen, the sign of greatness.
Europe was at peace, the Western Hemisphere protected by the Monroe Doc¬
trine. One took what remained to be taken, and the unwritten law of com-
ON RESOURCES 267
pensation, which the diplomacy of cabinets obeyed, obliged the states to claim
in turn a share of a continent which all could have safely ignored.
Such imperialism nonetheless created diplomatic conflicts between the
great powers: the Reich regarded itself as a kind of victim of the French
establishment in Morocco, as though humiliated that the neighboring re¬
public, weakened as it was, should enlarge its territories while Germany re¬
mained enclosed within its frontiers. The liberal-minded economists, on their
side, stressed that the causes of the conflicts were those encouraging the
return of the mercantile spirit. It was not sovereignty, they said, that mattered
on the economic level, it was the action of the sovereign. Let the sovereign
maintain equal conditions for all rivals and the flags floating over the public
buildings will be of no consequence. But the colonial spirit was increasingly
marked by the old mercantile spirit. The state, whether colonist or protector,
reserved for its nationals the concessions of territories or mines, top adminis¬
trative posts, and commerce with the metropolitan nation for its own mer¬
chant marine. Far from concealing them, the leagues which undertook to
popularize the imperial expansion of Great Britain and France (like the
Ligue maritime et coloniale') tended to exaggerate the profits of imperialism.
Public opinion inclined to indifference or to skepticism. Propaganda was not
so much directed against the “Marxists” as against the “liberals.” Whereas
the former could be dealt with by invoking the “civilizing mission,” against
the latter, it was necessary to prove that the metropolitan nation owed a good
share of its prosperity to its colonies.
Were leaders and peoples so convinced by their own ideology that they
desired or accepted the First World War, the division of the globe, as neces¬
sary (in the double sense of the word)? There is nothing to prove that this
was the case. It was not over colonial conflicts that the nations went to war,
but over conflicts of nationalities in the Balkans. In Morocco, French and
German banks were more disposed to come to terms than the chancelleries.
The fate of the southern Slavs jeopardized the existence of Austria-Hungary,
thus affecting the whole of the European equilibrium. Were the English de¬
termined to conquer Germany in order to eliminate a commercial rival? This
legend does not stand up under scrutiny. Certain sectors of the British export
trade were affected by German exports. Both nations increased their sales
abroad, although German progress was swifter. Shall we say that British pub¬
lic opinion mistakenly believed the national prosperity was threatened?
British public opinion was as conscious of the complementarity as of the
opposition between the two economies: they were each other’s best customer
and best purveyor. The voices of the liberals who denounced the futility of
conquest carried farther than those backward champions of mercantilism who
appealed to arms to save commerce.
Actually the War of 1914, like European imperialism in Africa, was es¬
sentially a traditional phenomenon. It was, in origin, a general war of a typi¬
cal character: all the member states of the international system were involved
268
SOCIOLOGY
in the struggle because the latter jeopardized the structure of the system. The
statesmen discovered too late that industry transformed the nature of war
more than there was occasion for conflict.
4. Capitalism and Imperialism
The facts we have discussed in the preceding paragraph do not refute any
particular theory of imperialism, but they make plausible a more complex in¬
terpretation than that of the Marxists or of certain liberals. It is not in a period
when conquests are less profitable and wars more ruinous than in any other
that we should explain either of them by a purely economic mechanism. Does
the abstract analysis of the capitalist system permit us to adopt a notion which
empirical analysis seems to deny?
Let us first recall that the tendency of the capitalist—-that is, progressive
and industrial—economy to spread throughout the world is not in question.
Every school admits this much. The theory should prove that capitalist econ¬
omy cannot survive without territories that are not yet capitalist, or, that it is
condemned by its internal contradictions to divide up the world into colonial
empires and spheres of influence, and that such division cannot be pacific.
Of the first proof—that capitalist economies cannot survive without popu¬
lations still alien to the capitalist mode of production—we shall say only a
few words. It has been attempted by Rosa Luxembourg, and rejected by
Lenin and the principal Marxists: it is no more than a historical curiosity.
The proof takes as its point of departure the division of all modem econ¬
omy into two sectors, one which produces the means of production and one
which produces consumer goods. Each of these two sectors produces a value
which is subdivided, according to Marxist concepts, into constant capital,
variable capital and surplus value. Thus:
I=Ci-|-I/i-f-S, (production goods)
II=C2-j-V , 2+S2 (consumer goods)
In a process of simple reproduction, surplus value can be "realized” (in the
Marxist sense of the term) only if equality is constantly maintained between
the sum of the variable capital and the surplus value in sector I, and the
constant capital in sector II.^H
Now let us consider the process known as that of expanded reproduction.
A part of the surplus value of the two sectors is consumed by the capitalist,
another part is reinvested so that the constant capital is enlarged. This in¬
vestment of a part of the surplus value constitutes what Marx called the
accumulation of capital.
Let us take as point of departure the accumulation of capital in sector I.
& 3 !ln simple reproduction, variable capital and surplus value are entirely consumed.
Now the sum (Cb-f-Vg-pS,) represents the totality of consumer goods available. Foi
Vj and Sj to be consumed they must be equal to C 2 .
ON RESOURCES
269
The surplus value is subdivided into two parts: one which will be consumed
by the capitalist, the other which will be transformed into capital for the
next phase. Henceforth the equation C2=Vi+Si is transformed. The total
value of consumer goods, that is, the total value of sector II, should be equal
to the sum of the variable capital of sector I and sector II, the consumed
part of the surplus value of sector I, and the consumed part of the surplus
value of sector II (ItlAq-k^-l-SiC-f-SbC). Or again, the total value of
sector I should equal the sum of the constant capital of the two sectors plus
the reinvested fraction of the surplus values of the two sectors. Within the
system defined by these schemes, the process of expanded reproduction can
take place unhampered only if these equations are respected.
Are they? Rosa Luxembourg, her disciples and her critics have played
with numerical examples. They have finally concluded that these equations
can be maintained on the condition that the rate of accumulation in sector
II (consumer goods) be determined by the rate of accumulation in sector I.
This conclusion, moreover, has what we might call the quality of evidence.
The authors posited the necessary equation between the constant capital of
sector II and the sum of the variable capital and the surplus value consumed
by the capitalists of sector I. This equation will be respected only in the
cases in which the increase of one of the two terms of the equation controls
the increase of the other. The Marxists, admitting that the accumulation of
capital is the essential phenomenon and the resiliency of the capitalist system,
first of all posit the growth of sector I by reinvestment of almost all the sur¬
plus value. The value of sector II—in other words, of the consumer goods—
should not exceed the value of the consumption of the workers of both sectors
(Vi and V2), plus the share of the surplus value of each sector consumed
by the capitalists. Otherwise, the surplus value could not be “realized,” in
other words the values, under the physical form in which they present them¬
selves, would not find a corresponding demand. There might exist, for
instance, an “unsalable” (or unrealizable) surplus of value, embodied in
consumer goods, which would not find a taker within the system.
The idea of an unsalable surplus of consumer goods within the capitalist
system (linked to the Marxist notion that capitalism is subject to the law of
concentration and that wages are maintained at the lowest possible level)
would be reinforced and renewed by the consideration of the relation be¬
tween the two sectors. As a matter of fact, the accumulation does not really
consist of reinvesting an important share of the surplus value in order to pro¬
duce more goods according to the same organic composition of capital; if this
were the case, there would be no insurmountable difficulties about respecting,
in the process of expanded reproduction, the equation C 2 =Vi-f-S 1 . But the
essence of technological progress, Rosa Luxembourg and her commentators
tell us, consists in modifying the relation of C to V; thus the maintenance of
proportionate values between the constant capital of one sector and the vari¬
able capital of the other is contradictory and impossible. Or at least, according
27 °
SOCIOLOGY
to the last of these backward disciples of Rosa Luxembourg, “the conditions
of equilibrium require, ultimately, a slowing down of the rhythm of techno¬
logical progress and even of the rhythm of the increase of production in sector
II as progress increases in sector I, and this to such a degree that, if we
imagined a very intense technological progress in sector I, it might have as
its counterpart a requirement for a production halt or even a deferment in
sector II.’lSl
Is it possible to find factual evidence in order to prove this contradiction?
I do not believe so. In the course of the first phase of industrial development,
the capitalist nations have perhaps tended to export consumer goods, but
these were manufactured products such as textiles. Today, the underde¬
veloped nations of the world, in the process of industrialization, also desire
to sell textile products abroad, not because of a surplus of value in sector
II in relation to the domestic purchasing power available for consumer goods,
but because such manufactured products are simpler, their technology less
difficult than that of most factory-produced goods. At present, the so-called
capitalist nations export, in the percentage of their total exports, increasing
amounts of manufactured goods, for the simple reason that the nations in
the process of development wish to equip themselves and reserve their scarce
foreign currency for such equipment. It would be reckless to conclude from
this that the relation between the two sectors results in a permanent excess
of production goods.
Nor has the transformation of agriculture during the last 150 years tended
to confirm the contradiction between the necessary equation of C 2 and
Vjlon the one hand, or the modification of the relation between C and V
on the other. The technological progress in agriculture has been slow or fast,
depending on the nations and the periods of capitalism. It has slowed down
in the nadons where additional production stimulated or risked stimulating
the collapse of the market—in any case had to be exported. It has accelerated
for some twenty years in the United States for reasons that appear even more
technological than social. The complexity of the variables which control
technological progress in capitalist agriculture is such that it is impossible to
find in the facts the confirmation of the “contradiction” discovered by Rosa
Luxembourg.
That the speed of accumulation in sector I tends to slow down the techno¬
logical progress in sector II might be suggested by a single historical experi¬
ment: that of the Soviet Union. Production and productivity have advanced
in sector I faster than in sector II. There has not been any surplus of produc¬
tion in sector II but, since the capitalist law of accumulation functions to the
full in sector I and since the surplus value, appropriated by the state, was
EULuden Goldmann, R echerches dialectiques, Paris, 1959, p. 336.
ESThis equation is simplified: developed, it should he C 2 -j-CA 2 =V 1 -f-VA 1 (CA 2
is the supplementary constant capital of sector II, VA t the supplementary variable
capital of sector I?.
ON RESOURCES
271
massively reinvested, neither the variable capital of sector I nor the constant
capital of sector II increased rapidly. The forced rhythm of accumulation in
sector I has not been the only cause, in terms of production and productivity,
of the slowness of the progress of Soviet agriculture. The peasant resistance
to collectivization has also been responsible. The Soviet case Illustrates none¬
theless the mechanism, imagined by certain Marxists, which has functioned
only in a planned system: if one accelerates the rhythm of accumulation in
sector I, the only way of avoiding a surplus of consumer goods is to slow
down the rhythm of accumulation and of technological progress in sector II.
We are not concerned with discussing in detail the theoretical schemes of
Rosa Luxembourg, which are mainly of historical interest. But it is evident
that the increase of the capital intensity per worker—that is, the value of the
machines with which the wage-earners work—could not be expressed, with¬
out excessive simplification, by the formula of the increase of C in relation to
V. The fraction of the value of the constant capital transmitted to each piece
of merchandise depends on the duration of the machine, the degree of amorti¬
zation, the number of products manufactured with the same machine. The
detours of production become increasingly long. The share of wages in the
national income does not decrease nor does the relation of the value of capi¬
tal to the annual value of production increase. In the last analysis, all the
theories concerning the contradictions in the capitalist regime are based on
the hypothesis that the real wages remain at the lowest level.
Hence I am tempted to believe that the best (or the better of two evils)
way of transforming into an “economic theory of imperialism” the facts which
J. A. Hobson described and which Lenin utilized is that of Mr. John
Strachey, in his last bookJiH that is to say, to consider the export of capital
and political-economic imperialism as one of the two ways out available to
capitalism, while the other is the increase of the purchasing power of the
masses by the raising of real wages.
J. A. Hobson described the imperialist movement of the last quarter of the
nineteenth century and of the beginning of the twentieth as follows. Within
nations, minorities are passionately interested in conquest. Members of the
ruling class find, in remote possessions, glamorous and well-paid posts for
their sons. Industrial or commercial enterprises accumulate excess profit.
Capitalists invest their money around the world and gradually become
rentiers, parasites of a national economy which, in its turn, becomes a parasite
of w'orld economy.
Historical study has not refuted this total view of a kind of symbiosis
between many individual interests and the imperialist diplomacy of the Euro¬
pean nations. It has led to a subtler and more complex interpretation, the
initiative of loans of capital or of conquest having often been taken by
politicians and not by businessmen, for diplomatic motives and not with a
\EThe End of Empire, London, 1959.
SOCIOLOGY
272
view to profits. But it has shown how arbitrary was the “theory” which Lenin
attempted to derive from the facts collected by Hobson, a theory which is
summed up in three propositions: the export of capital was inevitable, the
seizure or creation of zones of influence necessary, and the peaceful division
of the planet impossible.
Mr. John Strachey adopts the first proposition in order to save an essential
element of the theory. He cites a passage from Lenin on imperialism:
“It goes without saying that if capitalism could develop agriculture,
which today lags far behind industry everywhere, if it could raise
the standard of living of the masses, who are everywhere still
poverty-stricken and underfed, in spite of the amazing advance in
technical knowledge, there could be no talk of a superfluity of capi¬
tal. This ‘argument’ the petit bourgeois critics of capitalism advance
on every occasion. But if capitalism did these things it would not be
capitalism; for uneven development and wretched conditions of the
masses are the fundamental and inevitable conditions and premises
of this mode of production. As long as capitalism remains what it is,
surplus capital will never he used for the purpose of raising the
standard of living of the masses, in a given country, for this would
mean a decline in profits for the capitalists; it will be used for the
purpose of increasing those profits by exporting capital abroad to
the backward countries. In these backward countries, profits usually
are high, for capital is scarce, the price of land is relatively low, raw
materials are cheap. The possibility of exporting capital is created
by the entry of numerous backward countries into international cap¬
italist intercourse; main railways have either been built or are being
built there; the elementary conditions for industrial developments
have been created, etc. The necessity of exporting capital arises from
the fact that in a few countries capitalism has become ‘over-ripe’
and (owing to the backward state of agriculture and the impover¬
ished state of the masses) capital cannot find ‘profitable invest¬
ments.’ ’SI
We know today that the capitalist regime—-private ownership of the means
of production and mechanisms of the market—can, without destroying it¬
self, raise the standard of living of the masses. We even know that this eleva¬
tion conforms to the properly interpreted interest of the propertied class. The
debate henceforth focuses on two points: 1. Does ideal capitalism—as a type
analyzed according to a pure model—tend to the accumulation of capital and
to the misery of the masses, with only government action, favored by po¬
litical democracy, reversing the action of spontaneous forces; or on the con-
\Mhmperidism, The Final Stage of Capitalism, HJhapter ivi quoted in Strachey, op.
cit., pp. 110-11.
ON RESOURCES
273
trary, is the true model that o£ a simultaneous growth of production,
productivity and the level of the masses? 2. Has the immediate and neces¬
sary cause of the exports of capital and political-military imperialism at the
end of the nineteenth century and the beginning of the twentieth been the
distribution of income, the lack of profitable domestic investments?
The determination of a model for capitalism can never avoid some measure
of the arbitrary. It is not impossible to construct a model which would in¬
volve a tendency to impoverishment. But, as a matter of fact, even omitting
the foreseeable interventions of a democratic state, an economic regime such
as that of the West at the end of the nineteenth century and the beginning of
the twentieth may have stimulated an increased concentration of wealth; it
did not bring about the aggravated poverty of the masses. We must assume
an enormous industrial reserve army if the progress of productivity (or the
reduction of the necessary labor time, in Marxist language) is not expressed
by at least a constancy of real wages and generally by a rise in the latter.
It would certainly not be less erroneous to construct a model of market
economy which would result in a balanced growth of all nations within the
same system, and of all regions or all classes within a single nation. Depend¬
ing on many circumstances, the cumulative process tends to reduce or enlarge
the gaps between the economic collectivities. During the period which we
are considering, did the inequality of income among classes impose upon
European capitalism the export of capital and imperialism? Let us grant that
it is difficult to answer categorically yes or no. It would be paradoxical to
deny that there was a link between the social structure, the distribution of
income and the surplus of capital. It would be risky to assert that these for¬
eign investments were indispensable at the same time as being tempting (by
reason of superior yield). The interrelation of political and economic moti¬
vations, as we have seen, prohibits a simple theory.
Further, even if we subscribe to the relationship of the poverty of the
masses and the export of capital, the economic interpretation of imperialism
is not thereby established.
The tremendous amount of capital invested by Europeans in the territories
over which they did not exercise sovereignty, the insignificance of the sums
invested precisely where they did exercise sovereignty, shows the relative in¬
dependence of the two movements, one of capital, the other of soldiers. Set¬
ting aside France, whose conquests in North Africa were long, slow and
costly, the European nations intervened in areas where possession did not
require great efforts. The Europeans did not guarantee their most important
investments by political sovereignty; they seized weak or anarchic nations,
either to establish profitable conditions of trade with them, or to acquire
strategic positions, or to round out and protect territories already annexed, or
finally to serve their glory.
Shall we say, as Lenin occasionally suggests, that the variety of forms—
zone of influence, protectorate, colony—in which the European domination
SOCIOLOGY
274
was exercised are of little consequence, that they are merely expressions of
the same profound fact, European domination? This answer is equivalent to
recognizing the distinction between the economic movement and the political
movement. This separation has never been so marked in the modem period
as at the end of the nineteenth century. The conquest of South America by
the Spanish, the exploitation of men and resources by the European masters
in permanent colonies are inseparable. The conquest of India starting from
the commercial activity of a British corporation constitutes another example
of this traditional transition from exploitation to the acquisition of sover¬
eignty. It is at the end of the nineteenth century that, because capitalism
had become industrial at the same time as commercial, in one place the
Europeans chose to conquer without finding wealth on the spot, and in an¬
other to invest their capital without conquering.
Thereby, the third proposition—the impossibility of division—is shown for
what it is; purely arbitrary. The impossibility of peaceful division or of
equitable compromise is a vestige of the mercantilist doctrine. Were the great
corporations, the banks, the states animated by such a spirit of monopoly that
they considered war inevitable? Neither the facts nor reasoning afford any
basis to such a proposition. The Europeans had no difficulty finding use for
their capital around the world. At the beginning of the twentieth century,
world economy was in a phase of expansion and rising prices. Monopolistic
exclusion remained a relatively rare practice. The colonizers or moneylenders
were assured of advantages in competition; they did not deprive their rivals
of all opportunities.
Shall we say, with John Strachey, that the unequal development of the
metropolitan states was the insurmountable obstacle to peaceful division?
That the capitalistic nations have had unequal rates of demographic and
economic growth is incontestable, but the phenomenon does not date
from capitalism. The instability of international relations, for centuries and
millenniums, derives precisely from the fluctuation of the relative forces of
states. This fluctuation, for the last two centuries particularly, depends on
the number of men and factories as well as on the authority of the sovereigns.
The rate of development determines directly the configuration of the diplo¬
matic system. At the beginning of the twentieth century the dimensions of
the various colonial empires were not proportional to the (economic or mili¬
tary) forces of the metropolitan states. If this was the cause of the War of
1914, as Lenin suggests, the explanation has nothing to do with Marxism-
Leninism: Germany would have been warlike out of resentment against her
rivals who enjoyed a richer place in the sun. For this interpretation by un¬
equal development to constitute an economic theory of the fatal struggle for
the division of the world, the state disfavored in the distribution of colonies
would be obliged by economic necessity to attack its unjustly privileged
rivals. If monopoly—the exclusion of rivals by force—is indispensable to
capitalist economies, the nation whose development has been the swiftest,
ON RESOURCES
275
Germany, should have been paralyzed by the weakness of its own monopolies
or by the exclusion which the monopolies of the others inflicted upon it. Yet
in 1913 we find nothing of the kind: Germany’s development continued to
be swifter than that of the other European nations; foreign trade, export of
capital also progressed. Theoretical analysis as well as empirical study lead to
a traditional conclusion: perhaps the peaceful division would have been im¬
possible, but it is not modem capitalism, it is the age-old avarice which led
to war. If statesmen and peoples had acted according to economic rationality,
the War of 1914 would not have taken place. Neither monopolies nor dia¬
lectic had made inevitable what was irrational.
Modem industrial economy is the first which questions the economic utility
of conquest. Slavery was rational, in the economic sense of the term, once the
yield of servile labor left a surplus for the master, in other words, when the
slave produced more than what he needed to survive. Conquest was rational
only when the spoils were higher than the cost of the battle or of dominion.
Empire was rational as long as commerce was in essence monopolistic, fol¬
lowed the flag or had as its objective the possession of precious metals, the
stock of which was limited. This rationality, for an economy considered as a
whole, is no longer evident once wealth depends on free labor, once exchange
favors both parties to it, once producers and merchants both gain advantage
in accepting competition.
Liberals and socialists are more or less aware of this original feature of
the modem economy. But, observing the facts of imperialism, they emphasize
other, no less real aspects, of that economy which render imperialism intel¬
ligible. An economy of exchanges, to the degree that it is at the same time
industrial, is charged with a kind of dynamism. It tends to spread throughout
the entire world and to include all of humanity. Marx had said it in the
Communist Manifesto and he had seen clearly.
We shall not here discuss whether, by some mysterious malformation, a
regime of private property is incapable of absorbing its own production. In
any case, certain sectors of industry will occasionally be threatened with over¬
production. Growth occurs, without a general plan, by a series of creative
imbalances. How can we deny that dominion over foreign territories facili¬
tates the sale of manufactured products which do not find buyers in the
mother country?
Further, the European or world-wide economy did not conform to Ben-
tham’s ideal model. Trusts, cartels, maintenance of high domestic prices,
dumping abroad—these practices of the commercial war, contrary to the es¬
sence of a free economy, had not disappeared. To these residues of the spirit
of monopoly, liberal sociologists and economists imputed the imperialist en¬
terprises of the capitalist and bourgeois nations, while the socialists tried to
prove that this spirit of monopoly and conquest was inseparable from capi¬
talism itself.
Both were wrong. Insofar as it was of economic origin and signification,
SOCIOLOGY
276
the imperialism of the end of the nineteenth century was not the last stage
of capitalism hut the last stage of mercantile imperialism, itself the last stage
of millennial imperialism. Hobson and Schumpete :{3 emphasized in fact the
privileged minorities that tended toward imperialism, contrary to the spirit
of industry and commerce. But they forgot that men and, still more, states
have always desired dominion for its own sake.
It is not enough that empire be economically sterile for the people or for
those who speak in their names to renounce the glory of dominion.
5. Capitalism and Socialism
Every modem economy gives states an unprecedented capacity to act
abroad, since it enlarges the gap between the minimum indispensable to the
life of the population and the available goods. The greater this gap, the
higher the maximum degree of state mobilization of collective resources. War
is evidently not the only possible use abroad of the resources mobilized: aid
is another, but war has been the most frequent. That the capacity for pro¬
duction creates a surplus which men can consume by killing each other is
true for any economy of our period, whatever the regime. Stripped of the
passions and confusions perpetuated by a century of propaganda and ideo¬
logical disputes, the question of the influence on the possibility of peace and
the risk of war exerted by the choice between a capitalist regime (private
ownership and market mechanisms) and a socialist regime (public owner¬
ship and planning) leads in the abstract to simple terms: What stakes, occa¬
sions, causes of conflicts, inseparable from capitalism, would the socialist
regime suppress? What stakes, occasions, or causes would it create? By
definition, competition for the investment of capital, the intervention of
states in order to protect the interests of their nationals, threatened by ex¬
propriation laws, would be eliminated. Similarly, there would be no further
private interests to exert pressures on the leaders with a view to obtaining
higher tariff rates (which competitors regard as illegitimate or aggressive) or
other privileges contrary to the rules of honest competition. Nonetheless, all
occasions for conflicts between states in a socialist economy would not thereby
disappear.
The conditions of international exchanges, in a world market regime with
D HjT. A. Hobson, Imperialism, London, 1902, and Joseph Schumpeter, op. cit.
Schumpeter’s error seems to me to he explained by the confusion between the
modern case and the ancient cases. Schumpeter, as we know, explained the imperialism
of the Arabs, to take one example, by the persistence, in new conditions, of a traditional
way of life. The Arab horsemen continued to conquer because in the desert war was
the constant, normal activity adapted to circumstances. But modem societies are differ¬
entiated and are not defined by labor as the life of the Arab tribes was defined by
horseback raids. The capitalists or the bourgeois do not devote themselves to business
as the Arab horsemen devoted themselves to war. According to economic calculations,
the bourgeois should be peaceful and anti-imperialist. But they do not apply economic
calculations to their entire existence.
ON RESOURCES
277
relatively free prices, appear often inequitable to one or the other of the
parties to the exchange, as a result of the inequality of economic and po¬
litical weight. The small country which owes almost all its foreign currency
to the sale of one raw material is often subject to the dictates of the buyer
and above all of the chief buyer. In spite of everything, the mechanisms of
the market, even international, even imperfect, limit the influence of military
force on commercial transactions. The day when these transactions become
negotiations between governments, everything depends on men and on re¬
gimes. The increasing state control of international commerce enormously
increases the possibilities of the exploitation of the weak by the strong. The
Russian practices in Stalin’s time, the price at which the Poles had to sell
their coal, illustrate one of the intrinsic risks of this kind of socialism as long
as multiple sovereignties subsist.
A regime of private property, as long as it is authentically liberal and as
long as states, even hostile ones, respect it, has the advantage of reducing the
profits of a military victory. The benefits afforded by rearrangements of bor¬
ders are limited, once individuals preserve their possessions and their pro¬
fessions. When the Saar was included within the French economic union,
the goods the French obtained from it were paid for by those they sent to it.
The goods which they no longer sell in the German Saar, they perhaps sell
elsewhere just as profitably.
Socialism does not favor the same separation of property and sovereignty.
Domestic enterprises and persons are subject to the plan and the will of the
state, but foreign buyers and sellers act according to their interest or their
preferences. The tracing of borders therefore has a vital importance. Plan¬
ners do not like to depend on decisions beyond their control and imperfectly
predictable. Annexation eliminates unforeseeability, it offers the possibility
of putting nationals in positions of command, of transferring to the conquer¬
ing state the ownership of property taken from citizens of the conquered
state. In theory a planned economy reinforces the motives for desiring the
enlargement of the space of sovereignty.
Veblen considered that the modem system of production was, in itself,
peaceful, that on the other hand the entrepreneurs, industrialists, merchants
and corporations animated by the desire for profit were creators of conflicts
and responsible for wars. He forgot that the system of production, of itself,
determines neither what goods will be produced nor how the collective re¬
sources will be distributed among the various uses, nor incomes among
classes. These chiefly economic determinations can result either from the
mechanisms of the market (more or less controlled or oriented by the state),
or from a plan more or less thwarted by the weight of the material aspects of
society.
If we adopt the first solution, the stimulus to expansion or to protection
comes from ambitious or threatened “private interests.” Some of these, in
case of failure on the commercial terrain, mobilize public opinion or the state
SOCIOLOGY
278
against their competitors. Even if the players accept all the rules of the game,
the defeat which involves loss of jobs for workers or of income for capitalists
provokes bitterness and resentment, which eventually influence those respon¬
sible for diplomatic behavior. Such a regime is all the less dangerous to inter¬
state relations in that the leaders are more likely to act according to long-term
considerations and not to confuse with a permanent impoverishment the
transitory sacrifices which the commercial struggle inevitably imposes from
time to time.
If the second solution is adopted, the chief variable consists of the -political
regime and men. Rates of growth, the share of investments in the national
product are by definition the object of decisions taken by the planners, that
is, by the leaders of the state. It is to be feared that states, if they consider
themselves engaged in a rivalry for power, will extend the traditional com¬
petition of military force to the economic sphere. But if all humanity had
converted to a socialist regime, we might conceive a planned economy with
an eye to welfare and the slowing down of the race for growth.
No regime, then, whether capitalist or sodalist, makes war inevitable; none
suppresses all occasions for it. It is even difficult to specify, in the abstract,
which of these two regimes is more favorable or more contrary to pacification.
What is not doubtful is that the conflict of regimes, within an international
system, multiplies the causes and amplifies the stakes of conflicts. The Soviet
Union has no need to conquer new territories in order to improve the con¬
ditions of the life of its people. The Soviet citizens would accommodate
themselves easily to the survival of capitalism in other parts of the world:
the so-called Marxist-Leninist regime based on the absolute power of a single
party and on a state doctrine is nonetheless dedicated to expansion by a
necessity which is not economic but political and ideological. It is a necessity
in part imputable to circumstances: revolutionaries and rebels the world over
experience the attraction of the Soviet technique and model. But this neces¬
sity also derives from the way of life and style of thought of the Bolshevik
leaders: the political struggle is, in essence, continuous, permanent, and since
international relations are conceived in imitation of the struggle between
parties, they are also regarded as belligerent until the universal diffusion of
redeeming truth.
Every great ideocratic power, whatever its economic regime, is imperialistic
if the effort to spread an idea and to impose a mode of government abroad,
even by force, is specifically considered. In any case, such an effort appears
imperialistic to those states that wish to safeguard their own institutions, even
when the ideocratic power normally prefers subversion to invasion and re¬
frains from annexing the peoples which it converts to its faith. Crusaders
have never been regarded as messengers of peace. It is in our age that they
have drawn a dove on their blazon.
chapter X
Nations and Regimes
In the preceding chapters we have analyzed the determinants which di¬
rectly influence the strength of political units that constitute the elements of
the situation, as it is analyzed by the actors. Space, resources and number
are possible stakes of the conflict, objectives of those who direct the political
units. They may also be the unrecognized causes of collective behavior. The
relations of space, number and resources define, in each period, the optimum
of well-being or of power; they may govern, in certain circumstances, the
warlike impulse of peoples; they provide more or less sincere justifications for
the conquerors.
In the next three chapters we shall no longer consider the determinants
of the situation, but the actors’ styles of being and behaving, that is, the
styles of the subjects of diplomatic history which we have called political
units. Thus, we shall encounter a second type of explanation of wars. In¬
stead of invoking the inexorable determinism of need, the eternal hunger for
gold or wealth, we shall be discussing the arraignment of “eternal Germany,”
of “the despotic, Communist or democratic regime ,’0 the hypothesis of a
fatal development of civilizations or the theory of human nature, the origin
and outcome of history. In this chapter we shall proceed from political
regimes (Section i) to national constants (Section 2) to return, by the
intermediary of the nation considered as a historical type of political unit
(Section 3), and of the diversity of military organizations (Section 4), to the
present situation, characterized by the extreme heterogeneity of both states and
modes of combat.
1. On Political Regimes
I shall take, for my point of departure, the questions which the commenta-
01 n the chapter on Resources, we have already observed a problem of this type apropos
of the Marxist-Leninist theory of imperialism.
280
SOCIOLOGY
tors on foreign policy have continually raised since 1945: Is the foreign policy
of the Soviet Union Russian or Communist? Is it or is it not influenced by
the ideology which the revolutionary state claims as its inspiration? In
abstract terms the question is as follows: In a given period, is the behavior of
the actors a function (and to what degree) of the political regime?
The political regimes of a given period, which preside over the organization
of a certain type of society, inevitably present common characteristics. But
they differ at least by the mode of designation of those who wield the sover¬
eign authority, by the manner in which these latter make their decisions,
hence by the relations which are established between individuals, public
opinion and social groups on the one hand, and those who govern on the
other. The same men do not reach power in all regimes, they do not act
under the same conditions or under the same pressures. To postulate that the
same men in different circumstances or different men in the same circum¬
stances make equivalent decisions leads to a strange philosophy, implies one
or the other of the two following theories: either diplomacy is rigorously
determined by impersonal causes, the individual actors occupying the center
of the stage but playing roles learned by heart, or else the conduct of the
political units is controlled by a “national interest” capable of a rational
definition, vicissitudes of internal struggles and changes of regimes not modi¬
fying (nor should they modify) this definition. Each of these philosophies,
it seems to me, can be refuted by the facts.
Did Stalin have the same vision of the historical world as Nicholas II?
Would the latter’s successor have had the same vision as the militant Bolshe¬
vik who emerged victorious from the struggle among the diadochi? Did Hitler
have the same vision of the future of Germany as Stresemann or Briining?
Would the leader of a democratic party ot a Hohenzollem have hurled
Germany against the Western democracies and the Soviet Union in the style
adopted by the Fiihrer of the Third Reich?
Rhetorical questions, the reader will object. It is obvious that the answer
is negative: Hitler’s strategy and tactics were quite different from those of
Stresemann or of a possible descendant of the King of Prussia. By strategy
I mean both the long-term objectives and the representation of the historical
universe which makes their choice intelligible; by tactics I mean the day-to-day
reactions, the combination of means with a view to previously fixed ends.
To claim that the strategy and tactics of a (national or imperial) political
unit remain constant whatever the regime is quite simply absurd. In this
sense the proposition: the diplomacy of the Soviet Union is Communist and
not Russian, cannot be contested. The burden of proof lies, in any case,
upon those who seek to deny it.
Beyond this evidence stands the real problem. To what degree do foreign
policies change with regimes? Let us note immediately: this is not a question
of theory but of fact. The answer may vary according to periods and cir¬
cumstances. In our era, changes in regimes have involved diplomatic up-
NATIONS AND REGIMES 28 1
heavals. The external action of states has not been less influenced by ideolo¬
gies than the organization of societies.
Let us take the two examples of the Third Reich and the Soviet Union.
Hitler’s undertaking was inspired by a philosophy in which were mingled
theories of various origins: the racist theory of Gobineau or of Houston
Chamberlain, the geopolitical theories of Mackinder and of Haushofer, con¬
tempt for the Slavs considered as Untermenschen, hatred of the Jews—an
accursed race to be eliminated like harmful vermin, the need for population
space in the direction of Eastern Europe, the detestation of Christianity—
that Semitic religion of the weak, etc. ... In 1930 none of the politicians
of the Weimar Republic would have admitted the possibility of such an
enterprise as that which Hitler, quite lucidly, inaugurated in 1933: rearma¬
ment, annexation of Austria, liquidation of Czechoslovakia, defeat of France,
aggression against the Soviet Union, etcIH Certain of these objectives were
common to Hitler and to the German conservatives (enlargement of space),
others were common to the majority of German public opinion (equality of
rights, rearmament, Anschluss). Neither those who were nostalgic for im¬
perial Germany nor the parties of the Weimar Republic nourished such vast
ambitions, inspired by such a conception of the world.
The tactics were perhaps more specifically Hitlerian than the strategy.
They differed profoundly from traditional or democratic tactics because they
applied, on the international scene, the methods tested in the course of
domestic and internal struggles. The grand strategy, to adopt the expres¬
sion fashionable some twenty years ago, involved the constant use of propa¬
ganda, that completed and renovated the classic methods of diplomacy. “De¬
fiance” was, during that first period, the instrument of success. In peacetime,
instead of yielding to the will of the stronger, according to the polite practices
of the chancelleries, Hitler acted as though he were the master, defying his
adversaries to use force, to constrain him.
The very act in which superficial observers see the proof that Stalinist or
Hitlerian diplomacy was not ideological, the Russo-German Pact of 1939, is,
correctly interpreted, the proof if not of the contrary, at least of the influence
which regimes exert, in our period, upon the course of events. As a matter
of fact, a regime analogous to that of the Weimar Republic, or else a regime
derived from Tsarism as it existed in 1900, could not have reversed its
propaganda from one day to the next. The Weimar Republic, it is true, had
signed the Treaty of Rapallo, and the Reichswehr had undertaken arms tests
with the cooperation of the Red army. The kings and emperors had once
given the example of the partition of Poland. But, in the twentieth century,
the diplomacy of every non-revolutionary regime has lost the capacity for such
[§r am not asserting that in 1933 Hitler knew the successive stages of his undertak¬
ing. But he knew the point at which he wished to emerge: victory over the Soviet
Union, enlargement of the Germans’ space.
282
SOCIOLOGY
cynicism as that evidenced by Stalin and Hitler in 1939. Obliged to persuade
public opinion, to present the allies as good and the enemies as wicked, the
diplomacy of the European states, whether conservative or parliamentarian,
is modest in its remote objectives, with a limited margin of maneuver at any
given moment. Only the regime whose leaders have a short-range but vir¬
tually complete liberty with regard to public opinion can, from one moment
to the next, bum what they once adored, adore what they once burned,
without the people being profoundly disturbed, some believing in no propa¬
ganda, others believing in the truth of each moment, still others ready to
trust the necessary cunning of their masters.
Following this line of reasoning, we might formulate the following prop¬
osition: diplomatic tactics are more flexible as regimes are more authoritar¬
ian, that is, the leaders less subject to the pressures of groups or of public
opinion; further, the objectives of diplomacies vary with regimes and are more
rigorously determined as the regime is more ideological. These two proposi¬
tions are likely enough but not particularly instructive, and they require sev¬
eral corrections. To say that tactical flexibility is proportional to the leaders’
freedom of action is more of a platitude than a law. Moreover, if the leaders
sincerely believe in progress, a specific advance in the state’s future history,
they cannot fail to relate their plans to this prophetic vision. This does not
mean that individual decisions are never affected by ideology or that strategy
remains rigid in all cases.
Let us take the example of the Soviet conduct of diplomacy. On the whole
it is effectively flexible in its tactics and constant in its objectives and its
representation of the world. The commentators incline to deny the action of
ideology and have an easy time showing that most Soviet decisions can be
interpreted in so-called rational terms, that is, in terms of the calculation of
forces. The pact with the Third Reich shifted the war toward the West,
which was in accord with the national interest of Russia, regardless of regime.
Moscow’s domination of the Eastern European nations created a protective
glacis at the same time that it corresponded to a traditional ambition of
pan-Slavism. The conflict with the United States conforms to all the prece¬
dents, being implied, so to speak, by the geometry of the relations of forces:
the two great powers of a bipolar system are enemies by position. This mode
of comprehension is not false, but it is partial and may lead to erroneous
conclusions.
The contrast between the rigidity of strategy and the flexibility of tactics
does not derive exclusively from the ideological character of the former and
the non-ideological character of the latter. The ideology of the Soviet state
is such that it tolerates, if it does not impel, tactical flexibility. The Marxist-
Leninist vision of history is essentially a succession of regimes, socialism
following capitalism, socialism being defined as the government of the Com¬
munist party identified with the proletariat. But the degree of the develop¬
ment of productive forces does not fix the order in which the different nations
NATIONS AND REGIMES
283
achieve socialism. This process may be internal or external, caused by crisis
or war, coup d’etat or intervention of the Red army. Finally, once the
first so-called socialist state has been constituted, wars may either set the
capitalist states against each other because they are doomed to imperialism, or
may set the socialist camp against the capitalist camp because the former’s
victory is ultimately inevitable.
Whatever the course of events, an explanation or rather a theoretical
formulation is possible. Do the United States and Great Britain have a
dispute? Nothing is more logical, since the two economies are rivals. Do the
Anglo-American powers conclude an alliance? Of course, the contradiction
is expressed in an intimate cooperation. Does the Soviet Union sign an ex-
pediential pact with the Third Reich? The spokesmen celebrate the meet¬
ing of two revolutions. Does the same Soviet Union find itself, by the force
of circumstances, associated with the Western democracies? Bolshevism
again becomes the brother of social democracy within the great family of
the Left. Turn and turn about, wars between imperialist nations, then wars
between socialist and capitalist nations will be more likely.
Even the final goal is equivocal. Hitler’s strategic goal—a German Empire
within an enlarged space—was concretely defined. The strategic goal of the
Soviet Union is not defined to the same degree. Is it the universal diffusion
of a regime which the leaders in Moscow would agree to call socialist (a
single party identified with the proletariat, etc.)? Is it a world empire of the
Soviet Union or of the (Bolshevik) Communist party of the U.S.S.R.? The
two formulas are equivalent only provided the unity of the socialist camp
is maintained outside the struggle with capitalism. Finally, war itself is no
longer the inevitable stage before the universal victory of socialism.
Must we agree with those who deny the influence of ideology and impute
to institutions alone (to the modes of decisions) the difference in policy
according to regime? Even in the case of the Soviet Union this conclusion
would be erroneous. The Bolshevik vision of the world did not permit the
Soviet leaders during the Second World War to believe in the duration or
the authenticity of the alliance with the Western democracies. The awareness
of hostility at the very moment of cooperation was dictated by doctrine. The
Russo-American rivalry was established within the geometry of the relation of
forces: the emotional hostility has been amplified if not created by ideological
opposition. But further: doctrinal considerations have, on two occasions, mod¬
ified the calculation of forces and the determination of national interest.
One policy, called realist, attempts to reduce the resources of its enemies,
whether actual or potential; to increase that of its allies and to win to its
cause those states that are not committed. Stalin treated Yugoslavia as an
enemy the day the latter refused to obey Moscow’s directives; can we conceive
of the Russo-Yugoslav dispute if the two states did not claim one and the
same ideology? Why did Mr. Khrushchev for so many years refuse to show
any fear of China, and why did he favor Chinese industrialization when the
SOCIOLOGY
284
West unceasingly pointed out the danger of the "countless and impover¬
ished® yellow masses? According to Marxist philosophy, one socialist state
does not endanger another. This philosophy, it is true, has not offered much
resistance to experience, and from now on the two metropolitan nations of
communism will be rivals, each proclaiming a different interpretation of the
same gospel. The conflict, of course, results from opposing national interests,
incompatible aspirations to the leadership of the bloc, but it has also been
influenced by the faithful adherence of the two states to the same ideology.
The Soviet Union and the People’s Republic of China would neither have
become allies nor have quarreled as they have, without their common ad¬
herence to Marxism-Leninism. How could the calculation of national interest
help but change with regimes, since each of these, as a result of its own
doctrine, gauges affinities and hostilities differently?
As a matter of fact, the Soviet Union seems to me to Lave behaved with
Hitler, with its war allies, with its satellites, with the United States, and
today with the United States and China in the manner which only a way of
thinking linked to an ideological structure renders intelligible,!!
Is it possible to formulate some general propositions as to the scope of the
changes in diplomacy caused by the substitution of one regime for another?
At first glance one is inclined to suppose that a revolution has great diplomatic
consequences, insofar as they interest the actors who play the principal roles.
In fact, all conduct of foreign policy involves, of necessity, a share of adapta¬
tion to circumstances. The share of adaptation is greater, the share of initiative
smaller, when the actor plays a smaller role, in other words, has fewer forces
at his disposal.
However, this proposition requires modifications. A second-class state, by
definition, does not determine major events, the style of diplomatic rivalry.
It was Hitler’s success, not Mussolini’s, which changed the course of European
history. But, within a heterogeneous system, the vicissitudes of partisan con¬
flicts within states may cause a shift from one camp to another, or from com¬
mitment to neutrality. The "national interest” of small states, far from being
alien to ideological considerations, is, in a heterogeneous system, inseparable
from such considerations. In i960 no one could define France’s national
interest without taking into account the choice between regimes imposed by
circumstances.
For the theory of the insignificance of regimes to assume some likelihood,
we must imagine a diplomatic system in a space that has been demarked for
centuries, a relatively homogeneous system, all the actors following more
or less the same unwritten rules of diplomacy' and strategy. The geographical
constancy of the diplomatic field indicates the lines of expansion of the var-
HThe expression, it will be remembered, was coined by General de Gaulle.
LilEven in matters of tactics it is not impossible to observe particularities and constants
which characterize the Moscow leaders. Cf. N. Leites, The Operational Code of the
Politburo, New York, 1951.
NATIONS AND REGIMES
285
ious states. At the end of the nineteenth century, when the world’s great
powers were identified with the European states and the latter, whether
republican or Tsarist, formed their alliances according to the moderate
Machiavellianism of cabinets, the indifference of chancelleries to ideas and
to regimes was considered an ideal, approximately realized with the advances
of civilization. It requires a strange blindness in order to transform the
model of the diplomacy of one epoch into an eternal model.
2. The National Constants
Beyond these observations, on which it would be virtually unnecessary to
insist if some authors did not persist in denying them, an authentic question
remains, namely, that of national constants. Does the “national interest” of a
collectivity remain fundamentally the same throughout history?
We have, in an earlier chapter, shown why the “national interest” cannot
be the object of a rational determination. If the economist unhesitatingly
takes as his objective a certain maximum (of goods, of the national product
or profit), it is because economy is a science of means. The economist does
not tell men or collectivities what to do with their goods (and the latter are
defined in relation to demand). If the sociologist were capable of defining the
national interest, he would be in a position to dictate to statesmen, in the
name of science, their conduct. Such is not the case. The “maximization”
of forces is not obviously imperative, since it implies putting at the state’s
disposal the largest possible fraction of the collectivity’s resources. Why should
men be